]> pere.pagekite.me Git - text-free-culture-lessig.git/blob - freeculture.xml
Generated.
[text-free-culture-lessig.git] / freeculture.xml
1 <?xml version='1.0' encoding='UTF-8' ?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href="docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type="text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012-2015 with input from Martin Borg. -->
5 <!--
6 TODO
7 * Add missing indexterm entries by comparing with the 2004 edition.
8 -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC "-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
11 [
12 <!ENTITY copy "©">
13 ]>
14
15 <book id="index" lang="en">
16 <bookinfo>
17 <title>Free Culture</title>
18
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
20
21 <subtitle>How big media uses technology and the law to lock down
22 culture and control creativity</subtitle>
23
24 <pubdate>2015-09-04</pubdate>
25
26 <edition>1</edition>
27
28 <releaseinfo>Version 2004-02-10</releaseinfo>
29
30 <authorgroup>
31 <author>
32 <firstname>Lawrence</firstname>
33 <surname>Lessig</surname>
34 </author>
35 <!--
36 Keep these out to avoid showing up as author in the PDF.
37
38 <editor>
39 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
40 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
41 </editor>
42
43 <othercredit role='converter'>
44 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
45 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
46 <contrib>Created this Docbook version from an earlier version</contrib>
47 </othercredit>
48 -->
49 </authorgroup>
50
51 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
52 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
53 -->
54 <subjectset scheme="libraryofcongress">
55 <subject>
56 <subjectterm>Intellectual property&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
57 </subject>
58 <subject>
59 <subjectterm>Mass media&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
60 </subject>
61 <subject>
62 <subjectterm>Technological innovations&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
63 </subject>
64 <subject>
65 <subjectterm>Art&mdash;United States.</subjectterm>
66 </subject>
67 </subjectset>
68
69
70 <publisher>
71 <publishername>Petter Reinholdtsen</publishername>
72 <address><city>Oslo</city></address>
73 </publisher>
74
75 <copyright>
76 <year>2004</year>
77 <holder>Lawrence Lessig</holder>
78 </copyright>
79 <legalnotice>
80 <para>
81 <inlinemediaobject>
82 <imageobject>
83 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.png" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
84 </imageobject>
85 <imageobject>
86 <imagedata fileref="images/cc.svg" contentdepth="3em" width="100%" align="center"/>
87 </imageobject>
88 <textobject>
89 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved</phrase>
90 </textobject>
91 </inlinemediaobject>
92 </para>
93
94 <para>
95 This book is licensed under a Creative Commons license. This license
96 permits non-commercial use of this work, so long as attribution is
97 given. For more information about the license visit
98 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/"/>.
99 </para>
100 </legalnotice>
101
102 <abstract>
103 <title>About the author</title>
104 <para>
105 Lawrence Lessig
106 (<ulink url="http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org</ulink>),
107 professor of law and a Roy L. Furman Professor of Law and Leadership
108 at Harvard Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
109 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
110 (<ulink url="http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org</ulink>).
111 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) and Code: And
112 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), Lessig is a member of
113 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
114 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
115 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
116 twice listed in BusinessWeek's <quote>e.biz 25,</quote> and named one
117 of Scientific American's <quote>50 visionaries.</quote> A graduate of
118 the University of Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law
119 School, Lessig clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh
120 Circuit Court of Appeals.
121 </para>
122 </abstract>
123
124 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
125 <mediaobject role="cover">
126 <imageobject remap="lrg" role="front-large">
127 <imagedata fileref="images/cover.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
128 </imageobject>
129 <!--
130 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
131 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
132 </imageobject>
133 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
134 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
135 </imageobject>
136 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
137 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
138 </imageobject>
139 -->
140 </mediaobject>
141
142 <biblioid class="isbn">978-82-8067-010-6</biblioid>
143
144 <!-- LCCN from
145 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
146 -->
147 <biblioid class="libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
148
149 <biblioid class="uri">http://free-culture.cc/</biblioid>
150
151 </bookinfo>
152 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
153 <dedication id="alsobylessig">
154 <title>
155 Also by Lawrence Lessig
156 </title>
157
158 <itemizedlist>
159
160 <listitem><para>
161 The USA is lesterland: The nature of congressional corruption (2014)
162 </para></listitem>
163 <listitem><para>
164 Republic, lost: How money corrupts Congress - and a plan to stop it (2011)
165 </para></listitem>
166 <listitem><para>
167 Remix: Making art and commerce thrive in the hybrid economy (2008)
168 </para></listitem>
169 <listitem><para>
170 Code: Version 2.0 (2006)
171 </para></listitem>
172 <listitem><para>
173 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World (2001)
174 </para></listitem>
175 <listitem><para>
176 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace (1999)
177 </para></listitem>
178 </itemizedlist>
179 </dedication>
180 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
182 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
183 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
184 <dedication><title></title>
185 <!-- FIXME figure out how to do this better in dblatex and docbook-xsl -->
186 <?latex {\Huge \centering
187 ?>
188 <para>
189 To Eric Eldred &mdash; whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
190 it continues still.
191 </para>
192 <?latex } % \Huge \centering
193 ?>
194 </dedication>
195
196 <toc id="toc"></toc>
197
198 <lot>
199 <title>List of figures</title>
200 </lot>
201
202 <!--
203 c PREFACE xiii
204 c INTRODUCTION
205 c "PIRACY"
206 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
207 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
208 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
209 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
210 2 Film
211 2 Recorded Music
212 2 Radio
213 2 Cable TV
214 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
215 2 Piracy I
216 2 Piracy II
217 c "PROPERTY"
218 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
219 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
220 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
221 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
222 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
223 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
224 2 Beginnings
225 2 Law: Duration
226 2 Law: Scope
227 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
228 2 Architecture and Law: Force
229 2 Market: Concentration
230 2 Together
231 c PUZZLES
232 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
233 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
234 2 Constraining Creators
235 2 Constraining Innovators
236 2 Corrupting Citizens
237 c BALANCES
238 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
239 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
240 c CONCLUSION
241 c AFTERWORD
242 1 Us, Now
243 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
244 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
245 1 Them, Soon
246 2 1. More Formalities
247 3 Registration and Renewal
248 3 Marking
249 2 2. Shorter Terms
250 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
251 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
252 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
253 c NOTES
254 c ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
255 c INDEX
256 -->
257
258 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
259
260 <preface id="preface">
261 <title>Preface</title>
262 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'><primary>Pogue, David</primary></indexterm>
263 <para>
264 <emphasis role="bold">At the end</emphasis> of his review of my first
265 book, <citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle>, David
266 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
267 computer-related texts, wrote this:
268 </para>
269 <blockquote>
270 <para>
271 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
272 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
273 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
274 system, you can always flip off the modem.<footnote id="preface01"><para>
275 David Pogue, <quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 30 January 2000.
276 </para></footnote>
277 </para>
278 </blockquote>
279 <para>
280 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book&mdash;that
281 software, or <quote>code,</quote> functioned as a kind of law&mdash;and his review
282 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
283 could always <quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome</quote>-like simply flip a
284 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
285 any troubles that exist in <emphasis>that</emphasis> space wouldn't
286 <quote>affect</quote> us anymore.
287 </para>
288 <para>
289 Pogue might have been right in 1999&mdash;I'm skeptical, but maybe.
290 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
291 <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
292 causes even after the modem is turned
293 <!--PAGE BREAK 12-->
294 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
295 on-line have fundamentally affected <quote>people who aren't online.</quote> There
296 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
297 </para>
298 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'/>
299 <para>
300 But unlike <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
301 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
302 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
303 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
304 important.
305 </para>
306 <para>
307 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
308 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of <quote>free culture</quote>&mdash;not
309 <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free beer</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
310 free software movement<footnote>
311 <para>
312 Richard M. Stallman, <citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed. 2002).
313 </para></footnote>), but <quote>free</quote> as in <quote>free speech,</quote> <quote>free markets,</quote>
314 <quote>free trade,</quote> <quote>free enterprise,</quote> <quote>free will,</quote> and <quote>free elections.</quote> A
315 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
316 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
317 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
318 follow-on creators and innovators remain <emphasis>as free as
319 possible</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
320 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
321 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
322 <quote>permission culture</quote>&mdash;a culture in which creators get to create
323 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
324 past.
325 </para>
326 <para>
327 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not <quote>we</quote>
328 on the Left or <quote>you</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
329 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
330 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
331 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
332 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
333 culture deem fundamental.
334 </para>
335 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
336 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
337 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
338 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted</primary></indexterm>
339 <para>
340 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
341 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
342 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
343 generated more than 700,000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
344 As William Safire described marching <quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
345 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
346 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,</quote> he formulated perhaps
347 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
348 he asked,
349 </para>
350 <blockquote>
351 <para>
352 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
353 power&mdash;political, corporate, media, cultural&mdash;should be anathema to
354 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
355 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
356 the greatest expression of democracy.<footnote><para> William Safire,
357 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 May 2003.
358 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
359 </para></footnote>
360 </para>
361 </blockquote>
362 <para>
363 This idea is an element of the argument of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, though my
364 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
365 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
366 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
367 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
368 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
369 you&mdash;whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
370 Safire's left or on his right.
371 </para>
372 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'/>
373 <para>
374 <emphasis role="strong">The inspiration</emphasis> for the title and for
375 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
376 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
377 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in <citetitle>Free Software, Free
378 Society</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
379 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
380 that this work is <quote>merely</quote> derivative.
381 </para>
382 <para>
383 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
384 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
385 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
386 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
387 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
388 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
389 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
390 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
391
392 <!--PAGE BREAK 14-->
393 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
394 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
395 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
396 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
397 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
398 what I advance here.
399 </para>
400 <para>
401 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
402 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
403 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
404 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
405 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
406 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
407 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
408 book is written.
409 </para>
410
411 </preface>
412 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
413
414 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
415 <chapter label="" id="c-introduction">
416 <title>Introduction</title>
417 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
418 <para>
419 <emphasis role="strong">On December 17</emphasis>, 1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
420 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
421 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
422 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
423 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
424 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
425 </para>
426 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.</primary></indexterm>
427 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
428 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
429 <para>
430 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
431 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
432 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
433 and all the space above, to <quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.</quote><footnote><para>
434 St. George Tucker, <citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
435 Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18.
436 </para></footnote>
437 For many
438 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
439 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
440 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
441 </para>
442 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
443 <para>
444 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
445 law&mdash;deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
446 by the most important legal thinkers of our past&mdash;mattered. If
447 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
448 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
449 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
450 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
451 </para>
452 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
453 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
454 <para>
455 In 1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
456 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
457 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
458 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
459 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
460 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
461 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to <quote>an indefinite
462 extent, upwards,</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
463 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
464 </para>
465 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
466 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
467 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'><primary>Douglas, William O.</primary></indexterm>
468 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights</secondary></indexterm>
469 <para>
470 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
471 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
472 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
473 <quote>taking</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
474 that <quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
475 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.</quote> But Justice Douglas
476 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
477 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
478 </para>
479 <blockquote>
480 <para>
481 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
482 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
483 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
484 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
485 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
486 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
487 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
488 the public has a just claim.<footnote>
489 <para>
490 United States v. Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. The Court did find
491 that there could be a <quote>taking</quote> if the government's use of its land
492 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
493 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece, <quote>(Intellectual)
494 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
495 Authorship,</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review</citetitle> 48 (1996): 1293, 1333. See also Paul
496 Goldstein, <citetitle>Real Property</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press, 1984),
497 1112&ndash;13.
498 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
499 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
500 </para></footnote>
501 </para>
502 </blockquote>
503 <para>
504 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.</quote>
505 </para>
506 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'/>
507 <para>
508 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
509 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
510 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
511 <!--PAGE BREAK 18-->
512 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line: <quote>Common sense revolts
513 at the idea.</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
514 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
515 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
516 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
517 </para>
518 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
519 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
520 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
521 <para>
522 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
523 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
524 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
525 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
526 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
527 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
528 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
529 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
530 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by <quote>what
531 seemed reasonable</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
532 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
533 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
534 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
535 end, the force of what seems <quote>obvious</quote> to everyone else&mdash;the power of
536 <quote>common sense</quote>&mdash;would prevail. Their <quote>private interest</quote> would not be
537 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
538 </para>
539 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'/>
540 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'/>
541 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'/>
542 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'/>
543 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
544 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham</primary></indexterm>
545 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
546 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael</primary></indexterm>
547 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
548 <para>
549 <emphasis role='strong'>Edwin Howard Armstrong</emphasis> is one of
550 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
551 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
552 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
553 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
554 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
555 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in 1831. But
556 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
557 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
558 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
559 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
560 </para>
561 <para>
562 On the day after Christmas, 1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
563 for his most significant invention&mdash;FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
564 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
565 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
566 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
567 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
568 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
569 much less transmitter power and static.
570 </para>
571 <para>
572 On November 5, 1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
573 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
574 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
575 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
576 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
577 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
578 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
579 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
580 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.</quote>
581 </para>
582 <para>
583 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
584 </para>
585 <blockquote>
586 <para>
587 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
588 sounded like a glass of water being poured. &hellip; A paper was crumpled
589 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
590 fire. &hellip; Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
591 and guitar number were performed. &hellip; The music was projected with a
592 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio <quote>music
593 box.</quote><footnote><para>
594 Lawrence Lessing, <citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong</citetitle>
595 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209.
596 </para></footnote>
597 </para>
598 </blockquote>
599 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
600 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
601 <para>
602 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
603 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
604 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
605 AM radio market. By 1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
606 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
607 a handful of networks.
608 <!--PAGE BREAK 20-->
609 </para>
610 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
611 <para>
612 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
613 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
614 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
615 that removed static from <quote>radio.</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
616 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
617 </para>
618 <blockquote>
619 <para>
620 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
621 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
622 revolution&mdash; start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
623 RCA.<footnote><para> See <quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
624 Electronic Era,</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
625 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
626
627 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #1</ulink>.
628 </para></footnote>
629 </para>
630 </blockquote>
631 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
632 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David</primary></indexterm>
633 <para>
634 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
635 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
636 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
637 described,
638 </para>
639 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessing, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
640 <blockquote>
641 <para>
642 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
643 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
644 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
645 unrestrained, posed &hellip; a complete reordering of radio power
646 &hellip; and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
647 on which RCA had grown to power.<footnote><para>Lessing, 226.
648 </para></footnote>
649 </para>
650 </blockquote>
651 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'><primary>FCC</primary><secondary>on FM radio</secondary></indexterm>
652 <para>
653 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
654 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
655 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
656 FM radio's deployment generally. In 1936, RCA hired the former head
657 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
658 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM&mdash;principally by moving FM
659 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
660 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
661 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
662 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
663 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
664 </para>
665 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
666 <blockquote>
667 <para>
668 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
669 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
670 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
671 deviousness.<footnote><para>
672 Lessing, 256.
673 </para></footnote>
674 </para>
675 </blockquote>
676 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'/>
677 <indexterm><primary>AT&amp;T</primary></indexterm>
678 <para>
679 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
680 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
681 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
682 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
683 (This change was strongly supported by AT&amp;T, because the loss of
684 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
685 wired links from AT&amp;T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
686 least temporarily.
687 </para>
688 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'/>
689 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
690 <para>
691 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
692 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
693 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
694 invalid&mdash;baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
695 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
696 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
697 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
698 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
699 now broke, in 1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
700 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
701 </para>
702 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'/>
703 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'/>
704 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
705 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
706 <para>
707 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
708 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
709 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
710 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
711 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
712 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
713 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
714 course always public spirited; the reality is something
715 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
716 to themselves, would crumble in
717 <!--PAGE BREAK 22-->
718 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
719 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
720 effect of technological change.
721 </para>
722 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'/>
723 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'/>
724 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
725 <para>
726 <emphasis role="strong">There's no</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
727 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
728 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
729 Internet and American Life Project, 58 percent of Americans had access
730 to the Internet in 2002, up from 49 percent two years
731 before.<footnote><para>
732 Amanda Lenhart, <quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
733 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,</quote> Pew Internet and American
734 Life Project, 15 April 2003: 6, available at
735 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #2</ulink>.
736 </para></footnote>
737 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
738 of 2004.
739 </para>
740 <para>
741 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
742 changed things. Some of these changes are technical&mdash;the Internet has
743 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
744 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
745 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
746 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
747 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
748 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
749 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
750 </para>
751 <para>
752 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
753 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
754 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
755 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
756 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
757 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
758 has introduced.
759 </para>
760 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
761 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel</primary></indexterm>
762 <indexterm><primary>culture</primary><seealso>free culture</seealso></indexterm>
763 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'><primary>culture</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial</secondary></indexterm>
764 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah</primary></indexterm>
765 <para>
766 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
767 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
768 regulation of each. By <quote>commercial culture</quote> I mean that part of our
769 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
770 <quote>noncommercial culture</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
771 parks or on
772 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
773 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
774 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his <quote>Reader,</quote> or
775 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
776 </para>
777 <para>
778 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
779 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
780 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
781 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
782 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
783 left this culture <quote>free.</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
784 individuals shared and transformed their culture&mdash;telling
785 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
786 clubs, sharing music, making tapes&mdash;were left alone by the law.
787 </para>
788 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
789 <para>
790 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
791 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
792 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
793 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
794 marketplace.<footnote>
795 <para>
796 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
797 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
798 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
799 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
800 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
801 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
802 D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote> Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193,
803 198&ndash;200.
804 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
805 </para></footnote>
806 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
807 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
808 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
809 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
810 </para>
811 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
812 <indexterm><primary>permission culture</primary><secondary> free culture vs.</secondary></indexterm>
813 <para>
814 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
815 been erased.<footnote><para>
816 See Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
817 2001), ch. 13.
818 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
819 </para></footnote>
820 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
821 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
822 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
823 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
824 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
825 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
826 the balance of our history&mdash;between uses of our culture that were
827 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission&mdash;has
828 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
829 culture, more and more a permission culture.
830 </para>
831 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
832 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
833 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
834 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests</primary></indexterm>
835 <para>
836 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
837 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
838 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
839 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
840 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
841 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
842 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
843 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
844 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
845 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
846 Causbys.
847 </para>
848 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'/>
849 <para>
850 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
851 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
852 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
853 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
854 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
855 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
856 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
857 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
858 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
859 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
860 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
861 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
862 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
863 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
864 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
865 than creators do today&mdash;all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
866 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
867 </para>
868 <para>
869 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
870 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
871 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
872 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
873 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
874 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
875 remakes them.
876 </para>
877 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'/>
878 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary> on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
879 <para>
880 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
881 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
882 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
883 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions&mdash;whether <quote>piracy</quote> will
884 be permitted, and whether <quote>property</quote> will be protected. The <quote>war</quote> that
885 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet&mdash;what
886 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
887 calls his <quote>own terrorist war</quote><footnote><para>
888 Amy Harmon, <quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
889 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,</quote> <citetitle>New York
890 Times</citetitle>, 17 January 2002.
891 </para></footnote>&mdash;has been framed as a battle about the
892 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
893 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
894 against it.
895 </para>
896 <para>
897 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
898 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
899 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
900 <quote>creative property.</quote> I believe that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that the
901 law, properly tuned, should punish <quote>piracy,</quote> whether on or off the
902 Internet.
903 </para>
904 <para>
905 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
906 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
907 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet <quote>pirates</quote> will also rid our
908 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
909 </para>
910 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
911 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
912 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
913 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
914 <para>
915 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first 180 years of
916 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
917 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
918 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
919 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,<footnote>
920 <para>
921 Neil W. Netanel, <quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
922 Journal</citetitle> 106 (1996): 283.
923 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
924 </para></footnote>
925 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
926 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
927 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
928 could cultivate and extend our culture.
929 </para>
930 <para>
931 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
932 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
933 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
934 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist&ndash;like,
935 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
936 granted&mdash;but it is not often granted to the critical or the
937 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
938 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
939 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
940 </para>
941 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. -->
942 <para>
943 The story that follows is about this war. It is not about the
944 <quote>centrality of technology</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
945 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
946 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
947 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
948 against an industry.
949 </para>
950 <para>
951 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
952 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
953 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
954 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
955 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
956 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
957 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
958 </para>
959 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
960 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
961 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary></indexterm>
962 <para>
963 <emphasis role="strong">Like the Causbys'</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about <quote>property.</quote> The
964 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
965 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
966 this <quote>property</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
967 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
968 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
969 of <quote>intellectual property</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
970 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
971 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
972 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
973 <quote>trespassing</quote> upon legitimate claims of <quote>property.</quote> It is as plain to
974 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
975 trespass.
976 </para>
977 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
978 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
979 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers</primary></indexterm>
980 <para>
981 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
982 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
983 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
984 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
985 war. Unlike
986 <!--PAGE BREAK 27-->
987 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
988 on its side.
989 </para>
990 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of</primary></indexterm>
991 <para>
992 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
993 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
994 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
995 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
996 our <quote>culture</quote> was as <quote>owned</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
997 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
998 <emphasis>uses</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
999 accepted as it is now.
1000 </para>
1001 <para>
1002 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
1003 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1004 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1005 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1006 </para>
1007 <para>
1008 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1009 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1010 </para>
1011 <para>
1012 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1013 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1014 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1015 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1016 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1017 </para>
1018 <para>
1019 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1020 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1021 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1022 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1023 view?
1024 </para>
1025 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
1026 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
1027 <para>
1028 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1029 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1030 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1031 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of <quote>intellectual
1032 property.</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1033 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1034 this silliness will be much more profound.
1035 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1036 </para>
1037 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'/>
1038 <para>
1039 <emphasis role="strong">The struggle</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas: <quote>piracy</quote> and
1040 <quote>property.</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1041 ideas.
1042 </para>
1043 <para>
1044 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1045 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1046 obscure French theorists&mdash;however natural that is for the weird
1047 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1048 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1049 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1050 </para>
1051 <para>
1052 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1053 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1054 government, pushed by big media to respond to this <quote>something new,</quote> is
1055 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1056 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let <quote>common
1057 sense</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1058 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1059 law&mdash;and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1060 fundamental about who we have always been.
1061 </para>
1062 <para>
1063 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1064 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1065 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1066 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1067 of one more consequence of this form of corruption&mdash;a consequence
1068 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1069 </para>
1070 </chapter>
1071 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1072 <part id="c-piracy">
1073 <title><quote>Piracy</quote></title>
1074 <partintro>
1075 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1076 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
1077 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
1078 <indexterm><primary>music publishing</primary></indexterm>
1079 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
1080 <para>
1081 <emphasis role="strong">Since the inception</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1082 been a war against <quote>piracy.</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1083 <quote>piracy,</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1084 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1085 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1086 </para>
1087 <blockquote>
1088 <para>
1089 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1090 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1091 of them for his own use.<footnote><para>
1092 <!-- f1 -->
1093 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield).
1094 </para></footnote>
1095 </para>
1096 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'/>
1097 </blockquote>
1098 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on</secondary></indexterm>
1099 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>efficiency of</secondary></indexterm>
1100 <para>
1101 Today we are in the middle of another <quote>war</quote> against <quote>piracy.</quote> The
1102 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1103 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1104 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1105 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1106 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1107 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1108 </para>
1109 <para>
1110 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1111 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1112 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1113 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1114 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will <quote>rob the author of the
1115 profit.</quote>
1116 </para>
1117 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'/>
1118 <para>
1119 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1120 increasingly to technology to defend their <quote>property</quote> against this
1121 <quote>piracy.</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1122 raised to believe that <quote>property</quote> should be <quote>free.</quote> Forget tattoos,
1123 never mind body piercing&mdash;our kids are becoming
1124 <emphasis>thieves</emphasis>!
1125 </para>
1126 <para>
1127 There's no doubt that <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1128 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1129 notion of <quote>piracy</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1130 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1131 </para>
1132 <para>
1133 The idea goes something like this:
1134 </para>
1135 <blockquote>
1136 <para>
1137 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1138 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1139 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1140 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1141 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1142 piracy.
1143 </para>
1144 </blockquote>
1145 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP</primary></indexterm>
1146 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle</primary></indexterm>
1147 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts</primary></indexterm>
1148 <indexterm><primary>creative property</primary><seealso>intellectual property rights</seealso></indexterm>
1149 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory of</secondary></indexterm>
1150 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
1151 <para>
1152 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1153 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1154 theory of creative property<footnote><para>
1155 <!-- f2 -->
1156 See Rochelle Dreyfuss, <quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1157 in the Pepsi Generation,</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review</citetitle> 65 (1990): 397.
1158 </para></footnote>
1159 &mdash;if there is value, then someone must have a
1160 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1161 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1162 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.<footnote><para>
1163 <!-- f3 -->
1164 Lisa Bannon, <quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1165 Up,</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 21 August 1996, available at
1166 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #3</ulink>; Jonathan
1167 Zittrain, <quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1168 Speech, No One Wins,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 24 November 2002.
1169 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
1170 </para></footnote>
1171 There was <quote>value</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1172 <quote>right</quote>&mdash;even against the Girl Scouts.
1173 </para>
1174 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'/>
1175 <para>
1176 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1177 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1178 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1179 of law protecting creative property. But the <quote>if value, then right</quote>
1180 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1181 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1182 </para>
1183 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'/>
1184 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
1185 <indexterm><primary>creativity</primary><seealso>innovation</seealso></indexterm>
1186 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
1187 <para>
1188 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1189 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1190 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1191 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1192 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1193 </para>
1194 <para>
1195 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1196 takes care to draw&mdash;the distinction between republishing someone's
1197 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1198 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1199 copyright law today regulates both.
1200 </para>
1201 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'/>
1202 <para>
1203 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1204 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1205 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1206 entities could bear the burden of the law&mdash;even the burden of the
1207 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1208 more expense of doing business.
1209 </para>
1210 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by</secondary></indexterm>
1211 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1212 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1213 <para>
1214 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1215 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1216 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1217 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1218 <quote>copying,</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1219 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1220 outweighs any original benefit&mdash;certainly as it affects
1221 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1222 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1223 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1224 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1225 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1226 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1227 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1228 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1229 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1230 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the <quote>Rise of the Creative
1231 Class.</quote><footnote>
1232 <para>
1233 <!-- f4 -->
1234 In <citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class</citetitle> (New York:
1235 Basic Books, 2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1236 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1237 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1238 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1239 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1240 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1241
1242 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard</primary></indexterm>
1243 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)</primary></indexterm>
1244 </para></footnote>
1245 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1246 this creative class.
1247 </para>
1248 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'/>
1249 <para>
1250 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1251 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1252 context the current battles about behavior labeled <quote>piracy.</quote>
1253 </para>
1254 </partintro>
1255
1256 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1257 <chapter label="1" id="creators">
1258 <title>Chapter One: Creators</title>
1259 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'><primary>animated cartoons</primary></indexterm>
1260 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'><primary>cartoon films</primary></indexterm>
1261 <indexterm id='idxfilmsanimated' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>animated</secondary></indexterm>
1262 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatwillie' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Willie</primary></indexterm>
1263 <indexterm id='idxmickeymouse' class='startofrange'><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
1264 <para>
1265 <emphasis role="strong">In 1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1266 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called <citetitle>Plane Crazy</citetitle>.
1267 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1268 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound, <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle> brought
1269 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1270 </para>
1271 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1272 <para>
1273 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1274 movie <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1275 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1276 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1277 Disney ran a test in the summer of 1928, the results were unambiguous.
1278 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1279 </para>
1280 <blockquote>
1281 <para>
1282 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1283 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1284 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1285 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1286 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1287 </para>
1288 <para>
1289 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1290 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1291 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1292 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1293 synchronization was pretty close.
1294 </para>
1295 <para>
1296 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1297 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1298 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1299 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1300 it was something new!<footnote><para>
1301 <!-- f1 -->
1302 Leonard Maltin, <citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1303 Cartoons</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34&ndash;35.
1304 </para></footnote>
1305 </para>
1306 </blockquote>
1307 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub</primary></indexterm>
1308 <para>
1309 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1310 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly: <quote>I have never been so thrilled
1311 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.</quote>
1312 </para>
1313 <para>
1314 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1315 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1316 rarely&mdash;except in Disney's hands&mdash;been anything more than
1317 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1318 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1319 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1320 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1321 </para>
1322 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt' class='endofrange'/>
1323 <indexterm id='idxkeatonbuster' class='startofrange'><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1324 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='startofrange'><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1325 <para>
1326 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that 1928 also marks
1327 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1328 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1329 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>.
1330 </para>
1331 <para>
1332 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in 1895. In the era of silent
1333 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1334 uncontrollable laughter from his audience. <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1335 Jr</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1336 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton&mdash;wildly popular
1337 and among the best of its genre.
1338 </para>
1339 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1340 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1341 <para>
1342 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1343 Willie.
1344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1345 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1346 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,<footnote><para>
1347 <!-- f2 -->
1348 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1349 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #4</ulink>.
1350 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1351 use the music for five songs in <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>: <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote> <quote>The
1352 Simpleton</quote> (Delille), <quote>Mischief Makers</quote> (Carbonara), <quote>Joyful Hurry No. 1</quote>
1353 (Baron), and <quote>Gawky Rube</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song, <quote>The Turkey in the
1354 Straw,</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1355 Harry Surden, 10 July 2003, on file with author.
1356 </para></footnote>
1357 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1358 the invention of synchronized sound in <citetitle>The Jazz Singer</citetitle> that we
1359 get <citetitle>Steamboat Willie</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1360 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song <quote>Steamboat Bill,</quote>
1361 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1362 Mouse.
1363 </para>
1364 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatwillie' class='endofrange'/>
1365 <indexterm startref='idxmickeymouse' class='endofrange'/>
1366 <indexterm startref='idxkeatonbuster' class='endofrange'/>
1367 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='endofrange'/>
1368 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1369 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
1370 <para>
1371 This <quote>borrowing</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1372 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1373 films of his day.<footnote><para>
1374 <!-- f3 -->
1375 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman, <quote>The Mouse
1376 that Ate the Public Domain,</quote> Findlaw, 5 March 2002, at
1377 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #5</ulink>.
1378 </para></footnote>
1379 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1380 knockoffs&mdash;slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1381 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1382 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1383 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1384 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1385 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1386 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1387 old.
1388 </para>
1389 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1390 <para>
1391 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1392 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1393 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1394 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1395 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1396 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1397 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1398 </para>
1399 <para>
1400 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1401 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1402 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1403 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1404 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1405 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1406 work of others is astonishing when set together: <citetitle>Snow White</citetitle>
1407 (1937), <citetitle>Fantasia</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Pinocchio</citetitle> (1940), <citetitle>Dumbo</citetitle>
1408 (1941), <citetitle>Bambi</citetitle> (1942), <citetitle>Song of the South</citetitle> (1946),
1409 <citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle> (1950), <citetitle>Alice in Wonderland</citetitle> (1951), <citetitle>Robin
1410 Hood</citetitle> (1952), <citetitle>Peter Pan</citetitle> (1953), <citetitle>Lady and the Tramp</citetitle>
1411 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1412 (1955), <citetitle>Mulan</citetitle> (1998), <citetitle>Sleeping Beauty</citetitle> (1959), <citetitle>101
1413 Dalmatians</citetitle> (1961), <citetitle>The Sword in the Stone</citetitle> (1963), and
1414 <citetitle>The Jungle Book</citetitle> (1967)&mdash;not to mention a recent example
1415 that we should perhaps quickly forget, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>
1416 (2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1417 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1418 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1419 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1420 </para>
1421 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales' class='endofrange'/>
1422 <para>
1423 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1424 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1425 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1426 its importance. We could call this <quote>Disney creativity,</quote> though that
1427 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely, <quote>Walt Disney
1428 creativity</quote>&mdash;a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1429 culture around us and makes it something different.
1430 </para>
1431 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='endofrange'/>
1432 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='endofrange'/>
1433 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='endofrange'/>
1434 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><seealso>copyright law</seealso></indexterm>
1435 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
1436 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>defined</secondary></indexterm>
1437 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>traditional term for conversion to</secondary></indexterm>
1438 <para> In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1439 relatively fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was
1440 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1441 thirty years&mdash;for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1442 copyrighted.<footnote><para>
1443 <!-- f4 -->
1444 Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1445 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the <quote>average</quote> term by
1446 determining
1447 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1448 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in year
1449 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the
1450 average
1451 term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1452 Web site associated with this book, available at
1453 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #6</ulink>.
1454 </para></footnote>
1455 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1456 copyright holders of a creative work had an <quote>exclusive right</quote> to control
1457 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1458 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1459 </para>
1460 <para>
1461 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1462 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1463 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a <quote>lawyer-free
1464 zone.</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1465 for Disney to use and build upon in 1928. It was free for
1466 anyone&mdash; whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1467 approved or not&mdash;to use and build upon.
1468 </para>
1469 <indexterm startref='idxanimatedcartoons' class='endofrange'/>
1470 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsanimated' class='endofrange'/>
1471 <para>
1472 This is the ways things always were&mdash;until quite recently. For most
1473 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1474 until 1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1475 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1476
1477 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1478 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1479 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s
1480 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1481 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1482 content from before the Great Depression.
1483 </para>
1484 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'/>
1485 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc' class='endofrange'/>
1486 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='endofrange'/>
1487 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='endofrange'/>
1488 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='endofrange'/>
1489 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1490 <para>
1491 <emphasis role="strong">Of course</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on <quote>Walt Disney creativity.</quote>
1492 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1493 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1494 universal.
1495 </para>
1496 <indexterm id='idxcomicsjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1497 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1498 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1499 <indexterm id='idxmanga' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1500 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
1501 <para>
1502 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1503 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: <citetitle>manga</citetitle>, or
1504 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of
1505 publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives
1506 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1507 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1508 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1509 </para>
1510 <para>
1511 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1512 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1513 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1514 the stories that these <quote>graphic novels</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1515 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are <quote>men in tights.</quote>
1516 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1517 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1518 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1519 interestingly different way.
1520 </para>
1521 <para>
1522 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1523 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1524 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1525 </para>
1526 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='startofrange'><primary>creativity</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works</secondary></indexterm>
1527 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1528 <para>
1529 This is the phenomenon of <citetitle>doujinshi</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1530 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1531 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is <emphasis>just</emphasis> a
1532 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1533 transforming it either subtly or
1534 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1535 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1536 develop it differently&mdash;with a different story line. Or the comic can
1537 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1538 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently <quote>different.</quote> But they
1539 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1540 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1541 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1542 </para>
1543 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1544 <para>
1545 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1546 huge. More than 33,000 <quote>circles</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1547 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come
1548 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1549 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1550 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1551 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1552 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1553 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1554 </para>
1555 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1556 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1557 <para>
1558 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1559 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1560 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1561 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1562 one. Doujinshi are plainly <quote>derivative works.</quote> There is no general
1563 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1564 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1565 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with <citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1566 Jr</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that <quote>taking</quote> without
1567 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1568 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1569 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1570 </para>
1571 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt2' class='endofrange'/>
1572 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'><primary>Winick, Judd</primary></indexterm>
1573 <para>
1574 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1575 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1576 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, <quote>The
1577 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1578 in Japan now. &hellip; American comics were born out of copying each
1579 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1580 other. &hellip; That's how [the artists] learn to draw &mdash; by going into comic
1581 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them</quote>
1582 and building from them.<footnote><para>
1583 <!-- f5 -->
1584 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud, <citetitle>Reinventing Comics</citetitle> (New
1585 York: Perennial, 2000).
1586 </para></footnote>
1587 </para>
1588 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1589 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics</primary></indexterm>
1590 <para>
1591 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1592 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1593 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, <quote>there are these rules
1594 and you have to stick to them.</quote> There are things Superman <quote>cannot</quote>
1595 do. <quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1596 which are fifty years old.</quote>
1597 </para>
1598 <indexterm startref='idxwinickjudd' class='endofrange'/>
1599 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1600 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1601 <indexterm id='idxmehrasalil' class='startofrange'><primary>Mehra, Salil</primary></indexterm>
1602 <para>
1603 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1604 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1605 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1606 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1607 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1608 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1609 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.<footnote><para>
1610 <!-- f6 -->
1611 See Salil K. Mehra, <quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1612 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1613 Review</citetitle> 55 (2002): 155, 182. <quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1614 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1615 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1616 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1617 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1618 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.</quote>
1619 </para></footnote>
1620 </para>
1621 <indexterm startref='idxcomicsjapanese' class='endofrange'/>
1622 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics' class='endofrange'/>
1623 <indexterm startref='idxmanga' class='endofrange'/>
1624 <para>
1625 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1626 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1627 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1628 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1629 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1630 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1631 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1632 a more general pattern of blocking this <quote>free taking</quote> by the doujinshi
1633 culture?
1634 </para>
1635 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='endofrange'/>
1636 <indexterm startref='idxmehrasalil' class='endofrange'/>
1637 <para>
1638 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1639 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1640 a friend from a major Japanese law firm. <quote>We don't have enough
1641 lawyers,</quote> he told me one afternoon. There <quote>just aren't enough resources
1642 to prosecute cases like this.</quote>
1643 </para>
1644 <para>
1645 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1646 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1647 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1648 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1649 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1650 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1651 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1652 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1653 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1654 their clients or hurt them?
1655 </para>
1656 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics' class='endofrange'/>
1657 <para>
1658 <emphasis role='strong'>Let's pause</emphasis> for a moment.
1659 </para>
1660 <para>
1661 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1662 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1663 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1664 </para>
1665 <para>
1666 We live in a world that celebrates <quote>property.</quote> I am one of those
1667 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1668 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1669 <quote>intellectual property.</quote><footnote><para>
1670 <!-- f7 -->
1671 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
1672 The term <citetitle>intellectual property</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1673 Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 11 (New York: New York
1674 University Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
1675 (New York: Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately
1676 describes a set of <quote>property</quote> rights &mdash; copyright, patents,
1677 trademark, and trade-secret &mdash; but the nature of those rights is
1678 very different.
1679 </para></footnote>
1680 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1681 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1682 property.
1683 </para>
1684 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt3' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1685 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='startofrange'><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
1686 <indexterm><primary>Keaton, Buster</primary></indexterm>
1687 <para>
1688 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1689 plenty of value out there that <quote>property</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1690 mean <quote>money can't buy you love,</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1691 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1692 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1693 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1694 condemning that taking as wrong&mdash; even though trivial, even if
1695 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1696 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1697 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1698 Disney's use would have been considered <quote>fair.</quote> There was nothing
1699 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1700 the public domain.
1701 </para>
1702 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>derivative works based on</secondary></indexterm>
1703 <para>
1704 Thus, even though the things that Disney took&mdash;or more generally,
1705 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity&mdash;are
1706 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1707
1708 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1709 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1710 freedom is good.
1711 </para>
1712 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='endofrange'/>
1713 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>Japanese</secondary></indexterm>
1714 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese</primary></indexterm>
1715 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>doujinshi comics</primary></indexterm>
1716 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics2' class='startofrange'><primary>Japanese comics</primary></indexterm>
1717 <indexterm id='idxmanga2' class='startofrange'><primary>manga</primary></indexterm>
1718 <para>
1719 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1720 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1721 work&mdash;or even one copy&mdash;without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1722 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1723 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1724 form, whether large or small.
1725 </para>
1726 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='endofrange'/>
1727 <para>
1728 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1729 say that the copycat comic artists are <quote>stealing.</quote> This form of Walt
1730 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1731 particular find it hard to say why.
1732 </para>
1733 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1734 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='endofrange'/>
1735 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='endofrange'/>
1736 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1737 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics2' class='endofrange'/>
1738 <indexterm startref='idxmanga2' class='endofrange'/>
1739 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
1740 <para>
1741 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1742 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1743 without asking or paying for the privilege. (<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1744 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1745 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?</quote>) Acting companies
1746 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1747 permission from anyone. (Does <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> believe
1748 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1749 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1750 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1751 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s;
1752 two volcano disaster films in 1997.
1753 </para>
1754 <para>
1755 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1756 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1757 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1758 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1759 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1760 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1761 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking&mdash;free
1762 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1763 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1764 </para>
1765 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt3' class='endofrange'/>
1766 <para>
1767 The hard question is therefore not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> a
1768 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1769 question instead is <quote><emphasis>How</emphasis> free is this culture?</quote>
1770 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1771 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1772 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1773 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1774 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1775 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1776 a studio or not?
1777 </para>
1778 <para>
1779 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1780 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1781 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1782 </para>
1783 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='endofrange'/>
1784
1785 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1786 </chapter>
1787 <chapter label="2" id="mere-copyists">
1788 <title>Chapter Two: <quote>Mere Copyists</quote></title>
1789 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis</primary></indexterm>
1790 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1791 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'><primary>photography</primary></indexterm>
1792 <para>
1793 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1794 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1795 <quote>photographs.</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1796 <quote>daguerreotypes.</quote> The process was complicated and
1797 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1798 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1799 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1800 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1801 </para>
1802 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William</primary></indexterm>
1803 <para>
1804 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1805 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1806 <quote>automatic pictures.</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1807 making <quote>negatives.</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1808 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1809 the 1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1810 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1811 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1812 amateurs.
1813 </para>
1814 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Eastman, George</primary></indexterm>
1815 <para>
1816 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1817 didn't happen until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1818 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1819 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1820 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1821 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1822 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1823 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1824 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1825 population of photographers.
1826 </para>
1827 <indexterm id='idxkodakcameras' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1828 <indexterm id='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='startofrange'><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)</primary></indexterm>
1829 <para>
1830 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1831 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1832 marketed on the basis of its simplicity. <quote>You press the button and we
1833 do the rest.</quote><footnote><para>
1834 <!-- f1 -->
1835 Reese V. Jenkins, <citetitle>Images and Enterprise</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975), 112.
1836 </para></footnote> As he described in <citetitle>The Kodak Primer</citetitle>:
1837 </para>
1838 <blockquote>
1839 <para>
1840 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1841 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1842 that only an expert can do. &hellip; We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1843 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1844 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1845 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1846 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1847 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1848 chemicals.<footnote>
1849 <para>
1850 <!-- f2 -->
1851 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1852 Brian Coe, <citetitle>The Birth of Photography</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1853 1977), 53.
1854 </para></footnote>
1855 </para>
1856 </blockquote>
1857 <indexterm startref='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='endofrange'/>
1858 <para>
1859 For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1860 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1861 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1862 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1863 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1864 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in 1888; one
1865 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1866 From 1888 through 1909, while industrial production was rising by 4.7
1867 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by 11
1868 percent.<footnote><para>
1869 <!-- f3 -->
1870 Jenkins, 177.
1871 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1872 an average annual increase of over 17 percent.<footnote><para>
1873 <!-- f4 -->
1874 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p. 178.
1875 </para></footnote>
1876 </para>
1877 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian</primary></indexterm>
1878 <para>
1879
1880 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1881 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1882 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1883 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1884 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1885 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes, <quote>For the
1886 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1887 permanent record of his family and its activities. &hellip; For the first
1888 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1889 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1890 interpretation or bias.</quote><footnote><para>
1891 <!-- f5 -->
1892 Coe, 58.
1893 </para></footnote>
1894 </para>
1895 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
1896 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
1897 <para>
1898 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1899 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1900 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1901 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1902 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1903 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its <quote>quality</quote>;
1904 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1905 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1906 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1907 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1908 have before.
1909 </para>
1910 <indexterm startref='idxkodakcameras' class='endofrange'/>
1911 <indexterm id='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>permissions</primary><secondary>photography exempted from</secondary></indexterm>
1912 <para>
1913 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1914 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1915 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1916 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1917 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1918 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1919 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1920 he wanted. Their answer was no.<footnote><para>
1921 <!-- f6 -->
1922 For illustrative cases, see, for example, <citetitle>Pavesich</citetitle>
1923 v. <citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co</citetitle>., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905);
1924 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Chinn</citetitle>, 123090 S.W. 364, 366
1925 (Ky. 1909); <citetitle>Corliss</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Walker</citetitle>, 64 F. 280 (Mass.
1926 Dist. Ct. 1894).
1927 </para></footnote>
1928 </para>
1929 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology' class='endofrange'/>
1930 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt4' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
1931 <indexterm id='idximagesownershipof' class='startofrange'><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
1932 <para>
1933 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1934 familiar. The photographer was <quote>taking</quote> something from the person or
1935 building whose photograph he shot&mdash;pirating something of
1936 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1937 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1938 draw
1939 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1940 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1941 that they thought valuable.
1942 </para>
1943 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1944 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
1945 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology2' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
1946 <para>
1947 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1948 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1949 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1950 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1951 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.<footnote>
1952 <para>
1953 <!-- f7 -->
1954 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, <quote>The Right to Privacy,</quote>
1955 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review</citetitle> 4 (1890): 193.
1956 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.</primary></indexterm>
1957 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.</primary></indexterm>
1958 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1959 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1960 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1961 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1962 </para>
1963 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt4' class='endofrange'/>
1964 <para>
1965 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1966 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1967 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1968 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1969 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1970 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1971 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1972 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1973 clearing the rights to do the capturing.<footnote><para>
1974 <!-- f8 -->
1975 See Melville B. Nimmer, <quote>The Right of Publicity,</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1976 Problems</citetitle> 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, <quote>Privacy,</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1977 Review</citetitle> 48 (1960) 398&ndash;407; <citetitle>White</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1978 Inc</citetitle>., 971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951
1979 (1993).
1980 </para></footnote>)
1981 </para>
1982 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
1983 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
1984 <para>
1985 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1986 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1987 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1988 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1989 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1990 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1991 Kodak would be benefiting from the <quote>theft</quote> committed by the
1992 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1993 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1994 from the <quote>image-right</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1995 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1996 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1997 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1998 </para>
1999 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology2' class='endofrange'/>
2000 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology3' class='startofrange'><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
2001 <indexterm><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
2002 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
2003 <para>
2004
2005 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
2006 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
2007 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
2008 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
2009 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
2010 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
2011 technology as they did&mdash;since professionals could have more
2012 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
2013 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
2014 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
2015 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
2016 realized.
2017 </para>
2018 <indexterm startref='idxphotography' class='endofrange'/>
2019 <indexterm startref='idxeastmangeorge' class='endofrange'/>
2020 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
2021 <indexterm startref='idximagesownershipof' class='endofrange'/>
2022 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
2023 <indexterm id='idxjustthink' class='startofrange'><primary>Just Think!</primary></indexterm>
2024 <para>
2025 <emphasis role='strong'>If you drive</emphasis> through San
2026 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
2027 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
2028 <quote>Just Think!</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
2029 there's little that's <quote>just</quote> cerebral in the projects
2030 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
2031 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
2032 the film of your VCR. Rather the <quote>film</quote> of digital
2033 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
2034 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
2035 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2036 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2037 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2038 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2039 </para>
2040 <indexterm id='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>education</primary><secondary>in media literacy</secondary></indexterm>
2041 <indexterm id='idxmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'><primary>media literacy</primary></indexterm>
2042 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>media literacy and</secondary></indexterm>
2043 <para>
2044 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2045 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2046 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it, <quote>Five years ago, a good
2047 real-time digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get
2048 professional quality for $595.</quote><footnote><para>
2049 <!-- f9 -->
2050 H. Edward Goldberg, <quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2051 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,</quote>
2052 cadalyst, February 2002, available at
2053 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #7</ulink>.
2054 </para></footnote>
2055 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2056 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2057 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2058 learning more and more of something teachers call <quote>media literacy.</quote>
2059 </para>
2060 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2061 <para>
2062 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2063 <quote>Media literacy,</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2064 Think!, puts it, <quote>is the ability &hellip; to understand, analyze, and
2065 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2066 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2067 the way people access it.</quote>
2068 </para>
2069 <indexterm startref='idxjustthink' class='endofrange'/>
2070 <para>
2071 This may seem like an odd way to think about <quote>literacy.</quote> For most
2072 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2073 and noticing split infinitives are the things that <quote>literate</quote> people know
2074 about.
2075 </para>
2076 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2077 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
2078 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
2079 <para>
2080 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of
2081 television commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000
2082 commercials generally,<footnote><para>
2083 <!-- f10 -->
2084 Judith Van Evra, <citetitle>Television and Child Development</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2085 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1990); <quote>Findings on Family and TV
2086 Study,</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post</citetitle>, 25 May 1997, B6.
2087 </para></footnote>
2088 it is increasingly important to understand the <quote>grammar</quote> of media. For
2089 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2090 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2091 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2092 (at least at first) terrible media.
2093 </para>
2094 <para>
2095 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2096 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2097 has written understands how difficult writing is&mdash;how difficult
2098 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2099 language to be understandable&mdash;few of us have any real sense of
2100 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2101 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2102 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2103 </para>
2104 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology3' class='endofrange'/>
2105 <para>
2106 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2107 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2108 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2109 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2110 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2111 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2112 </para>
2113 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2114 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael</primary></indexterm>
2115 <para>
2116 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2117 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2118 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2119
2120 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2121 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2122 about <quote>the placement of objects, color, &hellip; rhythm, pacing, and
2123 texture.</quote><footnote>
2124 <para>
2125 <!-- f11 -->
2126 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish, 13 December
2127 2002.
2128 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2129 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2130 </para></footnote>
2131 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2132 <quote>played</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2133 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2134 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2135 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2136 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2137 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2138 to a wildly successful author.<footnote><para>
2139 <!-- f12 -->
2140 See Scott Steinberg, <quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,</quote> E!online, 4
2141 November 2000, available at
2142 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #8</ulink>; <quote>Timeline,</quote> 22 November 2000,
2143 available at
2144 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #9</ulink>.
2145 </para></footnote>
2146 </para>
2147 <indexterm><primary>computer games</primary></indexterm>
2148 <para>
2149 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2150 describes, <quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2151 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2152 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2153 led.</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2154 </para>
2155 <para>
2156 Yet the push for an expanded literacy&mdash;one that goes beyond text
2157 to include audio and visual elements&mdash;is not about making better
2158 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2159 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2160 </para>
2161 <blockquote>
2162 <para>
2163 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2164 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2165 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2166 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2167 being read-only.
2168 </para>
2169 </blockquote>
2170 <para>
2171 <quote>Read-only.</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2172 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2173 twentieth century.
2174 </para>
2175 <para>
2176 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2177 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2178 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2179 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2180 literacy,
2181 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2182 and this literacy in particular, is to <quote>empower people to choose the
2183 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2184 express.</quote><footnote>
2185 <para>
2186 <!-- f13 -->
2187 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2188 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2189 </para></footnote> It is to enable students <quote>to communicate in the
2190 language of the twenty-first century.</quote><footnote><para>
2191 <!-- f14 -->
2192 Ibid.
2193 </para></footnote>
2194 </para>
2195 <indexterm id='idxbarishstephanie' class='startofrange'><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2196 <para>
2197 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2198 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2199 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2200 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2201 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2202 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2203 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2204 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2205 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2206 students know something about&mdash;gun violence.
2207 </para>
2208 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='endofrange'/>
2209 <para>
2210 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2211 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2212 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2213 away. The <quote>kids were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night,</quote>
2214 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2215 what education should be about&mdash;learning how to express themselves.
2216 </para>
2217 <para>
2218 Using whatever <quote>free web stuff they could find,</quote> and relatively simple
2219 tools to enable the kids to mix <quote>image, sound, and text,</quote> Barish said
2220 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2221 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2222 close to the lives of these students. The project <quote>gave them a tool
2223 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2224 it,</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2225 expression&mdash;far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2226 been created using only text. <quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2227 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2228 gone and done something else,</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2229 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2230 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2231 <emphasis>these</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2232 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2233 </para>
2234 <indexterm startref='idxbarishstephanie' class='endofrange'/>
2235 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='startofrange'><primary>Daley, Elizabeth</primary></indexterm>
2236 <para>
2237
2238 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2239 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?</quote> I asked. In part,
2240 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2241 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of <quote>constructing
2242 meaning.</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2243 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2244 part&mdash;and increasingly, not the most powerful part&mdash;of
2245 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2246 our interview,
2247 </para>
2248 <blockquote>
2249 <para>
2250 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2251 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2252 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2253 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2254 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2255 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2256 you say, <quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.</quote>
2257 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2258 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2259 you. [But i]nstead, if you say, <quote>Well, with all these things that you
2260 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2261 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2262 for me something that reflects that.</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2263 camera and &hellip; saying, <quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2264 make a little movie.</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2265 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2266 about the topic.&hellip;
2267 </para>
2268 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2269 <para>
2270 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2271 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2272 bump up against the fact, <quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2273 to write something.</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2274 they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 times, till they got it right.
2275 </para>
2276 <para>
2277 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2278 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2279 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2280 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2281 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2282 had a lot of power with this language.
2283 </para>
2284 </blockquote>
2285 <indexterm startref='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2286 <indexterm startref='idxmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'/>
2287 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='endofrange'/>
2288 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='endofrange'/>
2289 <indexterm id='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='startofrange'><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2290 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center</primary></indexterm>
2291 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
2292 <para>
2293 <emphasis role='strong'>When two planes</emphasis> crashed into the
2294 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2295 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2296 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2297 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2298 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2299 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2300 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2301 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2302 watching.
2303 </para>
2304 <para>
2305 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2306 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2307 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was <quote>balance,</quote>
2308 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2309 increasingly come to expect it, <quote>news as entertainment,</quote> even if the
2310 entertainment is tragedy.
2311 </para>
2312 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
2313 <indexterm><primary>CBS</primary></indexterm>
2314 <para>
2315 But in addition to this produced news about the <quote>tragedy of September
2316 11,</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2317 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2318 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2319 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2320 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2321 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2322 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2323 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2324 the term in his book <citetitle>Cyber Rights</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2325 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2326 was also the Internet.
2327 </para>
2328 <indexterm startref='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='endofrange'/>
2329 <para>
2330 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet&mdash;though I do think the
2331 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2332 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2333 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2334 movie
2335 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2336 by a student on the <quote>Just Think!</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2337 with sound or text.
2338 </para>
2339 <para>
2340 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2341 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2342 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2343 tradition&mdash;not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2344 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2345 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2346 spread practically instantaneously.
2347 </para>
2348 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
2349 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2350 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2351 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2352 <para>
2353 September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2354 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2355 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2356 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2357 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2358 cultures, it records private facts in a public way&mdash;it's a kind
2359 of electronic <citetitle>Jerry Springer</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2360 </para>
2361 <indexterm><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2362 <indexterm id='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>public discourse conducted on</secondary></indexterm>
2363 <para>
2364 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2365 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2366 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2367 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2368 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2369 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2370 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2371 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2372 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2373 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2374 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2375 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2376 </para>
2377 <indexterm id='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression</secondary></indexterm>
2378 <indexterm id='idxelections' class='startofrange'><primary>elections</primary></indexterm>
2379 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='startofrange'><primary>expression, technologies of</primary><secondary>democratic</secondary></indexterm>
2380 <para>
2381 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2382 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2383 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2384 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2385 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2386 people vote
2387 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2388 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2389 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2390 </para>
2391 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2392 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson' class='endofrange'/>
2393 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs' class='endofrange'/>
2394 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de</primary></indexterm>
2395 <indexterm id='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='startofrange'><primary>democracy</primary><secondary>public discourse in</secondary></indexterm>
2396 <indexterm><primary>jury system</primary></indexterm>
2397 <para>
2398 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2399 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2400 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2401 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2402 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2403 most important account of early <quote>Democracy in America.</quote> It wasn't
2404 popular elections that fascinated him&mdash;it was the jury, an
2405 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2406 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2407 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2408 deliberated. Members argued about the <quote>right</quote> result; they tried to
2409 persuade each other of the <quote>right</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2410 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2411 come to an end.<footnote><para>
2412 <!-- f15 -->
2413 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, <citetitle>Democracy in America</citetitle>,
2414 bk. 1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16.
2415 </para></footnote>
2416 </para>
2417 <indexterm startref='idxelections' class='endofrange'/>
2418 <para>
2419 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2420 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2421 are pushing to create just such an institution.<footnote><para>
2422 <!-- f16 -->
2423 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, <quote>Deliberation Day,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2424 Political Philosophy</citetitle> 10 (2) (2002): 129.
2425 </para></footnote>
2426 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2427 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2428 place for <quote>democratic deliberation</quote> to occur.
2429 </para>
2430 <indexterm id='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='startofrange'><primary>political discourse</primary></indexterm>
2431 <para>
2432 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2433 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2434 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2435 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2436 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2437 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.<footnote><para>
2438 <!-- f17 -->
2439 Cass Sunstein, <citetitle>Republic.com</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001),
2440 65&ndash;80, 175, 182, 183, 192.
2441 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2442 little beyond what our friends say.
2443 </para>
2444 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2445 <indexterm><primary>e-mail</primary></indexterm>
2446 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>blogs on</secondary></indexterm>
2447 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs2' class='startofrange'><primary>Web-logs (blogs)</primary></indexterm>
2448 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='endofrange'/>
2449 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='endofrange'/>
2450 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='endofrange'/>
2451 <para>
2452 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2453 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2454 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2455 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2456 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2457
2458 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2459 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2460 place.
2461 </para>
2462 <para>
2463 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2464 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2465 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2466 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2467 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2468 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2469 </para>
2470 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard</primary></indexterm>
2471 <para>
2472 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2473 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race
2474 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2475 is having an effect.
2476 </para>
2477 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent</primary></indexterm>
2478 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom</primary></indexterm>
2479 <indexterm id='idxmediablogpressureon' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>blog pressure on</secondary></indexterm>
2480 <indexterm id='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>news events on</secondary></indexterm>
2481 <para>
2482 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2483 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2484 <quote>misspoke</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2485 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2486 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2487 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2488 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2489 more instances of the same <quote>misspeaking</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2490 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2491 resign as senate majority leader.<footnote><para>
2492 <!-- f18 -->
2493 Noah Shachtman, <quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,</quote> New
2494 York Times, 16 January 2003, G5.
2495 </para></footnote>
2496 </para>
2497 <indexterm id='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='startofrange'><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2498 <para>
2499 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2500 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2501 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2502 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2503 on.
2504 </para>
2505 <indexterm startref='idxmediablogpressureon' class='endofrange'/>
2506 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>peer-generated rankings on</secondary></indexterm>
2507 <para>
2508 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2509 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2510 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2511 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2512 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2513 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2514 peer-generated rankings.
2515 </para>
2516 <indexterm startref='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='endofrange'/>
2517 <indexterm id='idxjournalism' class='startofrange'><primary>journalism</primary></indexterm>
2518 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'><primary>Winer, Dave</primary></indexterm>
2519 <para>
2520 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2521 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2522 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2523 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2524 difference is the absence of a financial <quote>conflict of interest.</quote> <quote>I think you
2525 have to take the conflict of interest</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2526 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2527 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2528 get it out of the way.</quote>
2529 </para>
2530 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2531 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of</secondary></indexterm>
2532 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2533 <indexterm><primary>media</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in</secondary></indexterm>
2534 <para>
2535 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2536 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2537 from the public than an unconcentrated media can&mdash;as CNN admitted
2538 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2539 its own employees.<footnote><para>
2540 <!-- f19 -->
2541 Telephone interview with David Winer, 16 April 2003.
2542 </para></footnote>
2543 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2544 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2545 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2546 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2547 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2548 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2549 told her that <emphasis>they</emphasis> were writing <quote>the story.</quote>)
2550 </para>
2551 <indexterm startref='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='endofrange'/>
2552 <para>
2553 Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2554 debate&mdash;<quote>amateur</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced,
2555 but in the sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to
2556 give their reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a
2557 story, as reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds
2558 from across the southwest United States turned to the Internet to
2559 retell what they had seen.<footnote><para>
2560 <!-- f20 -->
2561 John Schwartz, <quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2562 Information Online,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci
2563 D. Kramer, <quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,</quote>
2564 Online Journalism Review, 2 February 2003, available at
2565 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #10</ulink>.
2566 </para></footnote>
2567 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2568 <quote>triangulate,</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2569 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2570 out of it</quote>&mdash;with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2571 </para>
2572 <para>
2573 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2574 with blogs. <quote>It's going to become an essential skill,</quote> Winer predicts,
2575 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2576 not clear that <quote>journalism</quote> is happy about this&mdash;some journalists
2577 have been told to curtail their blogging.<footnote>
2578 <para>
2579 <!-- f21 -->
2580 <indexterm><primary>CNN</primary></indexterm>
2581 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
2582 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve</primary></indexterm>
2583 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)</primary></indexterm>
2584 See Michael Falcone, <quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?</quote> <citetitle>New
2585 York Times</citetitle>, 29 September 2003, C4. (<quote>Not all news organizations have
2586 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2587 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2588 war on March 9, stopped posting 12 days later at his bosses'
2589 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a <citetitle>Houston Chronicle</citetitle> reporter, was
2590 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2591 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.</quote>)
2592 </para></footnote>
2593 But it is clear that we are still in transition. <quote>A
2594
2595 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2596 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,</quote> Winer told me.
2597 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2598 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2599 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said, <quote>we will
2600 be the last thing that gets shut down.</quote>
2601 </para>
2602 <indexterm startref='idxjournalism' class='endofrange'/>
2603 <para>
2604 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because <quote>you
2605 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.</quote>
2606 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2607 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2608 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2609 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2610 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2611 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2612 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2613 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2614 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2615 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2616 extraordinary to report.
2617 </para>
2618 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage' class='endofrange'/>
2619 <indexterm startref='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='endofrange'/>
2620 <indexterm startref='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='endofrange'/>
2621 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2622 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson2' class='endofrange'/>
2623 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs2' class='endofrange'/>
2624 <indexterm startref='idxwinerdave' class='endofrange'/>
2625 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
2626 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
2627 <para>
2628 <emphasis role='strong'>John Seely Brown</emphasis> is the chief
2629 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2630 describes it, is <quote>human learning and &hellip; the creation of
2631 knowledge ecologies for creating &hellip; innovation.</quote>
2632 </para>
2633 <para>
2634 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2635 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2636 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2637 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2638 affect learning.
2639 </para>
2640 <para>
2641 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When <quote>a lot of us grew up,</quote>
2642 he explains, that tinkering was done <quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2643 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.</quote> But digital technologies
2644 enable a different kind of tinkering&mdash;with abstract ideas though
2645 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2646 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2647 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2648 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2649 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2650 or <quote>free collage,</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2651 the tinkering of many others.
2652 </para>
2653 <para>
2654 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2655 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2656 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2657 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2658 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2659 </para>
2660 <para>
2661 This opportunity creates a <quote>completely new kind of learning platform,</quote>
2662 as Brown describes. <quote>As soon as you start doing that, you &hellip;
2663 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2664 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2665 if they can improve it.</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2666 apprenticeship. <quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.</quote>
2667 </para>
2668 <para>
2669 In this process, <quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2670 They are code.</quote> Kids are <quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2671 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2672 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2673 platform. &hellip; You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2674 you tinker the more you improve.</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2675 learn.
2676 </para>
2677 <para>
2678 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2679 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2680 it, <quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2681 intelligence.</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2682 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2683 text. <quote>The Web &hellip; says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2684 you are visual, if you are interested in film &hellip; [then] there is a
2685 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2686 these multiple forms of intelligence.</quote>
2687 </para>
2688 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'/>
2689 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie</primary></indexterm>
2690 <para>
2691 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2692 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2693
2694 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2695 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2696 kind of recognition.
2697 </para>
2698 <para>
2699 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2700 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2701 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2702 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2703 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2704 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2705 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2706 </para>
2707 <para>
2708 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2709 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2710 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>)
2711 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the <quote>right to
2712 tinker</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2713 general.<footnote><para>
2714 <!-- f22 -->
2715 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, <quote>Technological Access
2716 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2717 of the Association for Computer Machinery</citetitle> 43 (2000): 9.
2718 </para></footnote>
2719 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2720 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2721 </para>
2722 <para>
2723 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,</quote> Brown
2724 explains. We need to <quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2725 and want to learn.</quote>
2726 </para>
2727 <para>
2728 <quote>Yet,</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2729 evince, <quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2730 natural tendencies of today's digital kids. &hellip; We're building an
2731 architecture that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2732 system that closes down that part of the brain.</quote>
2733 </para>
2734 <para>
2735 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2736 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2737 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2738 the law to close down that technology.
2739 </para>
2740 <indexterm><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
2741 <indexterm startref='idxbrownjohnseely' class='endofrange'/>
2742 <para>
2743 <quote>No way to run a culture,</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2744 chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="collectors"/>,
2745 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2746 </para>
2747 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2748 </chapter>
2749 <chapter label="3" id="catalogs">
2750 <title>Chapter Three: Catalogs</title>
2751 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2752 <indexterm><primary>RPI</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</see></indexterm>
2753 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary></indexterm>
2754 <indexterm id='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='startofrange'><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)</primary><secondary>computer network search engine of</secondary></indexterm>
2755 <indexterm id='idxsearchengines' class='startofrange'><primary>search engines</primary></indexterm>
2756 <indexterm id='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='startofrange'><primary>university computer networks, p2p sharing on</primary></indexterm>
2757 <indexterm id='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>search engines used on</secondary></indexterm>
2758 <para>
2759 <emphasis role='strong'>In the fall</emphasis> of 2002, Jesse Jordan
2760 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2761 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2762 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2763 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2764 was available on the RPI network.
2765 </para>
2766 <para>
2767 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2768 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2769 to information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand
2770 undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school
2771 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2772 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2773 </para>
2774 <para>
2775 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2776 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2777 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2778 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2779 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2780 </para>
2781 <indexterm id='idxgoogle' class='startofrange'><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2782 <para>
2783 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2784 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2785 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2786 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2787 engines can do this even better. The idea of <quote>intranet</quote> search
2788 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2789 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2790 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2791 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2792 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2793 </para>
2794 <indexterm id='idxjordanjesse' class='startofrange'><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
2795 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>network file system of</secondary></indexterm>
2796 <para>
2797 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2798 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2799 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2800 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2801 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2802 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2803 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2804 </para>
2805 <indexterm startref='idxgoogle' class='endofrange'/>
2806 <para>
2807 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2808 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2809 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2810 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2811 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2812 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2813 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2814 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2815 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2816 on-line.
2817 </para>
2818 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='endofrange'/>
2819 <para>
2820 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2821 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2822 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2823 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2824 be on users' computers.
2825 </para>
2826 <indexterm startref='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='endofrange'/>
2827 <para>
2828 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2829 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2830 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2831 might have created; university brochures&mdash;basically anything that
2832 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2833 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2834 computer.
2835 </para>
2836 <indexterm><primary>Google</primary></indexterm>
2837 <indexterm><primary>education</primary><secondary>tinkering as means of</secondary></indexterm>
2838 <para>
2839 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2840 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2841 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and&mdash;so that this
2842 point is absolutely clear&mdash;Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2843 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2844 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2845 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2846 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2847 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2848 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2849 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2850 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2851 supposed to do.
2852 </para>
2853 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
2854 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>against student file sharing</secondary></indexterm>
2855 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
2856 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
2857 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='endofrange'/>
2858 <para>
2859 On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2860 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2861 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2862 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2863 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2864 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2865 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2866 </para>
2867 <para>
2868 <quote>It was absurd,</quote> he told me. <quote>I don't think I did anything
2869 wrong. &hellip; I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2870 engine that I ran or &hellip; what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2871 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2872 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2873 easier to use</quote>&mdash;again, a <emphasis>search engine</emphasis>,
2874 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2875 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2876 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2877 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2878 with music.
2879 </para>
2880 <indexterm startref='idxsearchengines' class='endofrange'/>
2881 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
2882 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>statutory damages of</secondary></indexterm>
2883 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>individual defendants intimidated by</secondary></indexterm>
2884 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages</primary></indexterm>
2885 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>intimidation tactics of</secondary></indexterm>
2886 <para>
2887 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2888 network and had therefore <quote>willfully</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2889 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2890 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2891 <quote>willful infringement,</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2892 call <quote>statutory damages.</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2893 claim $150,000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2894 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2895 Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000.
2896 </para>
2897 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University</primary></indexterm>
2898 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University</primary></indexterm>
2899 <para>
2900 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2901 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2902 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2903 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2904 huge demands for <quote>damages</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2905 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2906 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $100
2907 <emphasis>billion</emphasis>&mdash;six times the
2908 <emphasis>total</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2909 2001.<footnote><para>
2910
2911 <!-- f1 -->
2912 Tim Goral, <quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks:
2913 Suit Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages,</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC</citetitle> 6
2914 (2003): 5, available at 2003 WL 55179443.
2915 </para></footnote>
2916 </para>
2917 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaer' class='endofrange'/>
2918 <para>
2919 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2920 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2921 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2922 $12,000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2923 $12,000 to dismiss the case.
2924 </para>
2925 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt</primary></indexterm>
2926 <para>
2927 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2928 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2929 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2930 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2931 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2932 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2933 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, <quote>You don't want to pay another
2934 visit to a dentist like me.</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2935 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2936 </para>
2937 <indexterm><primary>legal system, attorney costs in</primary></indexterm>
2938 <para>
2939 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2940 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2941 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2942 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2943 at least $250,000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2944 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2945 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2946 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2947 </para>
2948 <para>
2949 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $250,000 and a chance at winning,
2950 or $12,000 and a settlement.
2951 </para>
2952 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
2953 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
2954 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
2955 <para>
2956 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2957 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2958 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2959 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2960 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $1 million a year.
2961 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2962 artist makes $45,900.<footnote><para>
2963 <!-- f2 -->
2964 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001)
2965 (27&ndash;2042&mdash;Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2966 the Arts, <citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon</citetitle> (2000).
2967 </para></footnote>
2968 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2969 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2970 student for running a search engine?<footnote><para>
2971 <!-- f3 -->
2972 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in <quote>KaZaA and Punishment,</quote>
2973 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, A24.
2974 </para></footnote>
2975 </para>
2976 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='endofrange'/>
2977 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='endofrange'/>
2978 <para>
2979 On June 23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2980 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2981 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $15 million lawsuit became an
2982 activist:
2983 </para>
2984 <blockquote>
2985 <para>
2986 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2987 an activist. &hellip; [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2988 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2989 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2990 </para>
2991 </blockquote>
2992 <para>
2993 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2994 his father told me, Jesse <quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2995 I. &hellip; He's not a tree hugger. &hellip; I think it's bizarre that they would
2996 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2997 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.</quote>
2998 </para>
2999 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'/>
3000 <indexterm startref='idxjordanjesse' class='endofrange'/>
3001 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3002 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='endofrange'/>
3003 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='endofrange'/>
3004 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='endofrange'/>
3005 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
3006 </chapter>
3007 <chapter label="4" id="pirates">
3008 <title>Chapter Four: <quote>Pirates</quote></title>
3009 <indexterm id='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in development of content industry</secondary></indexterm>
3010 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right</quote> theory</primary></indexterm>
3011 <para>
3012 <emphasis role='strong'>If <quote>piracy</quote> means</emphasis>
3013 using the creative property of others without their
3014 permission&mdash;if <quote>if value, then right</quote> is
3015 true&mdash;then the history of the content industry is a history of
3016 piracy. Every important sector of <quote>big media</quote>
3017 today&mdash;film, records, radio, and cable TV&mdash;was born of a
3018 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
3019 generation's pirates join this generation's country club&mdash;until
3020 now.
3021 </para>
3022 <section id="film">
3023 <title>Film</title>
3024 <indexterm><primary>Hollywood film industry</primary><seealso>film industry</seealso></indexterm>
3025 <indexterm id='idxhollywoodfilmindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>Hollywood film industry</primary></indexterm>
3026 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonfilmtechnology' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on film technology</secondary></indexterm>
3027 <para>
3028 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.<footnote><para>
3029 <!-- f1 -->
3030 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
3031 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
3032 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 87&ndash;93,
3033 which details Edison's <quote>adventures</quote> with copyright and patent.
3034 </para></footnote>
3035 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
3036 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
3037 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
3038 exercised through a monopoly <quote>trust,</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
3039 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
3040 property&mdash;patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
3041 this creative property
3042 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
3043 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
3044 </para>
3045 <para>
3046 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
3047 </para>
3048 <blockquote>
3049 <para>
3050 A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
3051 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
3052 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
3053 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
3054 summer of 1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
3055 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
3056 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
3057 </para>
3058 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William</primary></indexterm>
3059 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company</primary></indexterm>
3060 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3061 <para>
3062 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
3063 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
3064 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
3065 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
3066 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
3067 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
3068 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
3069 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
3070 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
3071 license was revoked.<footnote><para>
3072 <!-- f2 -->
3073 J. A. Aberdeen, <citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
3074 Picture Producers</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts
3075 posted at <quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
3076 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,</quote> available at
3077 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #11</ulink>. For a
3078 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
3079 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, <quote>From
3080 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
3081 the Propertization of Copyright</quote> (September 2002), University of
3082 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
3083 Working Paper No. 159.
3084 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
3085 </para></footnote>
3086 </para>
3087 </blockquote>
3088 <para>
3089 The Napsters of those days, the <quote>independents,</quote> were companies like
3090 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
3091 resisted. <quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
3092 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
3093 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.</quote><footnote><para>
3094 <!-- f3 -->
3095 Marc Wanamaker, <quote>The First Studios,</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority</citetitle>, archived at
3096 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #12</ulink>.
3097 </para></footnote>
3098 That led the independents to flee the East
3099 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
3100 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
3101 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
3102 did just that.
3103 </para>
3104 <indexterm startref='idxhollywoodfilmindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3105 <para>
3106 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
3107 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
3108 patent holder a truly <quote>limited</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
3109
3110 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
3111 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
3112 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
3113 Edison's creative property.
3114 </para>
3115 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonfilmtechnology' class='endofrange'/>
3116 </section>
3117 <section id="recordedmusic">
3118 <title>Recorded Music</title>
3119 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
3120 <para>
3121 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
3122 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
3123 </para>
3124 <indexterm id='idxfourneauxhenri' class='startofrange'><primary>Fourneaux, Henri</primary></indexterm>
3125 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil</primary></indexterm>
3126 <para>
3127 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
3128 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3129 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3130 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3131 their music. In other words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3132 1899 hit <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3133 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3134 right to perform it publicly.
3135 </para>
3136 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3137 <para>
3138 But what if I wanted to record <quote>Happy Mose,</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3139 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3140 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3141 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3142 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3143 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3144 <quote>public performance</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3145 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3146 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3147 brain are not&mdash;yet&mdash; regulated by copyright law). So if I
3148 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3149 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3150 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3151 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3152 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3153 its composer anything.
3154 </para>
3155 <indexterm startref='idxfourneauxhenri' class='endofrange'/>
3156 <para>
3157 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3158 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3159 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3160 put it,
3161 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3162 </para>
3163 <blockquote>
3164 <para>
3165 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3166 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3167 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3168 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3169 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3170 rights.<footnote><para>
3171 <!-- f4 -->
3172 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3173 S. 6330 and H.R. 19853 Before the (Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th
3174 Cong. 59, 1st sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3175 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in <citetitle>Legislative History of the
3176 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3177 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3178 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred</primary></indexterm>
3179 </para></footnote>
3180 </para>
3181 </blockquote>
3182 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip</primary></indexterm>
3183 <para>
3184 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3185 people's works were <quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3186 genius of American composers,</quote><footnote><para>
3187 <!-- f5 -->
3188 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223
3189 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3190 </para></footnote>
3191 and the <quote>music publishing industry</quote>
3192 was thereby <quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.</quote><footnote><para>
3193 <!-- f6 -->
3194 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226
3195 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3196 </para></footnote>
3197 As John Philip
3198 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible, <quote>When they make money
3199 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.</quote><footnote><para>
3200 <!-- f7 -->
3201 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23
3202 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3203 </para></footnote>
3204 </para>
3205 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company</primary></indexterm>
3206 <indexterm><primary>player pianos</primary></indexterm>
3207 <indexterm><primary>sheet music</primary></indexterm>
3208 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
3209 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
3210 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
3211 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>statutory license system in</secondary></indexterm>
3212 <para>
3213 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3214 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3215 player piano argued that <quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3216 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3217 of anything he had before their introduction.</quote> Rather, the machines
3218 increased the sales of sheet music.<footnote><para>
3219 <!-- f8 -->
3220
3221 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283&ndash;84
3222 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3223 Perforating Company of New York).
3224 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3225 Congress was <quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3226 they represent, and whose servants they are.</quote> <quote>All talk about
3227 `theft,'</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3228 wrote, <quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3229 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3230 statute.</quote><footnote><para>
3231 <!-- f9 -->
3232 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared
3233 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3234 Graphophone Company Association).
3235 </para></footnote>
3236 </para>
3237 <indexterm><primary>cover songs</primary></indexterm>
3238 <para>
3239 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3240 <emphasis>and</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3241 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the <quote>mechanical
3242 reproductions</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3243 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3244 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3245 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3246 recorded once. This is the part of
3247
3248 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3249 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3250 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3251 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3252 </para>
3253 <indexterm id='idxcompulsorylicense' class='startofrange'><primary>compulsory license</primary></indexterm>
3254 <indexterm id='idxstatutorylicenses' class='startofrange'><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
3255 <para>
3256 American law ordinarily calls this a <quote>compulsory license,</quote> but I will
3257 refer to it as a <quote>statutory license.</quote> A statutory license is a license
3258 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3259 Copyright Act in 1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3260 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3261 the fee set by the statute.
3262 </para>
3263 <indexterm id='idxgrishamjohn' class='startofrange'><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
3264 <para>
3265 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3266 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3267 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3268 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3269 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3270 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3271 Grisham.
3272 </para>
3273 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='endofrange'/>
3274 <indexterm><primary>Beatles</primary></indexterm>
3275 <para>
3276 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3277 thus, in effect, the law <emphasis>subsidizes</emphasis> the recording
3278 industry through a kind of piracy&mdash;by giving recording artists a
3279 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3280 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3281 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3282 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3283 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3284 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3285 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3286 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3287 creativity.<footnote><para>
3288
3289 <!-- f10 -->
3290 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and
3291 H.R. 11794 Before the (Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st
3292 sess., 217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3293 in <citetitle>Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3294 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976).
3295 </para></footnote>
3296 </para>
3297 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='endofrange'/>
3298 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3299 <indexterm startref='idxgrishamjohn' class='endofrange'/>
3300 <para>
3301 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3302 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3303 records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3304 relates,
3305 </para>
3306 <blockquote>
3307 <para>
3308 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3309 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3310 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3311 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3312 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3313 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3314 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3315 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3316 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before 1909 and
3317 the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3318 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3319 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3320 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3321 choice.<footnote><para>
3322 <!-- f11 -->
3323 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee
3324 on the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8
3325 March 1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3326 this report.</para></footnote>
3327 </para>
3328 </blockquote>
3329 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='endofrange'/>
3330 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='endofrange'/>
3331 <indexterm startref='idxcompulsorylicense' class='endofrange'/>
3332 <indexterm startref='idxstatutorylicenses' class='endofrange'/>
3333 <para>
3334 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3335 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3336 </para>
3337 </section>
3338 <section id="radio">
3339 <title>Radio</title>
3340 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
3341 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
3342 <para>
3343 Radio was also born of piracy.
3344 </para>
3345 <para>
3346 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3347 <quote>public performance</quote> of the composer's work.<footnote><para>
3348 <!-- f12 -->
3349 See 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning,
3350 record companies printed <quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast</quote> and other
3351 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3352 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3353 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3354 station. See <citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Whiteman</citetitle>, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd
3355 Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3356 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3357 Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 281.
3358 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned</primary></indexterm>
3359 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
3360 </para></footnote>
3361 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3362 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3363 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3364 </para>
3365 <indexterm id='idxradiomusicrecordingsplayedon' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
3366 <para>
3367 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3368 copy of the <emphasis>composer's</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3369 also performing a copy of the <emphasis>recording artist's</emphasis>
3370 work. It's one thing to have <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> sung on the radio by the
3371 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3372 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3373 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3374 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3375 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3376 music for his work.
3377 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
3378
3379 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3380 </para>
3381 <para>
3382 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3383 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3384 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3385 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3386 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3387 of playing the song.
3388 </para>
3389 <indexterm id='idxmadonna' class='startofrange'><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3390 <para>
3391 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3392 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3393 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3394 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3395 </para>
3396 <para>
3397 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3398 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3399 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3400 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3401 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3402 <quote>protected</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3403 <emphasis>pirate</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3404 her anything.
3405 </para>
3406 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='endofrange'/>
3407 <indexterm startref='idxradiomusicrecordingsplayedon' class='endofrange'/>
3408 <indexterm startref='idxmadonna' class='endofrange'/>
3409 <para>
3410 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3411 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3412 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3413 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3414 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3415 to take something for nothing.
3416 </para>
3417 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='endofrange'/>
3418 </section>
3419 <section id="cabletv">
3420 <title>Cable TV</title>
3421 <indexterm id='idxcabletelevision' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
3422 <para>
3423 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3424 </para>
3425 <para>
3426 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3427 television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3428 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3429 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3430 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3431 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3432 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3433 did&mdash; Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3434 give away.
3435 </para>
3436 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas</primary></indexterm>
3437 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin</primary></indexterm>
3438 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3439 <para>
3440 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3441 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3442 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.</quote><footnote><para>
3443 <!-- f13 -->
3444 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the
3445 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3446 Committee on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966)
3447 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3448 Commission).
3449 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.</primary></indexterm>
3450 </para></footnote>
3451 There may have been a <quote>public interest</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3452 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3453 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, <quote>Does public
3454 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?</quote><footnote><para>
3455 <!-- f14 -->
3456 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3457 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3458 </para></footnote>
3459 As another broadcaster put it,
3460 </para>
3461 <blockquote>
3462 <para>
3463 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3464 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3465 paid for.<footnote><para>
3466 <!-- f15 -->
3467 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3468 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3469 </para></footnote>
3470 </para>
3471 </blockquote>
3472 <para>
3473 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3474 </para>
3475 <blockquote>
3476 <para>
3477 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3478 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3479 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3480 think there are harsher words which would fit it.<footnote><para>
3481 <!-- f16 -->
3482 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3483 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3484 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3485 </para></footnote>
3486 </para>
3487 </blockquote>
3488 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3489 <para>
3490 These were <quote>free-ride[rs],</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3491 Heston said, who were <quote>depriving actors of
3492 compensation.</quote><footnote><para>
3493 <!-- f17 -->
3494 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3495 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3496 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton</primary></indexterm>
3497 </para>
3498 </footnote>
3499 </para>
3500 <para>
3501 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3502 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3503 </para>
3504 <blockquote>
3505 <para>
3506 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3507 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3508 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3509 should be permitted to extend that monopoly. &hellip; The
3510
3511 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3512 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3513 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.<footnote><para>
3514 <!-- f18 -->
3515 Copyright Law Revision&mdash;CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M.
3516 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3517 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3518 </para></footnote>
3519 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin</primary></indexterm>
3520 </para>
3521 </blockquote>
3522 <para>
3523 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3524 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3525 </para>
3526 <para>
3527 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3528 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they <quote>pirated.</quote>
3529 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3530 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3531 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3532 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3533 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3534 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3535 companies thus built their empire in part upon a <quote>piracy</quote> of the value
3536 created by broadcasters' content.
3537 </para>
3538 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='endofrange'/>
3539 <indexterm startref='idxcabletelevision' class='endofrange'/>
3540 <para>
3541 <emphasis role='strong'>These separate stories</emphasis> sing a
3542 common theme. If <quote>piracy</quote> means using value from someone
3543 else's creative property without permission from that creator&mdash;as
3544 it is increasingly described today<footnote><para>
3545 <!-- f19 -->
3546 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, <citetitle>The Engine
3547 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet&mdash;The Myth of Free
3548 Information</citetitle>, available at
3549 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #13</ulink>. <quote>The
3550 threat of piracy&mdash;the use of someone else's creative work without
3551 permission or compensation&mdash;has grown with the Internet.</quote>
3552 </para></footnote>
3553 &mdash; then <emphasis>every</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3554 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3555 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV. &hellip; The list is long and
3556 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3557 last. Every generation&mdash;until now.
3558 </para>
3559 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3560 </section>
3561 </chapter>
3562 <chapter label="5" id="piracy">
3563 <title>Chapter Five: <quote>Piracy</quote></title>
3564 <para>
3565 <emphasis role='strong'>There is piracy</emphasis> of copyrighted
3566 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3567 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3568 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3569 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3570 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3571 </para>
3572 <para>
3573 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of <quote>taking</quote>
3574 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3575 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3576 taking <quote>piracy,</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3577 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3578 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3579 has so often done in the past.
3580 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3581 </para>
3582 <section id="piracy-i">
3583 <title>Piracy I</title>
3584 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3585 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3586 <para>
3587 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3588 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3589 content, copy it, and sell it&mdash;all without the permission of a copyright
3590 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion
3591 every year to physical piracy<footnote><para>
3592 <!-- f1 -->
3593 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), <citetitle>The
3594 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003</citetitle>, July 2003, available
3595 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #14</ulink>. See
3596 also Ben Hunt, <quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3597 Times</citetitle>, 14 February 2003, 11.
3598 </para></footnote>
3599 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3600 estimates that it loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3601 </para>
3602 <para>
3603 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3604 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3605 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3606 This piracy is wrong.
3607 </para>
3608 <para>
3609 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3610 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3611 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3612 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3613 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3614 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3615 of our existence, treated as right.
3616 </para>
3617 <para>
3618 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3619 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3620 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3621 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3622 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3623 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3624 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3625 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3626 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3627 </para>
3628 <para>
3629 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3630 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3631 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3632 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3633 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3634 similar childhood.
3635 </para>
3636 <para>
3637 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3638 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3639 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3640 of intellectual property law.<footnote><para>
3641 <!-- f2 -->
3642 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3643 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The
3644 New Press, 2003), 10&ndash;13, 209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3645 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3646 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3647 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3648 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3649 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3650 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3651 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3652 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3653 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3654 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3655 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3656 TRIPS framework.
3657 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents</primary></indexterm>
3658 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
3659 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3660 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3661 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3662 is wrong.
3663 </para>
3664 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3665 <para>
3666 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3667 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3668 to American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3669 bought those American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any
3670 less money than they otherwise would have had.<footnote><para>
3671 <!-- f3 -->
3672 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3673 Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002),
3674 144&ndash;90. <quote>In some instances &hellip; the impact of piracy on the
3675 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3676 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3677 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3678 pirating were not an option.</quote> Ibid., 149.
3679 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3680 </para></footnote>
3681 </para>
3682 <para>
3683 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3684 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3685 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3686 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3687 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes &amp; Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3688 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?</quote>
3689 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes &amp;
3690 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3691 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3692 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3693 piracy of the tangible.
3694 </para>
3695 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'/>
3696 <para>
3697 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3698 property right of a very special sort, it <emphasis>is</emphasis> a
3699 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3700 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3701 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3702 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3703 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3704 give people the right to <quote>take</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3705 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3706
3707 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3708 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3709 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3710 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3711 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3712 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what <quote>property</quote> means.
3713 </para>
3714 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
3715 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
3716 <indexterm><primary>open-source software</primary><see>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</see></indexterm>
3717 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
3718 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3719 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3720 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of</secondary></indexterm>
3721 <indexterm><primary>Windows</primary></indexterm>
3722 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>international software piracy of</secondary></indexterm>
3723 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of</secondary></indexterm>
3724 <para>
3725 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3726 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese <quote>steal</quote>
3727 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3728 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3729 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3730 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3731 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3732 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3733 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3734 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3735 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3736 </para>
3737 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
3738 <para>
3739 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3740 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3741 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3742 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3743 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3744 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3745 </para>
3746 <indexterm><primary>Netscape</primary></indexterm>
3747 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer</primary></indexterm>
3748 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3749 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
3750 <para>
3751 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3752 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3753 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3754 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3755 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3756 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3757 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3758 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3759 what&mdash;at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3760 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3761 violating the law is still wrong.
3762 </para>
3763 <para>
3764 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3765 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3766 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3767 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3768 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3769 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3770 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3771 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3772 is flat out wrong.
3773 </para>
3774 <para>
3775 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3776 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is. Or
3777 at least, not all <quote>piracy</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3778 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of <quote>piracy</quote> are useful
3779 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3780 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3781 <quote>piracy</quote> in that sense of the term.
3782 </para>
3783 <para>
3784 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3785 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3786 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3787 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3788 </para>
3789 <para>
3790 For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3791 controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it
3792 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable
3793 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3794 </para>
3795 <para>
3796 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3797 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3798 sharing to survive.
3799 </para>
3800 </section>
3801 <section id="piracy-ii">
3802 <title>Piracy II</title>
3803 <para>
3804 The key to the <quote>piracy</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that <quote>rob[s]
3805 the author of [his] profit.</quote><footnote><para>
3806 <!-- f4 -->
3807 <citetitle>Bach</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Longman</citetitle>, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777).
3808 </para></footnote>
3809 This means we must determine whether
3810 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3811 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3812 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3813 author of his profit.
3814 </para>
3815 <para>
3816 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn</primary></indexterm>
3817 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary><seealso>creativity</seealso></indexterm>
3818 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3819 <indexterm id='idxnapster' class='startofrange'><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
3820 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3821 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3822 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3823 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well<footnote><para>
3824 <!-- f5 -->
3825 <indexterm><primary>innovation</primary></indexterm>
3826 See Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3827 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle> (New York:
3828 HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3829 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3830 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3831 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3832 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3833 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 89&ndash;92, 139.
3834
3835 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
3836 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3837 put together components that had been developed independently.
3838 </para>
3839 <para>
3840 <indexterm><primary>Kazaa</primary></indexterm>
3841 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>number of registrations on</secondary></indexterm>
3842 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>replacement of</secondary></indexterm>
3843 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999,
3844 Napster amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After
3845 eighteen months, there were close to 80 million registered users of the
3846 system.<footnote><para>
3847 <!-- f6 -->
3848 See Carolyn Lochhead, <quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,</quote> <citetitle>San
3849 Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24 September 2002, A1; <quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,</quote>
3850 <citetitle>New Scientist</citetitle>, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Napster Names CEO,
3851 Secures New Financing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 23 May 2003, C1;
3852 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton,
3853 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet</quote> (London) <citetitle>Times</citetitle>, 26 July 2002, 18.
3854 </para></footnote>
3855 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3856 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3857 boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3858 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3859 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3860 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend&mdash;
3861 or your 20,000 best friends.
3862 </para>
3863 <indexterm startref='idxnapster' class='endofrange'/>
3864 <para>
3865 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3866 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3867 September 2002 estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded
3868 music&mdash;28 percent of Americans older than 12.<footnote><para>
3869
3870 <!-- f7 -->
3871 See Ipsos-Insight, <citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution</citetitle>
3872 (September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3873 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have
3874 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3875 </para></footnote>
3876 A survey by the NPD group quoted in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>
3877 estimated that 43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3878 exchange content in May 2003.<footnote><para>
3879 <!-- f8 -->
3880 Amy Harmon, <quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,</quote> <citetitle>New
3881 York Times</citetitle>, 6 June 2003, A1.
3882 </para></footnote>
3883 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3884 massive quantity of content is being <quote>taken</quote> on these networks. The
3885 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3886 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3887 </para>
3888 <para>
3889 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3890 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3891 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3892 complicated than one might think. So consider&mdash;a bit more
3893 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3894 do&mdash;the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3895 of harm it entails.
3896 </para>
3897 <para>
3898 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3899 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3900 different kinds into four types.
3901 </para>
3902 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
3903 <listitem>
3904 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
3905 <para>
3906 <!-- A. -->
3907 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3908 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3909 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3910 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3911 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3912 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3913 users who download instead of purchasing.
3914 </para></listitem>
3915 <listitem><para>
3916 <!-- B. -->
3917 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3918 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3919 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3920 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3921 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3922 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3923 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3924 music purchased.
3925 </para></listitem>
3926 <listitem><para>
3927 <!-- C. -->
3928 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3929 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3930 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3931 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3932 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3933 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3934 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend <quote>recalling</quote> old
3935 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3936 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3937 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3938 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero&mdash;the same
3939 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to
3940 a local collector.
3941 </para></listitem>
3942 <listitem><para>
3943 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3944 <!-- D. -->
3945 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3946 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3947 wants to give away.
3948 </para></listitem>
3949 </orderedlist>
3950 <para>
3951 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3952 </para>
3953 <para>
3954 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3955 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3956 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3957 harmful.<footnote><para>
3958 <!-- f9 -->
3959 See Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy</citetitle>, 148&ndash;49.
3960 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
3961 </para></footnote>
3962 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3963 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3964 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3965 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3966 answer&mdash;and certainly much more difficult than the current
3967 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3968 </para>
3969 <para>
3970 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3971 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3972 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3973 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3974 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of <quote>theft</quote> that is
3975 <quote>devastating</quote> the industry.
3976 </para>
3977 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
3978 <para>
3979 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3980 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3981 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3982 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3983 &amp; Young put it, <quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3984 technology, the labels fought it.</quote><footnote><para>
3985 <!-- f10 -->
3986 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary></indexterm>
3987 See Cap Gemini Ernst &amp; Young, <citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3988 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis</citetitle> (2003), 3. This report
3989 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3990 practice of cassette taping in the 1970s, including an advertising
3991 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption <quote>Home taping
3992 is killing music.</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3993 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3994 behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3995 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3996 Assessment, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law</citetitle>,
3997 OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3998 October 1989), 145&ndash;56. </para></footnote>
3999 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
4000 when record sales fell by 11.4 percent in 1981, the industry claimed
4001 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
4002 regulating technology was the answer.
4003 </para>
4004 <indexterm><primary>MTV</primary></indexterm>
4005 <para>
4006 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
4007 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
4008 turnaround. <quote>In the end,</quote> Cap Gemini concludes, <quote>the `crisis' &hellip; was
4009 not the fault of the tapers&mdash;who did not [stop after MTV came into
4010 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
4011 being]&mdash;but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
4012 innovation at the major labels.</quote><footnote><para>
4013 <!-- f11 -->
4014 U.S. Congress, <citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying</citetitle>, 4.
4015 </para></footnote>
4016 </para>
4017 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'/>
4018 <para>
4019 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
4020 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
4021 the industry in particular, and society in general&mdash;or at least
4022 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
4023 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
4024 VCR&mdash;the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
4025 harmful. The question is also <emphasis>how</emphasis> harmful type A
4026 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
4027 </para>
4028 <para>
4029 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
4030 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
4031 The <quote>net harm</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
4032 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
4033 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
4034 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
4035 therefore have little <emphasis>static</emphasis> reason to resist
4036 them.
4037
4038 </para>
4039 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>sales levels of</secondary></indexterm>
4040 <para>
4041 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
4042 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
4043 actually suggest it might be close.
4044 </para>
4045 <para>
4046 In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent,
4047 from 882 million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7
4048 percent.<footnote><para>
4049 <!-- f12 -->
4050 See Recording Industry Association of America, <citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics</citetitle>,
4051 available at
4052 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #15</ulink>. A later
4053 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
4054 Association of America, <citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy</citetitle>, 25 June 2003,
4055 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
4056 #16</ulink>: <quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
4057 have fallen by 26 percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million
4058 units in 2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
4059 of sales, revenues are down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6
4060 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
4061 industry worldwide has gone from a $39 billion industry in 2000 down
4062 to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
4063 shipments).</quote>
4064 </para></footnote>
4065 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
4066 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
4067 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
4068 than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no
4069 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
4070 account for at least some of the loss. <quote>From 1999 to 2001, the average
4071 price of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19.</quote><footnote>
4072 <!-- f13 -->
4073 <para>
4074 Jane Black, <quote>Big Music's Broken Record,</quote> BusinessWeek online, 13
4075 February 2003, available at
4076 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #17</ulink>.
4077 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane</primary></indexterm>
4078 </para>
4079 </footnote>
4080 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
4081 the decline. As Jane Black of <citetitle>BusinessWeek</citetitle> notes, <quote>The
4082 soundtrack to the film <citetitle>High Fidelity</citetitle> has a list price of
4083 $18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
4084 $19.99.</quote><footnote><para>
4085 <!-- f14 -->
4086 Ibid.
4087 </para></footnote>
4088 </para>
4089 <para>
4090
4091 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
4092 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
4093 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
4094 that the RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
4095 estimates that 2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
4096 although 2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4097 free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 percent.
4098 </para>
4099 <para>
4100 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
4101 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
4102 The recording industry constantly asks, <quote>What's the difference between
4103 downloading a song and stealing a CD?</quote>&mdash;but their own numbers
4104 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
4105 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
4106 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
4107 downloads. If every download were a lost sale&mdash;if every use of
4108 Kazaa <quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit</quote>&mdash;then the industry
4109 would have suffered a 100 percent drop in sales last year, not a 7
4110 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4111 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, then there is
4112 a huge difference between <quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.</quote>
4113 </para>
4114 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'/>
4115 <para>
4116 These are the harms&mdash;alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
4117 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
4118 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
4119 these costs?
4120 </para>
4121 <para>
4122 One benefit is type C sharing&mdash;making available content that
4123 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
4124 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
4125 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
4126 available.<footnote><para>
4127 <!-- f15 -->
4128 By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels
4129 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
4130 Law&mdash;Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
4131 Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April
4132 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
4133 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #18</ulink>.
4134 </para></footnote>
4135 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
4136 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
4137 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
4138 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
4139 sense <emphasis>to the company</emphasis> to make it available.
4140 </para>
4141 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4142 <indexterm><primary>used record sales</primary></indexterm>
4143 <para>
4144 In real space&mdash;long before the Internet&mdash;the market had a simple
4145 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
4146 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
4147 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
4148 today.<footnote><para>
4149 <!-- f16 -->
4150 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
4151 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
4152 in existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the
4153 United States, an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter
4154 Press, <citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
4155 Market</citetitle> (2002), available at
4156 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #19</ulink>. Used
4157 records accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See National
4158 Association of Recording Merchandisers, <quote>2002 Annual Survey
4159 Results,</quote> available at
4160 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #20</ulink>.
4161 </para></footnote>
4162 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4163 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4164 content, <emphasis>even if the content is still under
4165 copyright</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4166 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4167 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4168 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4169 the content they sell.
4170 </para>
4171 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
4172 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard</primary></indexterm>
4173 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
4174 <para>
4175 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4176 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4177 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4178 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4179 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4180 when someone shares my 1949 recording of Bernstein's <quote>Two Love Songs,</quote>
4181 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4182 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4183 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4184 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4185 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4186 </para>
4187 <para>
4188 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4189 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4190 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4191 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4192 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4193 shut as well?
4194 </para>
4195 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
4196 <indexterm><primary>Doctorow, Cory</primary></indexterm>
4197 <indexterm><primary>Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom (Doctorow)</primary></indexterm>
4198 <para>
4199 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4200 type D sharing to occur&mdash;the sharing of content that copyright owners
4201 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4202 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4203 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
4204 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4205
4206 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4207 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4208 would be a great advertisement for the <quote>real</quote> book. People would read
4209 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4210 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4211 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4212 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4213 great book!)
4214 </para>
4215 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'/>
4216 <para>
4217 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4218 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4219 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4220 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4221 </para>
4222 <para>
4223 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4224 understandably says, <quote>This is how much we've lost,</quote> we must also ask,
4225 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4226 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4227 unavailable?</quote>
4228 </para>
4229 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson' class='endofrange'/>
4230 <para>
4231 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4232 chapter, much of the <quote>piracy</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4233 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4234 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="pirates"/>, much of
4235 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4236 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4237 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4238 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4239 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4240 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4241 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4242 found only with time.
4243 </para>
4244 <para>
4245 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4246 just what you call type A sharing?</quote>
4247 </para>
4248 <para>
4249 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The effect
4250 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4251 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4252 Napster case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4253 developed a technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of
4254 identified
4255
4256 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4257 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4
4258 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4259 <quote>down to zero.</quote><footnote><para>
4260 <!-- f17 -->
4261 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34-
4262 35 (N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183
4263 MHP, available at
4264
4265 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #21</ulink>. For an
4266 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4267 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster</citetitle> (New
4268 York: Crown Business, 2003), 269&ndash;82.
4269 </para></footnote>
4270 </para>
4271 <para>
4272 If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4273 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4274 assure that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance
4275 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of
4276 VCRs or 100 percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns
4277 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4278 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4279 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4280 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4281 </para>
4282 <para>
4283 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4284 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4285 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4286 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4287 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4288 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4289 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4290 </para>
4291 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
4292 <indexterm><primary>composers, copyright protections of</primary></indexterm>
4293 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4294 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
4295 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on music recordings</secondary></indexterm>
4296 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
4297 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
4298 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
4299 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright protections in</secondary></indexterm>
4300 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
4301 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
4302 <indexterm><primary>composer's rights vs. producers' rights in</primary></indexterm>
4303 <para>
4304 So, as we've seen, when <quote>mechanical reproduction</quote> threatened the
4305 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4306 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4307 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4308 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4309 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4310 complained to Congress that their <quote>creative property</quote> was not being
4311 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4312 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4313 benefit was enough.
4314 </para>
4315 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
4316 <para>
4317 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4318 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4319 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4320 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4321 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4322 price.
4323 </para>
4324 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='endofrange'/>
4325 <para>
4326
4327 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4328 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4329 pianos, served two important goals&mdash;indeed, the two central goals
4330 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4331 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4332 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4333 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4334 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4335 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4336 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4337 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4338 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4339 Congress chose a path that would assure
4340 <emphasis>compensation</emphasis> without giving the past
4341 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4342 </para>
4343 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='endofrange'/>
4344 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='endofrange'/>
4345 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'/>
4346 <indexterm id='idxbetamax' class='startofrange'><primary>Betamax</primary></indexterm>
4347 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
4348 <indexterm id='idxsonybetamaxtechnologydevelopedby' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Betamax technology developed by</secondary></indexterm>
4349 <para>
4350 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4351 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4352 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4353 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4354 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4355 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4356 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4357 <quote>record</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4358 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4359 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4360 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4361 </para>
4362 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='endofrange'/>
4363 <para>
4364 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4365 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4366 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4367 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4368 machine to copy only if there were a special <quote>copy me</quote> signal on the
4369 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4370 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4371 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4372 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4373 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4374 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4375 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4376 for the architecture it chose.
4377 </para>
4378 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
4379 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on VCR technology</secondary></indexterm>
4380 <para>
4381 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4382 champion. Valenti called VCRs <quote>tapeworms.</quote> He warned, <quote>When there are
4383 20, 30, 40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4384 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4385 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4386 copyright.</quote><footnote><para>
4387 <!-- f18 -->
4388 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4389 S. 1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st
4390 and 2nd sess., 459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4391 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4392 </para></footnote>
4393 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4394 creative judgment,</quote> he told Congress, <quote>to understand the devastation
4395 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4396 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4397 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4398 and plain common sense.</quote><footnote><para>
4399 <!-- f19 -->
4400 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475.
4401 </para></footnote>
4402 Indeed, as surveys would later show, 45
4403 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more<footnote><para>
4404 <!-- f20 -->
4405 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 480 F. Supp. 429,
4406 (C.D. Cal., 1979).
4407 </para></footnote>
4408 &mdash; a use the Court would later hold was not <quote>fair.</quote> By
4409 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4410 copyright infringement without creating a mechanism to compensate
4411 copyright owners,</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would <quote>take from the
4412 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4413 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4414 profit from its reproduction.</quote><footnote><para>
4415 <!-- f21 -->
4416 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony
4417 of Jack Valenti).
4418 </para></footnote>
4419 </para>
4420 <indexterm startref='idxbetamax' class='endofrange'/>
4421 <indexterm startref='idxsonybetamaxtechnologydevelopedby' class='endofrange'/>
4422 <para>
4423 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4424 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4425 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction&mdash;leading Judge Alex
4426 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the <quote>Hollywood
4427 Circuit</quote>&mdash;held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4428 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4429 rule, this totally familiar technology&mdash;which Jack Valenti had
4430 called <quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry</quote> (worse
4431 yet, it was a <emphasis>Japanese</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4432 American film industry)&mdash;was an illegal
4433 technology.<footnote><para>
4434 <!-- f22 -->
4435 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle>, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th Cir.
4436 1981).
4437 </para></footnote>
4438 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex</primary></indexterm>
4439 </para>
4440 <para>
4441 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4442
4443 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4444 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4445 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4446 Court wrote,
4447 </para>
4448 <blockquote>
4449 <para>
4450 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4451 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4452 market
4453 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4454 authority
4455 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4456 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4457 implicated
4458 by such new technology.<footnote><para>
4459 <!-- f23 -->
4460 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417, 431 (1984).
4461 </para></footnote>
4462 </para>
4463 </blockquote>
4464 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='endofrange'/>
4465 <para>
4466 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4467 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4468 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4469 enough, this <quote>taking</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4470 together, a pattern is clear:
4471 </para>
4472
4473 <informaltable id="t1">
4474 <tgroup cols="4" align="left">
4475 <thead>
4476 <row>
4477 <entry>CASE</entry>
4478 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS <quote>PIRATED</quote></entry>
4479 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS</entry>
4480 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS</entry>
4481 </row>
4482 </thead>
4483 <tbody>
4484 <row>
4485 <entry>Recordings</entry>
4486 <entry>Composers</entry>
4487 <entry>No protection</entry>
4488 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4489 </row>
4490 <row>
4491 <entry>Radio</entry>
4492 <entry>Recording artists</entry>
4493 <entry>N/A</entry>
4494 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4495 </row>
4496 <row>
4497 <entry>Cable TV</entry>
4498 <entry>Broadcasters</entry>
4499 <entry>No protection</entry>
4500 <entry>Statutory license</entry>
4501 </row>
4502 <row>
4503 <entry>VCR</entry>
4504 <entry>Film creators</entry>
4505 <entry>No protection</entry>
4506 <entry>Nothing</entry>
4507 </row>
4508 </tbody>
4509 </tgroup>
4510 </informaltable>
4511 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'/>
4512 <para>
4513 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4514 way content was distributed.<footnote><para>
4515 <!-- f24 -->
4516 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4517 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4518 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4519 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4520 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4521 1992 (Title 17 of the <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat.
4522 4237, codified at 17 U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4523 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4524 Lessig, <citetitle>Future</citetitle>, 71. See also Picker, <quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,</quote>
4525 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 293&ndash;96.
4526 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
4527 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
4528 </para></footnote>
4529 In each case, throughout our history,
4530 that change meant that someone got a <quote>free ride</quote> on someone else's
4531 work.
4532 </para>
4533 <para>
4534 In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4535 Congress eliminate all free riding. In <emphasis>none</emphasis> of
4536 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4537 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4538 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of <quote>piracy.</quote>
4539 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4540 the behavior of the <quote>pirates.</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4541 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4542 interests at stake.
4543 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4544 </para>
4545 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
4546 <para>
4547 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4548 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4549 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4550 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4551 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4552 regulated?
4553 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4554 to $15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4555 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4556 permission to record a song?
4557 </para>
4558 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on balance of interests in copyright law</secondary></indexterm>
4559 <para>
4560 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4561 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4562 copyright <quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4563 over all possible uses of his work.</quote><footnote><para>
4564 <!-- f25 -->
4565 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
4566 (1984).
4567 </para></footnote>
4568 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4569 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4570 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4571 balancing has historically been done <emphasis>after</emphasis> a
4572 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4573 facilitate the distribution of content.
4574 </para>
4575 <para>
4576 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4577 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4578 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4579 should not become a tool for <quote>stealing</quote> from artists. But neither
4580 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4581 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4582 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4583 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4584 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4585 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4586 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4587 public interest that innovation continue.
4588 </para>
4589 <para>
4590
4591 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4592 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4593 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4594 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4595 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4596 efficient. Yet these <quote>potential public benefits,</quote> as John Schwartz
4597 writes in <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, <quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4598 fight.</quote><footnote><para>
4599 <!-- f26 -->
4600 John Schwartz, <quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4601 Echoes Past Efforts,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 22 September 2003, C3.
4602 </para></footnote>
4603 </para>
4604 <para>
4605 <emphasis role='strong'>Yet when anyone</emphasis> begins to talk
4606 about <quote>balance,</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4607 argument. <quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4608 incentives,</quote> they say, <quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4609 content,</quote> the warriors insist, <quote>is our
4610 <emphasis>property</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4611 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4612 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4613 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4614 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?</quote>
4615 </para>
4616 <para>
4617 <quote>It is <emphasis>our property</emphasis>,</quote> the warriors
4618 insist. <quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4619 is protected.</quote>
4620 </para>
4621 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4622 </section>
4623 </chapter>
4624 </part>
4625 <part id="c-property">
4626 <title><quote>Property</quote></title>
4627 <partintro>
4628 <para>
4629
4630 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4631 <emphasis role='strong'>The copyright warriors</emphasis> are right: A
4632 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4633 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4634 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4635 that partially determine the price she can get.
4636 </para>
4637 <para>
4638 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a <quote>property</quote> right is a
4639 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4640 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4641 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4642 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4643 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4644 when I take the good <emphasis>idea</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4645 table in the backyard&mdash;by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4646 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4647 then?
4648 </para>
4649 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
4650 <para>
4651 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4652 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4653 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4654 in the ordinary case&mdash;indeed, in practically every case except for a
4655 narrow
4656 range of exceptions&mdash;ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4657 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress&mdash;though I
4658 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4659 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4660 when I copy the way someone else dresses), <quote>He who receives an idea
4661 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4662 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.</quote><footnote><para>
4663 <!-- f1 -->
4664 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in
4665 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson</citetitle>, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4666 Ellery Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333&ndash;34.
4667 </para></footnote>
4668 </para>
4669 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>intangibility of</secondary></indexterm>
4670 <para>
4671 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4672 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4673 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4674 expression
4675 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4676 property.
4677 </para>
4678 <para>
4679 But how, and to what extent, and in what form&mdash;the details,
4680 in other words&mdash;matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4681 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4682 <quote>property</quote> in its proper context.<footnote><para>
4683 <!-- f2 -->
4684 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4685 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4686 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4687 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4688 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4689 Adam Mossoff, <quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,</quote>
4690 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review</citetitle> 45 (2003): 373, 429 n. 241.
4691 </para></footnote>
4692 </para>
4693 <para>
4694 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4695 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4696 <quote>copyright material is property</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4697 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4698 these stories, the significance of this true
4699 statement&mdash;<quote>copyright material is property</quote>&mdash; will be a bit
4700 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4701 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4702 </para>
4703 </partintro>
4704
4705 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4706 <chapter label="6" id="founders">
4707 <title>Chapter Six: Founders</title>
4708 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for</secondary></indexterm>
4709 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
4710 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>English</secondary></indexterm>
4711 <indexterm id='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='startofrange'><primary>England, copyright laws developed in</primary></indexterm>
4712 <indexterm id='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='startofrange'><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>history of copyright law in</secondary></indexterm>
4713 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4714 <indexterm><primary>Henry V</primary></indexterm>
4715 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4716 <indexterm id='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='startofrange'><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4717 <para>
4718 <emphasis role='strong'>William Shakespeare</emphasis> wrote
4719 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> in 1595. The play was first
4720 published in 1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4721 written. He would continue to write plays through 1613, and the plays
4722 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4723 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4724 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4725 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4726 Henry V: <quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4727 clichés.</quote>
4728 </para>
4729 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4730 <indexterm id='idxtonsonjacob' class='startofrange'><primary>Tonson, Jacob</primary></indexterm>
4731 <para>
4732 In 1774, almost 180 years after <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> was written, the
4733 <quote>copy-right</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4734 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.<footnote><para>
4735 <!-- f1 -->
4736 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben</primary></indexterm>
4737 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John</primary></indexterm>
4738 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4739 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4740 handsome <quote>definitive editions</quote> of classic works. In addition to <citetitle>Romeo and
4741 Juliet</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4742 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4743 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker, <quote>Jacob Tonson,
4744 Bookseller,</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar</citetitle> 61:3 (1992): 424&ndash;31.
4745 </para></footnote>
4746 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4747 the Conger<footnote><para>
4748 <!-- f2 -->
4749 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle> (Nashville:
4750 Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151&ndash;52.
4751 </para></footnote>
4752 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4753 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the <quote>copy</quote> of
4754 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4755 that no
4756 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4757 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4758 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4759 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4760 </para>
4761 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4762 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4763 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
4764 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4765 <para>
4766 Now, there's something puzzling about the year 1774 to anyone who
4767 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4768 history of copyright is 1710, the year that the British Parliament
4769 adopted the first <quote>copyright</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4770 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4771 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4772 works already published by 1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4773 additional years.<footnote><para>
4774 <!-- f3 -->
4775 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
4776 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4777 <quote>copyright law.</quote> See Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs</citetitle>, 40.
4778 </para></footnote> Under this law, <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> should have been
4779 free in 1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4780 Tonson's control in 1774?
4781 </para>
4782 <indexterm startref='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='endofrange'/>
4783 <indexterm startref='idxtonsonjacob' class='endofrange'/>
4784 <indexterm id='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
4785 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
4786 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (1662)</primary></indexterm>
4787 <para>
4788 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a <quote>copyright</quote>
4789 was&mdash;indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4790 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4791 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of 1662, had
4792 expired in 1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4793 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4794 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4795 that the publishers, or <quote>Stationers,</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4796 books.
4797 </para>
4798 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='endofrange'/>
4799 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
4800 <para>
4801 There was no <emphasis>positive</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4802 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4803 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4804 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4805 from legislatures <quote>positive law.</quote> We call the words from judges
4806 <quote>common law.</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4807 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4808 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4809 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4810 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4811 </para>
4812 <indexterm startref='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='endofrange'/>
4813 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4814 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4815 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
4816 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4817 <para>
4818 This question was important to the publishers, or <quote>booksellers,</quote> as
4819 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4820 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4821 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4822
4823 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4824 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4825 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4826 ultimately
4827 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4828 </para>
4829 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>as narrow monopoly right</secondary></indexterm>
4830 <para>
4831 The Statute of Anne granted the author or <quote>proprietor</quote> of a book an
4832 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4833 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4834 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4835 copyright <quote>expired,</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4836 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4837 believed.
4838 </para>
4839 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne' class='endofrange'/>
4840 <para>
4841 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4842 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4843 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4844 <emphasis>at all?</emphasis>
4845 </para>
4846 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'/>
4847 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4848 <indexterm><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)</primary></indexterm>
4849 <para>
4850 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4851 strong claim. Take <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet</citetitle> as an example: That play
4852 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4853 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4854 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4855 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4856 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4857 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4858 reason is there to allow someone else to <quote>steal</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4859 </para>
4860 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
4861 <para>
4862 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4863 about the notion of <quote>copyright</quote> that existed at the time of the
4864 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4865 <quote>booksellers.</quote>
4866 </para>
4867 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
4868 <para>
4869 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4870 to apply the concept of <quote>copyright</quote> ever more broadly. But in 1710, it
4871 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4872 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4873 others from reprinting a book. In 1710, the <quote>copy-right</quote> was a right
4874 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4875 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4876 generally how
4877 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4878 a work could be <emphasis>used</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4879 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4880 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4881 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4882 </para>
4883 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
4884 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
4885 <para>
4886 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4887 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4888 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4889 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4890 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4891 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4892 allowed to make his films. The <quote>copy-right</quote> was only an exclusive
4893 right to print&mdash;no less, of course, but also no more.
4894 </para>
4895 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England</primary></indexterm>
4896 <indexterm id='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='startofrange'><primary>monopoly, copyright as</primary></indexterm>
4897 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (1656)</primary></indexterm>
4898 <para>
4899 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4900 They had had a long and ugly experience with <quote>exclusive rights,</quote>
4901 especially <quote>exclusive rights</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4902 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4903 monopolies&mdash;especially monopolies for works that already
4904 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4905 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4906 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In 1656, it passed the
4907 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4908 inventions. And by 1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4909 monopoly in publishing.
4910 </para>
4911 <para>
4912 Thus the <quote>copy-right,</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4913 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4914 claim that <quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,</quote> try
4915 sounding convincing when uttering, <quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4916 have it forever.</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4917 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4918 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4919 </para>
4920 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
4921 <indexterm id='idxbooksellersenglish' class='startofrange'><primary>booksellers, English</primary></indexterm>
4922 <indexterm><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
4923 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
4924 <para>
4925 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4926 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4927 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4928 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4929 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4930
4931 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4932 kind&mdash;tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4933 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4934 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as <quote>old patentees
4935 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling</quote>; they were <quote>men who do
4936 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4937 indetted.</quote><footnote><para>
4938
4939 <!-- f4 -->
4940 Philip Wittenberg, <citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4941 Property</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31.
4942 </para></footnote>
4943 </para>
4944 <indexterm><primary>Enlightenment</primary></indexterm>
4945 <indexterm><primary>knowledge, freedom of</primary></indexterm>
4946 <para>
4947 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4948 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4949 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4950 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4951 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4952 with that idea.
4953 </para>
4954 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament2' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
4955 <para>
4956 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4957 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4958 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4959 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4960 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4961 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4962 compromise
4963 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4964 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4965 construction and spread of culture.
4966 </para>
4967 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne2' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)
4968 </primary></indexterm>
4969 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
4970 <para>
4971 When 1731 (1710 + 21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4972 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4973 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4974 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4975 to control publication. But in 1735 and 1737, they tried to persuade
4976 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4977 they said; they needed more time.
4978 </para>
4979 <para>
4980 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4981 words that echo today,
4982 </para>
4983 <blockquote>
4984 <para>
4985 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4986 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4987 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4988 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4989 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4990 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4991 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4992 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4993 Booksellers.<footnote><para>
4994 <!-- f5 -->
4995 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4996 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4997 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4998 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4999 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
5000 mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
5001 al., 8, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618).
5002 </para></footnote>
5003 </para>
5004 </blockquote>
5005 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne2' class='endofrange'/>
5006 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='endofrange'/>
5007 <indexterm><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5008 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>common vs. positive</secondary></indexterm>
5009 <indexterm><primary>positive law</primary></indexterm>
5010 <para>
5011 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
5012 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
5013 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
5014 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
5015 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
5016 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
5017 creative <quote>property</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
5018 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
5019 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
5020 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
5021 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
5022 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
5023 way to protect authors.
5024 </para>
5025 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament2' class='endofrange'/>
5026 <para>
5027 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
5028 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
5029 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
5030 <quote>The publishers &hellip; had as much concern for authors as a cattle
5031 rancher has for cattle.</quote><footnote><para>
5032 <!-- f6 -->
5033 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5034 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
5035 Lyman Ray Patterson, <quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
5036 Law Review</citetitle> 40 (1987): 28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
5037 Vaidhyanathan, 37&ndash;48.
5038 </para></footnote>
5039 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
5040 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
5041 </para>
5042 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5043 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5044 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5045 <para>
5046 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
5047 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
5048 Donaldson.<footnote><para>
5049 <!-- f7 -->
5050 For a compelling account, see David Saunders, <citetitle>Authorship and Copyright</citetitle>
5051 (London: Routledge, 1992), 62&ndash;69.
5052 </para></footnote>
5053 </para>
5054 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne3' class='startofrange'><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
5055 <indexterm id='idxconger' class='startofrange'><primary>Conger</primary></indexterm>
5056 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James</primary></indexterm>
5057 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew</primary></indexterm>
5058 <para>
5059 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
5060 career in Edinburgh in 1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
5061 reprints <quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,</quote> at least
5062 under the Statute of Anne.<footnote><para>
5063 <!-- f8 -->
5064 Mark Rose, <citetitle>Authors and Owners</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
5065 1993), 92.
5066 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
5067 </para></footnote>
5068 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
5069 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
5070 and became <quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.</quote> <quote>[A]mong
5071 them,</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was <quote>the young James Boswell
5072 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
5073 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.</quote><footnote><para>
5074 <!-- f9 -->
5075 Ibid., 93.
5076 </para></footnote>
5077 </para>
5078 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5079 <para>
5080 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
5081 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
5082 inexpensive editions <quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
5083 of the supposed common law right of Literary
5084 Property.</quote><footnote><para>
5085 <!-- f10 -->
5086 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond</primary></indexterm>
5087 Lyman Ray Patterson, <citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective</citetitle>, 167 (quoting
5088 Borwell).
5089 </para></footnote>
5090 His books undercut the Conger prices by 30 to 50 percent, and he
5091 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
5092 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
5093 </para>
5094 <indexterm startref='idxconger' class='endofrange'/>
5095 <indexterm id='idxmillarvtaylor' class='startofrange'><primary>Millar v. Taylor</primary></indexterm>
5096 <para>
5097 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block <quote>piracy</quote> like
5098 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the <quote>pirates,</quote>
5099 the most important early victory being <citetitle>Millar</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Taylor</citetitle>.
5100 </para>
5101 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='endofrange'/>
5102 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers' class='endofrange'/>
5103 <indexterm id='idxthomsonjames' class='startofrange'><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5104 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5105 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)</primary></indexterm>
5106 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert</primary></indexterm>
5107 <para>
5108 Millar was a bookseller who in 1729 had purchased the rights to James
5109 Thomson's poem <quote>The Seasons.</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
5110 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
5111 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
5112 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
5113 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.<footnote><para>
5114 <!-- f11 -->
5115 Howard B. Abrams, <quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
5116 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review</citetitle> 29
5117 (1983): 1152.
5118 </para></footnote>
5119 </para>
5120 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord</primary></indexterm>
5121 <para>
5122 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
5123 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
5124 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
5125 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
5126 law would protect the author against subsequent <quote>pirates.</quote>
5127 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
5128 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
5129 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
5130 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
5131 </para>
5132 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw' class='endofrange'/>
5133 <indexterm startref='idxthomsonjames' class='endofrange'/>
5134 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='endofrange'/>
5135 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament3' class='startofrange'><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5136 <para>
5137 Considered as a matter of abstract justice&mdash;reasoning as if
5138 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
5139 principles&mdash;Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
5140 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
5141 with in 1710: How best to limit
5142 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
5143 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
5144 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in 1710, but
5145 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
5146 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
5147 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
5148 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
5149 </para>
5150 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'/>
5151 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson, Alexander</primary></indexterm>
5152 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers2' class='startofrange'><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5153 <para>
5154 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
5155 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
5156 </para>
5157 <indexterm><primary>Thomson, James</primary></indexterm>
5158 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
5159 <indexterm id='idxhouseoflords' class='startofrange'><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5160 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='startofrange'><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>House of Lords vs.</secondary></indexterm>
5161 <para>
5162 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
5163 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
5164 Thomas Beckett.<footnote><para>
5165 <!-- f12 -->
5166 Ibid., 1156.
5167 </para></footnote>
5168 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
5169 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in <citetitle>Millar</citetitle>,
5170 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
5171 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
5172 Court. In February of 1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
5173 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
5174 </para>
5175 <indexterm startref='idxmillarvtaylor' class='endofrange'/>
5176 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament3' class='endofrange'/>
5177 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='startofrange'><primary>Donaldson v. Beckett</primary></indexterm>
5178 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>common law</primary></indexterm>
5179 <para>
5180 As few legal cases ever do, <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle> drew an
5181 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
5182 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
5183 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
5184 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
5185 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
5186 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
5187 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
5188 </para>
5189 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne3' class='endofrange'/>
5190 <para>
5191 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
5192 presented to the House and voted upon first by the <quote>law lords,</quote>
5193 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
5194 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
5195 House of Lords generally voted.
5196 </para>
5197 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='endofrange'/>
5198 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
5199 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5200 <para>
5201 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
5202 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
5203 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
5204 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
5205 (22 to 11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
5206 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
5207 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
5208 passed into the public domain.
5209 </para>
5210 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis</primary></indexterm>
5211 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John</primary></indexterm>
5212 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel</primary></indexterm>
5213 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John</primary></indexterm>
5214 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William</primary></indexterm>
5215 <para>
5216 <quote>The public domain.</quote> Before the case of <citetitle>Donaldson</citetitle>
5217 v. <citetitle>Beckett</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
5218 England. Before 1774, there was a strong argument that common law
5219 copyrights were perpetual. After 1774, the public domain was
5220 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
5221 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
5222 history&mdash;including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
5223 and Bunyan&mdash;were free of legal restraint.
5224 </para>
5225 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='endofrange'/>
5226 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers2' class='endofrange'/>
5227 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw2' class='endofrange'/>
5228 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='endofrange'/>
5229 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5230 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers</primary></indexterm>
5231 <para>
5232 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
5233 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
5234 where most of the <quote>pirate publishers</quote> did their work, people
5235 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the <citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser</citetitle>
5236 reported, <quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
5237 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
5238 decision of which so many individuals were interested.</quote> <quote>Great
5239 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
5240 and illuminations.</quote><footnote><para>
5241 <!-- f13 -->
5242 Rose, 97.
5243 </para></footnote>
5244 </para>
5245 <indexterm startref='idxhouseoflords' class='endofrange'/>
5246 <para>
5247 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
5248 equally strong in the opposite direction. The <citetitle>Morning Chronicle</citetitle>
5249 reported:
5250 </para>
5251 <blockquote>
5252 <para>
5253 By the above decision &hellip; near 200,000 pounds worth of what was
5254 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
5255 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
5256 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
5257 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
5258 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
5259 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
5260 successors.<footnote><para>
5261 <!-- f14 -->
5262 Ibid.
5263 </para></footnote>
5264 </para>
5265 </blockquote>
5266 <indexterm><primary>House of Lords</primary></indexterm>
5267 <indexterm><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of</secondary></indexterm>
5268 <para>
5269 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5270 <quote>Ruined</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5271 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5272 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5273 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5274 <emphasis>free</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5275 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5276 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5277 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5278 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5279 book from someone. But <emphasis>free</emphasis> in the sense that the
5280 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5281 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5282 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5283 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5284 develop&mdash; chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5285 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a <emphasis>competitive
5286 context</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5287 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5288 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5289 </para>
5290 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellersenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5291 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament</primary></indexterm>
5292 <para>
5293 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5294 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5295 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5296 protected.
5297 </para>
5298 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='endofrange'/>
5299 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'/>
5300 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='endofrange'/>
5301 <indexterm startref='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='endofrange'/>
5302 <indexterm startref='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='endofrange'/>
5303 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='endofrange'/>
5304 <indexterm startref='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='endofrange'/>
5305 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='endofrange'/>
5306 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='endofrange'/>
5307 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5308 </chapter>
5309 <chapter label="7" id="recorders">
5310 <title>Chapter Seven: Recorders</title>
5311 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
5312 <indexterm id='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>documentary film</primary></indexterm>
5313 <indexterm id='idxelsejon' class='startofrange'><primary>Else, Jon</primary></indexterm>
5314 <indexterm id='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>in documentary film</secondary></indexterm>
5315 <indexterm id='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='startofrange'><primary>films</primary><secondary>fair use of copyrighted material in</secondary></indexterm>
5316 <para>
5317 <emphasis role='strong'>Jon Else</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5318 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5319 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5320 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5321 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5322 </para>
5323 <para>
5324 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5325 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5326 today.
5327 </para>
5328 <indexterm id='idxwagnerrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5329 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5330 <para>
5331 In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5332 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5333 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5334 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5335 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5336 stage.
5337 </para>
5338 <indexterm id='idxsimpsonsthe' class='startofrange'><primary>Simpsons, The</primary></indexterm>
5339 <para>
5340 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5341 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5342 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5343 and the opera company played Wagner, was <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. As Else judged
5344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5345 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5346 about the scene.
5347 </para>
5348 <indexterm startref='idxwagnerrichard' class='endofrange'/>
5349 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>multiple copyrights associated with</secondary></indexterm>
5350 <para>
5351 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5352 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>.
5353 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5354 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5355 unless <quote>fair use</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5356 </para>
5357 <indexterm id='idxgraciefilms' class='startofrange'><primary>Gracie Films</primary></indexterm>
5358 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5359 <para>
5360 Else called <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5361 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5362 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5363 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5364 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5365 </para>
5366 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5367 <para>
5368 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5369 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5370 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5371 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5372 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5373 </para>
5374 <indexterm startref='idxgraciefilms' class='endofrange'/>
5375 <para>
5376 Then, as Else told me, <quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5377 &hellip; that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation&mdash;or at
5378 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.</quote>
5379 And second, Fox <quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5380 to use this four-point-five seconds of &hellip; entirely unsolicited
5381 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.</quote>
5382 </para>
5383 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt' class='endofrange'/>
5384 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='endofrange'/>
5385 <indexterm id='idxherrerarebecca' class='startofrange'><primary>Herrera, Rebecca</primary></indexterm>
5386 <para>
5387 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5388 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5389 explained to her, <quote>There must be some mistake here. &hellip; We're
5390 asking for your educational rate on this.</quote> That was the educational
5391 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5392 confirm what he had been told.
5393 </para>
5394 <indexterm><primary>Wagner, Richard</primary></indexterm>
5395 <para>
5396 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,</quote> he told me. <quote>Yes, you
5397 have your facts straight,</quote> she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the
5398 clip of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5399 about
5400
5401 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5402 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, <quote>And
5403 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.</quote> As an assistant
5404 to Herrera told Else later on, <quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5405 the money.</quote>
5406 </para>
5407 <indexterm startref='idxherrerarebecca' class='endofrange'/>
5408 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera</primary></indexterm>
5409 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The</primary></indexterm>
5410 <para>
5411 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5412 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5413 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5414 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5415 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5416 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5417 </para>
5418 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5419 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt2' class='startofrange'><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5420 <para>
5421 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5422 copyright to <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5423 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5424 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5425 <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5426 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5427 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5428 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5429 says the owner gets to control.
5430 </para>
5431 <para>
5432 For example, <quote>public performance</quote> is a use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle> that the
5433 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5434 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see <quote>My
5435 Favorite <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>,</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5436 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5437 whatever she wants&mdash;$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set
5438 by the law.
5439 </para>
5440 <para>
5441 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5442 thought is <quote>fair use.</quote><footnote><para>
5443 <!-- f1 -->
5444 For an excellent argument that such use is <quote>fair use,</quote> but that
5445 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is <quote>fair use,</quote> see Richard
5446 A. Posner with William F. Patry, <quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5447 Wake of <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5448 Law School, 5 August 2003.
5449 </para></footnote>
5450 Else's use of just 4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>
5451 episode is clearly a fair use of <citetitle>The Simpsons</citetitle>&mdash;and fair use does
5452 not require the permission of anyone.
5453 </para>
5454 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='endofrange'/>
5455 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt2' class='endofrange'/>
5456 <para>
5457 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5458 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon <quote>fair use.</quote> Here's his reply:
5459 </para>
5460 <blockquote>
5461 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
5462 <para>
5463 The <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5464 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5465 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5466 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was <quote>clearly
5467 fair use</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5468 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5469 </para>
5470 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
5471 <listitem>
5472 <indexterm><primary>Errors and Omissions insurance</primary></indexterm>
5473 <para>
5474 <!-- 1. -->
5475 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5476 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5477 <quote>visual cue sheet</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5478 shot in the film. They take a dim view of <quote>fair use,</quote> and a claim of
5479 <quote>fair use</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5480 </para></listitem>
5481 <listitem>
5482 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='startofrange'><primary>Fox (film company)</primary></indexterm>
5483 <indexterm><primary>Groening, Matt</primary></indexterm>
5484 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George</primary></indexterm>
5485 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5486 <para>
5487 <!-- 2. -->
5488 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5489 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5490 tracking down and stopping unlicensed <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle> usage, just as George
5491 Lucas had a very high profile litigating <citetitle>Star Wars</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5492 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5493 license to four seconds of <citetitle>Simpsons</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5494 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5495 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5496 principle.
5497 </para></listitem>
5498 <listitem><para>
5499 <!-- 3. -->
5500 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5501 School &hellip; who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5502 that Fox would <quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5503 life,</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5504 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5505 pockets, me or them.
5506 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5507 </para>
5508 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='endofrange'/>
5509 </listitem>
5510 <listitem><para>
5511 <!-- 4. -->
5512 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5513 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5514 money.
5515 </para></listitem>
5516 </orderedlist>
5517 </blockquote>
5518 <indexterm startref='idxsimpsonsthe' class='endofrange'/>
5519 <para>
5520 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5521 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5522 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5523 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5524 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5525 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5526 </para>
5527 <para>
5528 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5529 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5530 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5531 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5532 not.
5533 </para>
5534 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='endofrange'/>
5535 <indexterm startref='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5536 <indexterm startref='idxelsejon' class='endofrange'/>
5537 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'/>
5538 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='endofrange'/>
5539 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='endofrange'/>
5540 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5541 </chapter>
5542 <chapter label="8" id="transformers">
5543 <title>Chapter Eight: Transformers</title>
5544 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul</primary></indexterm>
5545 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5546 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary></indexterm>
5547 <para>
5548 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5549 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5550 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5551 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5552 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5553 anticipation of the power of networks.
5554 </para>
5555 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on</secondary></indexterm>
5556 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in</primary></indexterm>
5557 <para>
5558 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5559 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology&mdash;not to distribute
5560 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5561 difficult. In 1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5562 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5563 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5564 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5565 important to his career.
5566 </para>
5567 <para>
5568 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5569 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5570 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5571 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5572 </para>
5573 <para>
5574 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5575 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5576 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5577 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5578 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5579 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5580 </para>
5581 <para>
5582 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. <quote>Our
5583 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5584 Eastwood's films,</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5585 arose. <quote>No one had ever really done this before,</quote> Alben explained. <quote>No
5586 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5587 actor's career.</quote>
5588 </para>
5589 <para>
5590 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5591 Slade asked, <quote>Well, what will it take?</quote>
5592 </para>
5593 <para>
5594 Alben replied, <quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5595 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5596 else that we want to use in these film clips.</quote> Slade said, <quote>Great! Go
5597 for it.</quote><footnote>
5598 <para>
5599 <!-- f1 -->
5600 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5601 publicity&mdash;rights an artist has to control the commercial
5602 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden <quote>Rip, Mix,
5603 Burn</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5604 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of</secondary></indexterm>
5605 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5606 </para></footnote>
5607 </para>
5608 <para>
5609 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5610 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5611 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5612 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5613 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5614 </para>
5615 <para>
5616 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5617 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5618 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5619 </para>
5620 <blockquote>
5621 <para>
5622 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5623 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include&mdash;of
5624 course we were going to use the <quote>Make my day</quote> clip from <citetitle>Dirty
5625 Harry</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5626 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5627 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5628 </para>
5629 <para>
5630 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5631 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5632 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5633 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5634 rate at the time was about $600. So we had to identify the
5635 people&mdash;some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5636 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5637 glass&mdash;is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5638 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5639 started calling people.
5640 </para>
5641 </blockquote>
5642 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald</primary></indexterm>
5643 <para>
5644 Some actors were glad to help&mdash;Donald Sutherland, for example,
5645 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5646 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5647 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5648 know, $1,200?</quote> And they would say, <quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5649 to get $1,200.</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5650 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5651 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5652 career.
5653 </para>
5654 <para>
5655 It was one <emphasis>year</emphasis> later&mdash;<quote>and even then we
5656 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.</quote>
5657 </para>
5658 <para>
5659 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5660 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5661 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5662 </para>
5663 <blockquote>
5664 <para>
5665 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5666 hands and said, <quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5667 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5668 actors.</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5669 constituent parts and said, <quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5670 directors, &hellip; this many musicians,</quote> and we just went at it very
5671 systematically and cleared the rights.
5672 </para>
5673 </blockquote>
5674 <para>
5675
5676 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5677 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5678 loved it, and it sold very well.
5679 </para>
5680 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter</primary></indexterm>
5681 <para>
5682 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5683 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5684 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, <quote>There is
5685 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5686 at all.</quote><footnote><para>
5687 <!-- f2 -->
5688 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, <citetitle>Seven
5689 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition</citetitle>, available at
5690 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #22</ulink>.
5691 </para></footnote>
5692 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5693 has to be made?
5694 </para>
5695 <para>
5696 For, as he acknowledged, <quote>very few &hellip; have the time and resources,
5697 and the will to do this,</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5698 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5699 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5700 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5701 </para>
5702 <blockquote>
5703 <para>
5704 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5705 he or she gets paid very well. &hellip; And then when 30 seconds of
5706 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5707 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person &hellip; should be
5708 compensated for that.
5709 </para>
5710 </blockquote>
5711 <para>
5712 Or at least, is this <emphasis>how</emphasis> the artist should be
5713 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5714 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5715 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5716 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5717 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5718 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5719 made to be more clean?
5720 </para>
5721 <blockquote>
5722 <para>
5723 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5724 mechanism&mdash;where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5725 subject to estranged former spouses&mdash;you'd see a lot more of this
5726 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5727 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5728 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5729 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5730 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5731 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5732 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5733 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5734 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5735 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5736 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, <quote>Oh, I
5737 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5738 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5739 money,</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5740 </para>
5741 </blockquote>
5742 <para>
5743 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5744 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5745 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5746 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5747 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5748 </para>
5749 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'/>
5750 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'/>
5751 <para>
5752 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5753 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5754 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5755 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5756 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5757 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5758 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5759 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5760 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5761 <quote>Does this still make sense?</quote>
5762 </para>
5763 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'/>
5764 <para>
5765 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5766 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5767 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5768 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5769
5770 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5771 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5772 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5773 </para>
5774 <para>
5775 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5776 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode.
5777 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5778 judges loved every minute of it.
5779 </para>
5780 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David</primary></indexterm>
5781 <para>
5782 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5783 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5784 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5785 room of over 250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5786 began his talk with a question: <quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5787 were just violated in this room?</quote>
5788 </para>
5789 <para>
5790 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
5791 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David</primary></indexterm>
5792 <indexterm><primary>Court of Appeals</primary><secondary>Ninth Circuit</secondary></indexterm>
5793 <indexterm><primary>Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals</primary></indexterm>
5794 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary></indexterm>
5795 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5796 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5797 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5798 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5799 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle
5800 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5801 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5802 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5803 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5804 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5805 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5806 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5807 couldn't easily do them legally.
5808 </para>
5809 <para>
5810 We live in a <quote>cut and paste</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5811 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5812 and paste architecture of the Internet created&mdash;in a second you can
5813 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5814 planted in your presentation.
5815 </para>
5816 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos</primary></indexterm>
5817 <para>
5818 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5819 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5820 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5821 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5822 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5823 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5824 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5825 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5826 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5827 </para>
5828 <para>
5829 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5830 wanted to be <quote>legal,</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5831 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5832 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5833 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5834 </para>
5835 <para>
5836 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5837 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5838 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5839 necessarily requiring that the <quote>free</quote> use be free as in <quote>free beer.</quote>
5840 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5841 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5842 along: a rule, for example, that says <quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5843 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5844 will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5845 copyright owner.</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5846 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5847 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5848 registers the work.
5849 </para>
5850 <para>
5851 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5852 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5853 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5854 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5855 </para>
5856 <para>
5857 <emphasis role='strong'>In February 2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5858 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5859 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live</citetitle> and
5860 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5861 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5862 would work together to form a <quote>unique filmmaking pact.</quote> Under the
5863 agreement, DreamWorks <quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5864 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and&mdash;with the use
5865 of stateof-the-art digital technology&mdash;insert Myers and other
5866 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5867 entertainment.</quote>
5868 </para>
5869 <para>
5870 The announcement called this <quote>film sampling.</quote> As Myers explained,
5871 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5872 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5873 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5874 to take that same concept and apply it to film.</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5875 quoted as saying, <quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5876 new audiences, it is Mike.</quote>
5877 </para>
5878 <para>
5879 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5880 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5881 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5882 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5883 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5884 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5885 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5886 privilege reserved for the funny and famous&mdash;and presumably rich.
5887 </para>
5888 <para>
5889 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5890 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of <quote>fair use.</quote>
5891 Much of <quote>sampling</quote> should be considered <quote>fair use.</quote> But few would
5892 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5893 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5894 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5895 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5896 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5897 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5898 process is a process of paying lawyers&mdash;again a privilege, or perhaps a
5899 curse, reserved for the few.
5900 </para>
5901 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5902 </chapter>
5903 <chapter label="9" id="collectors">
5904 <title>Chapter Nine: Collectors</title>
5905 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
5906 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
5907 <para>
5908 <emphasis role='strong'>In April 1996</emphasis>, millions of
5909 <quote>bots</quote>&mdash;computer codes designed to
5910 <quote>spider,</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5911 content&mdash;began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5912 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5913 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5914 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5915 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5916 Internet and stored them.
5917 </para>
5918 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5919 <para>
5920 By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5921 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5922 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5923 the world. Using a technology called <quote>the Way Back Machine,</quote> you could
5924 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to 1996, as
5925 well as when those pages changed.
5926 </para>
5927 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'><primary>Orwell, George</primary></indexterm>
5928 <para>
5929 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5930 appreciated. In the dystopia described in <citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5931 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5932 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5933 reports.
5934 </para>
5935 <para>
5936 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5937 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5938 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5939 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5940 </para>
5941 <para>
5942 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5943 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5944 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5945 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5946 library&mdash;constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5947 </para>
5948 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'/>
5949 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
5950 <para>
5951 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5952 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5953 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5954 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5955 what others might prefer you forget.<footnote><para>
5956 <!-- f1 -->
5957 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war</primary></indexterm>
5958 <indexterm><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
5959 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases</primary></indexterm>
5960 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5961 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003,
5962 press release stated, <quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.</quote> That was
5963 later changed, without notice, to <quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5964 Have Ended.</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003.
5965 </para></footnote>
5966 </para>
5967 <indexterm><primary>history, records of</primary></indexterm>
5968 <para>
5969 <emphasis role='strong'>We take it</emphasis> for granted that we can
5970 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5971 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5972 race riots in Watts in 1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in 1963,
5973 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5974 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5975 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
5976 remember&mdash;not just what it is convenient to remember, but
5977 remember something close to the truth.
5978 </para>
5979 <para>
5980 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5981 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We <emphasis>all</emphasis>
5982 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5983 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5984 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5985 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5986 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5987 </para>
5988 <para>
5989 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5990 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5991 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5992 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5993 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5994 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5995 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5996 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet&mdash;the
5997 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5998 </para>
5999 <indexterm id='idxkahlebrewster' class='startofrange'><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
6000 <para>
6001 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
6002 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
6003 researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
6004 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
6005 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
6006 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
6007 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10
6008 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
6009 </para>
6010 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
6011 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive</primary></indexterm>
6012 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University</primary></indexterm>
6013 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine</primary></indexterm>
6014 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>archival function of</secondary></indexterm>
6015 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage2' class='startofrange'><primary>news coverage</primary></indexterm>
6016 <para>
6017 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
6018 human history. At the end of 2002, it held <quote>two hundred and thirty
6019 terabytes of material</quote>&mdash;and was <quote>ten times larger than the
6020 Library of Congress.</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
6021 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
6022 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
6023 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
6024 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
6025 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
6026 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University&mdash;thanks to a
6027 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
6028 is available to scholars for a very low fee. <quote>But other than that,
6029 [television] is almost unavailable,</quote> Kahle told me. <quote>If you were
6030 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
6031 just a graduate student?</quote> As Kahle put it,
6032 </para>
6033 <blockquote>
6034 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan</primary></indexterm>
6035 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes</primary></indexterm>
6036 <para>
6037 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
6038 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
6039 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
6040 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
6041 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
6042
6043 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
6044 <citetitle>60 Minutes</citetitle> episode that came out after it &hellip; it would be almost
6045 impossible. &hellip; Those materials are almost unfindable. &hellip;
6046 </para>
6047 </blockquote>
6048 <indexterm><primary>newspapers</primary><secondary>archives of</secondary></indexterm>
6049 <para>
6050 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
6051 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
6052 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
6053 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
6054 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
6055 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
6056 </para>
6057 <para>
6058 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
6059 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
6060 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
6061 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
6062 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
6063 work.
6064 </para>
6065 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
6066 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6067 <para>
6068 These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library
6069 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
6070 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
6071 borrow back the deposits&mdash;for an unlimited time at no cost. In
6072 1915 alone, there were more than 5,475 films deposited and <quote>borrowed
6073 back.</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
6074 held by any library. The copy exists&mdash;if it exists at
6075 all&mdash;in the library archive of the film company.<footnote><para>
6076 <!-- f2 -->
6077 Doug Herrick, <quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
6078 the Library of Congress,</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly</citetitle> 13 nos. 2&ndash;3
6079 (1980): 5; Anthony Slide, <citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
6080 Preservation in the United States</citetitle> (Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland &amp;
6081 Co., 1992), 36.
6082 </para></footnote>
6083 </para>
6084 <para>
6085 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
6086 were originally not copyrighted&mdash;there was no way to capture the
6087 broadcasts, so there was no fear of <quote>theft.</quote> But as technology enabled
6088 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
6089 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
6090 <quote>copyrighted.</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
6091 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
6092 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
6093 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
6094 </para>
6095 <indexterm><primary>September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks of</primary></indexterm>
6096 <para>
6097 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and
6098 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
6099 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
6100 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
6101 September 11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
6102 stations from around the world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made
6103 their coverage during the week of September 11 available free on-line.
6104 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
6105 events of that day.
6106 </para>
6107 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive</primary></indexterm>
6108 <indexterm><primary>archive.org</primary><seealso>Internet Archive</seealso></indexterm>
6109 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage2' class='endofrange'/>
6110 <indexterm><primary>films</primary><secondary>archive of</secondary></indexterm>
6111 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive</primary></indexterm>
6112 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film</primary></indexterm>
6113 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films</primary></indexterm>
6114 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick</primary></indexterm>
6115 <para>
6116 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
6117 archive of film includes close to 45,000 <quote>ephemeral films</quote> (meaning
6118 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
6119 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
6120 1,300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
6121 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
6122 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
6123 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
6124 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
6125 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
6126 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
6127 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
6128 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the <quote>Duck and Cover</quote> film
6129 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
6130 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
6131 few minutes&mdash;for free.
6132 </para>
6133 <para>
6134 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
6135 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
6136 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
6137 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
6138 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
6139 to find them.
6140 </para>
6141 <para>
6142 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
6143 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
6144 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
6145 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
6146 property, but during a second life that all creative property
6147 has&mdash;a noncommercial life.
6148 </para>
6149 <para>
6150 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
6151 of creative property goes through different <quote>lives.</quote> In its first
6152 life, if the
6153
6154 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
6155 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
6156 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
6157 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
6158 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
6159 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
6160 </para>
6161 <para>
6162 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
6163 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
6164 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
6165 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
6166 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
6167 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
6168 longer sold.
6169 </para>
6170 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6171 <para>
6172 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
6173 very quickly (the average today is after about a year<footnote><para>
6174 <!-- f3 -->
6175 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
6176 Dave Barns, <quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
6177 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>,
6178 5 September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927
6179 and 1946, only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese,
6180 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,</quote> <citetitle>Boston
6181 College Law Review</citetitle> 44 (2003): 593 n. 51.
6182 </para></footnote>). After
6183 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
6184 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
6185 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
6186 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
6187 important to the spread and stability of culture.
6188 </para>
6189 <para>
6190 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
6191 creative property does not hold true with the most important
6192 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
6193 centuries. For these&mdash;television, movies, music, radio, the
6194 Internet&mdash;there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
6195 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes &amp;
6196 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
6197 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
6198 disappears.
6199 </para>
6200 <para>
6201 <emphasis role='strong'>For most of</emphasis> the twentieth century,
6202 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
6203 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
6204 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
6205 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
6206 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
6207 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
6208 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
6209 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
6210 little practical effect.
6211 </para>
6212 <para>
6213 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
6214 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
6215 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
6216 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
6217 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
6218 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
6219 </para>
6220 <para>
6221 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
6222 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
6223 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
6224 Kahle describes,
6225 </para>
6226 <blockquote>
6227 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>total number of</secondary></indexterm>
6228 <para>
6229 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
6230 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
6231 movies, &hellip; and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
6232 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
6233 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
6234 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
6235 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
6236 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
6237 &hellip; thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
6238 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
6239 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
6240 </para>
6241 </blockquote>
6242 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
6243 <para>
6244 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
6245 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
6246 libraries or archives could be. <emphasis>When</emphasis> the
6247 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
6248 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
6249 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
6250 will draw upon it to understand it;
6251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
6252 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
6253 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
6254 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past&mdash;a
6255 future <emphasis>for</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
6256 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
6257 </para>
6258 <para>
6259 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
6260 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
6261 call these <quote>archives,</quote> as warm as the idea of a <quote>library</quote> might seem,
6262 the <quote>content</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
6263 someone's <quote>property.</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
6264 that Kahle and others would exercise.
6265 </para>
6266 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'/>
6267 <indexterm startref='idxkahlebrewster' class='endofrange'/>
6268 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
6269 </chapter>
6270 <chapter label="10" id="property-i">
6271 <title>Chapter Ten: <quote>Property</quote></title>
6272 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon</primary></indexterm>
6273 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
6274 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>background of</secondary></indexterm>
6275 <para>
6276 <emphasis role='strong'>Jack Valenti</emphasis> has been the president
6277 of the Motion Picture Association of America since 1966. He first came
6278 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
6279 administration&mdash;literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
6280 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
6281 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
6282 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
6283 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
6284 </para>
6285 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
6286 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment</primary></indexterm>
6287 <indexterm><primary>MGM</primary></indexterm>
6288 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6289 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox</primary></indexterm>
6290 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures</primary></indexterm>
6291 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
6292 <para>
6293 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
6294 Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal
6295 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
6296 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
6297 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
6298 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
6299 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
6300 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
6301 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
6302 Warner Brothers.
6303 </para>
6304 <indexterm id='idxvalentijackbackgroundof' class='startofrange'><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>background of</secondary></indexterm>
6305 <para>
6306 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
6307 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
6308 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
6309 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
6310 political skill of a Southerner&mdash;the ability to appear simple and
6311 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
6312 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
6313 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
6314 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
6315 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
6316 Washingtonian way.
6317 </para>
6318 <para>
6319 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6320 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6321 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6322 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6323 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6324 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6325 redefine the meaning of <quote>creative property.</quote>
6326 </para>
6327 <para>
6328 In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6329 perfectly:
6330 </para>
6331 <blockquote>
6332 <para>
6333 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6334 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6335 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6336 theme which animates this entire debate: <emphasis>Creative property
6337 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6338 other property owners in the nation</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6339 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6340 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.<footnote><para>
6341 <!-- f1 -->
6342 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R.
6343 4794, H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the
6344 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6345 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6346 Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack
6347 Valenti).
6348 </para></footnote>
6349 </para>
6350 </blockquote>
6351 <para>
6352 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6353 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6354 <quote>central theme</quote> to which <quote>reasonable men and women</quote> will return is
6355 this:
6356 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6357 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6358 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.</quote>
6359 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6360 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6361 </para>
6362 <para>
6363 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6364 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6365 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6366 extreme a claim made by <emphasis>anyone</emphasis> who is serious in
6367 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6368 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6369 it comes to the nature and scope of <quote>creative property.</quote> His views
6370 have <emphasis>no</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6371 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6372 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6373 </para>
6374 <indexterm startref='idxvalentijackbackgroundof' class='endofrange'/>
6375 <para>
6376 While <quote>creative property</quote> is certainly <quote>property</quote> in a nerdy and
6377 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,<footnote><para>
6378 <!-- f2 -->
6379 Lawyers speak of <quote>property</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6380 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6381 object. Thus, my <quote>property right</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6382 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For
6383 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of <quote>property</quote> to
6384 <quote>lawyer talk,</quote> see Bruce Ackerman, <citetitle>Private Property and the
6385 Constitution</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 26&ndash;27.
6386 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6387 <quote>creative property owners</quote> have been <quote>accorded the same rights and
6388 protection resident in all other property owners.</quote> Indeed, if creative
6389 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6390 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6391 in our tradition.
6392 </para>
6393 <para>
6394 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6395 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6396 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6397 overturned in 1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6398 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6399 culture would develop.
6400 </para>
6401 <para>
6402 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6403 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6404 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6405 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6406 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6407 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6408 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6409 the same would be to
6410
6411 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6412 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6413 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6414 perfect control.
6415 </para>
6416 <para>
6417 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6418 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6419 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6420 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6421 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6422 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6423 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6424 </para>
6425 <para>
6426 <emphasis role='strong'>To get</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6427 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6428 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6429 </para>
6430 <para>
6431 The framers of our Constitution loved <quote>property.</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6432 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6433 important requirement. If the government takes your property&mdash;if
6434 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6435 farm&mdash;it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's <quote>Takings
6436 Clause,</quote> to pay you <quote>just compensation</quote> for that taking. The
6437 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6438 sacred. It cannot <emphasis>ever</emphasis> be taken from the property
6439 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6440 </para>
6441 <para>
6442 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6443 Valenti calls <quote>creative property.</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6444 power to create <quote>creative property,</quote> the Constitution
6445 <emphasis>requires</emphasis> that after a <quote>limited time,</quote> Congress
6446 take back the rights that it has granted and set the <quote>creative
6447 property</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6448 the expiration of a copyright term <quote>takes</quote> your copyright and turns it
6449 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6450 pay <quote>just compensation</quote> for this <quote>taking.</quote> Instead, the same
6451 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6452 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6453 requires that you lose your <quote>creative property</quote> right without any
6454 compensation at all.
6455 </para>
6456 <para>
6457 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6458 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6459 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6460 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6461 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6462 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6463 itself.
6464 </para>
6465 <indexterm id='idxjeffersonthomas' class='startofrange'><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
6466 <para>
6467 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6468 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6469 The Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6470 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6471 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6472 president (as it did in 1800). The framers were no doubt
6473 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6474 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6475 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6476 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6477 </para>
6478 <para>
6479 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6480 least try to understand <emphasis>why</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6481 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6482 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6483 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6484 domain?
6485 </para>
6486 <indexterm startref='idxjeffersonthomas' class='endofrange'/>
6487
6488 <para>
6489 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6490 history of these <quote>creative property</quote> rights, and the control that they
6491 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6492 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6493 should be at the core of this war: Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis>
6494 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6495 <emphasis>whether</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6496 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6497 ought to be. Not <emphasis>whether</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6498 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6499 also control how culture develops.
6500 </para>
6501 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>four modalities of constraint on</secondary></indexterm>
6502 <indexterm id='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>four modalities of</secondary></indexterm>
6503 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as ex post regulation modality</secondary></indexterm>
6504 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6505 <para>
6506
6507 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6508 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6509 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6510 than the narrow language of the law allows. In <citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6511 Cyberspace</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6512 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6513 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6514 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6515 </para>
6516 <figure id="fig-1331">
6517 <title></title>
6518 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6519 </figure>
6520 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6521 <para>
6522 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6523 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6524 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6525 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6526 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6527 be regulated&mdash; either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6528 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6529 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6530 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6531 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6532 Web, you can be punished
6533 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6534 with a $150,000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6535 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6536 <indexterm><primary>Madonna</primary></indexterm>
6537 </para>
6538 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6539 <para>
6540 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6541 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6542 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6543 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6544 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6545 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6546 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6547 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6548 the source of the enforcement.
6549 </para>
6550 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6551 <para>
6552 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6553 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6554 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6555 norms&mdash;it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6556 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6557 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6558 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6559 individual or group might behave.
6560 </para>
6561 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6562 <para>
6563 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6564 <quote>architecture</quote>&mdash;the physical world as one finds it&mdash;is a
6565 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6566 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6567 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6568 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6569 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6570 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6571 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6572 theft, but by nature, by <quote>architecture.</quote> If a 500-pound boulder
6573 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6574 constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6575 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6576 </para>
6577 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6578 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='endofrange'/>
6579 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints' class='endofrange'/>
6580 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6581 <para>
6582
6583 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6584 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6585 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6586 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6587 undermined by another.
6588 </para>
6589 <para>
6590 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6591 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6592 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6593 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6594 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6595 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6596 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6597 </para>
6598 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6599 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6600 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6601 <indexterm id='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>driving speed, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6602 <indexterm id='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='startofrange'><primary>speeding, constraints on</primary></indexterm>
6603 <para>
6604 So, for example, consider the <quote>freedom</quote> to drive a car at a high
6605 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6606 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6607 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6608 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6609 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6610 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6611 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6612 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6613 the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own
6614 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6615 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6616 </para>
6617 <para>
6618 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6619 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6620 special role in affecting the three.<footnote><para>
6621 <!-- f3 -->
6622 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6623 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6624 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6625 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6626 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, <citetitle>Code: And
6627 Other Laws of Cyberspace</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90&ndash;95;
6628 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>The New Chicago School,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies</citetitle>,
6629 June 1998.
6630 </para></footnote>
6631 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6632 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6633 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6634 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6635 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6636 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6637 used to require that other laws be more
6638 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6639 strict&mdash;a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6640 limit, for example&mdash;so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6641 driving.
6642 </para>
6643 <indexterm startref='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6644 <indexterm startref='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='endofrange'/>
6645 <figure id="fig-1361">
6646 <title></title>
6647 <graphic fileref="images/1361.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6648
6649 </figure>
6650 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6651 <para>
6652 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6653 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6654 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6655 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6656 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6657 another.<footnote>
6658 <para>
6659 <!-- f4 -->
6660 Some people object to this way of talking about <quote>liberty.</quote> They object
6661 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6662 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6663 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6664 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6665 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6666 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6667 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6668 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6669 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6670 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6671 of liberty. As I argued in <citetitle>Code</citetitle>, we come from a
6672 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6673 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6674 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6675 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6676 <citetitle>On Liberty</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6677 1978), 19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6678 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, <quote>The
6679 Right to Work,</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6680 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays</citetitle> (London:
6681 Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6682 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6683 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6684 places easier; 42 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
6685 12101 (2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6686 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6687 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6688 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6689 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (1990)</primary></indexterm>
6690 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.</primary></indexterm>
6691 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6692 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6693 </para></footnote>
6694 </para>
6695 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='endofrange'/>
6696 <section id="hollywood">
6697 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right</title>
6698 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
6699 <para>
6700 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6701 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6702 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6703 rallying makes sense.
6704 </para>
6705 <para>
6706 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6707 Internet:
6708 </para>
6709 <figure id="fig-1371">
6710 <title></title>
6711 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6712
6713 </figure>
6714 <indexterm id='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='startofrange'><primary>architecture, constraint effected through</primary></indexterm>
6715 <indexterm><primary>law</primary><secondary>as constraint modality</secondary></indexterm>
6716 <indexterm id='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='startofrange'><primary>norms, regulatory influence of</primary></indexterm>
6717 <para>
6718 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6719 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6720 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6721 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6722 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6723 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6724 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6725 recognize&mdash;kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6726 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6727 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6728 this form of infringement.
6729 </para>
6730 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright regulatory balance lost with</secondary></indexterm>
6731 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>regulatory balance lost in</secondary></indexterm>
6732 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
6733 <indexterm><primary>MP3s</primary></indexterm>
6734 <para>
6735 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6736 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6737 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6738 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6739 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6740 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6741 </para>
6742 <indexterm startref='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='endofrange'/>
6743 <indexterm startref='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='endofrange'/>
6744 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>established industries threatened by changes in</secondary></indexterm>
6745 <para>
6746 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6747 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6748 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6749 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6750 Iraq
6751 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6752 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6753 looting that results.
6754 </para>
6755 <figure id="fig-1381">
6756 <title></title>
6757 <graphic fileref="images/1381.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
6758
6759 </figure>
6760 <indexterm><primary>Commerce, U.S. Department of</primary></indexterm>
6761 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
6762 <para>
6763 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6764 warriors. Indeed, in a <quote>White Paper</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6765 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995,
6766 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6767 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6768 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should
6769 strengthen intellectual property law, (2) businesses should adopt
6770 innovative marketing techniques, (3) technologists should push to
6771 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (4) educators should
6772 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6773 </para>
6774 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='endofrange'/>
6775 <indexterm startref='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='endofrange'/>
6776 <indexterm><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6777 <indexterm><primary>steel industry</primary></indexterm>
6778 <para>
6779 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed&mdash;if it was to
6780 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6781 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6782 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6783 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6784 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6785 life. Homeowners living in a
6786
6787 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6788 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6789 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6790 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6791 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6792 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6793 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6794 </para>
6795 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='endofrange'/>
6796 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='endofrange'/>
6797 <indexterm><primary>Brown, John Seely</primary></indexterm>
6798 <para>
6799 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6800 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6801 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6802 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6803 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6804 Brown describes it, its <quote>architecture of revenue.</quote>
6805 </para>
6806 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
6807 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
6808 <indexterm><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
6809 <indexterm><primary>camera technology</primary></indexterm>
6810 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras</primary></indexterm>
6811 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras</primary></indexterm>
6812 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry</primary></indexterm>
6813 <indexterm><primary>remote channel changers</primary></indexterm>
6814 <para>
6815 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6816 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6817 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6818 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6819 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20
6820 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6821 of digital cameras.<footnote><para>
6822 <!-- f5 -->
6823 See Geoffrey Smith, <quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?</quote>
6824 BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at
6825 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #23</ulink>. For a more
6826 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6827 R. Schoenberger, <quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?</quote> Forbes.com, 6
6828 October 2003, available at
6829 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #24</ulink>.
6830 </para></footnote>
6831
6832 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6833 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6834 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6835 <emphasis>for the purpose of</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6836 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6837 weakened the <quote>stickiness</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6838 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf), and it
6839 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6840 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6841 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6842 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6843 </para>
6844 <indexterm id='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='startofrange'><primary>free market, technological changes in</primary></indexterm>
6845 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
6846 <indexterm><primary>FM radio</primary></indexterm>
6847 <indexterm><primary>radio</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of</secondary></indexterm>
6848 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
6849 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
6850 <indexterm><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
6851 <para>
6852 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6853 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6854 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6855 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6856 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6857 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6858 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6859 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents, <quote>established companies
6860 have an interest in excluding future competitors.</quote><footnote><para>
6861 <!-- f6 -->
6862 Fred Warshofsky, <citetitle>The Patent Wars</citetitle> (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170&ndash;71.
6863 </para></footnote>
6864 And relative to a
6865 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6866 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6867 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6868 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6869 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6870 Brezhnev.
6871 </para>
6872 <para>
6873 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6874 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6875 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6876 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6877 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6878 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6879 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6880 opportunities for innovation and change.
6881 </para>
6882 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
6883 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
6884 <indexterm><primary>speech, freedom of</primary><secondary>constitutional guarantee of</secondary></indexterm>
6885 <para>
6886 In the context of laws regulating speech&mdash;which include,
6887 obviously, copyright law&mdash;that duty is even stronger. When the
6888 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6889 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6890 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6891 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6892 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6893 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution: <quote>Congress
6894 shall make no law &hellip; abridging the freedom of speech.</quote> So when
6895 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would <quote>abridge</quote> the freedom
6896 of speech, it should ask&mdash; carefully&mdash;whether such
6897 regulation is justified.
6898 </para>
6899 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='endofrange'/>
6900 <indexterm startref='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='endofrange'/>
6901 <para>
6902 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6903 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6904 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6905 <quote>justified.</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6906 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6907 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6908 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6909 </para>
6910 <para>
6911 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6912 </para>
6913 <indexterm id='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='startofrange'><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann</primary></indexterm>
6914 <indexterm id='idxddt' class='startofrange'><primary>DDT</primary></indexterm>
6915 <indexterm id='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='startofrange'><primary>insecticide, environmental consequences of</primary></indexterm>
6916 <indexterm id='idxfarming' class='startofrange'><primary>farming</primary></indexterm>
6917 <para>
6918 In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss
6919 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6920 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the
6921 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6922 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6923 </para>
6924 <para>
6925 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6926 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6927 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6928 </para>
6929 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel</primary></indexterm>
6930 <indexterm><primary>Silent Spring (Carson)</primary></indexterm>
6931 <indexterm id='idxenvironmentalism' class='startofrange'><primary>environmentalism</primary></indexterm>
6932 <para>
6933 But in 1962, Rachel Carson published <citetitle>Silent Spring</citetitle>, which argued that
6934 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6935 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6936 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6937 </para>
6938 <para>
6939 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6940 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6941 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6942 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6943 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6944 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6945 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6946 </para>
6947 <indexterm startref='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='endofrange'/>
6948 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James</primary></indexterm>
6949 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovative freedom balanced with fair compensation in</secondary></indexterm>
6950 <para>
6951 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6952 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an <quote>environmentalism</quote> for
6953 culture.<footnote><para>
6954 <!-- f7 -->
6955 See, for example, James Boyle, <quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6956 Environmentalism for the Net?</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal</citetitle> 47 (1997): 87.
6957 </para></footnote>
6958 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6959 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6960 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6961 <quote>for free.</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6962 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6963 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6964 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6965 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6966 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6967 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6968 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6969 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6970 </para>
6971 <indexterm startref='idxfarming' class='endofrange'/>
6972 <para>
6973 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6974 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6975 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6976 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6977 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6978 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6979 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6980 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6981 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6982 </para>
6983 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='endofrange'/>
6984 <para>
6985 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6986 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6987 be lost.
6988 </para>
6989 <indexterm startref='idxddt' class='endofrange'/>
6990 <indexterm startref='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='endofrange'/>
6991 <indexterm startref='idxenvironmentalism' class='endofrange'/>
6992 </section>
6993 <section id="beginnings">
6994 <title>Beginnings</title>
6995 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>on creative property</secondary></indexterm>
6996 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
6997 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
6998 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
6999 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7000 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>constitutional tradition on</secondary></indexterm>
7001 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
7002 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7003 <para>
7004 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
7005 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of <quote>creative
7006 property</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
7007 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
7008 </para>
7009 <indexterm id='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>in constitutional Progress Clause</secondary></indexterm>
7010 <para>
7011 The power to establish <quote>creative property</quote> rights is granted to
7012 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
7013 odd. Article I, section 8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that:
7014 </para>
7015 <para>
7016 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
7017 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
7018 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
7019
7020 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
7021 We can call this the <quote>Progress Clause,</quote> for notice what this clause
7022 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
7023 <quote>creative property rights.</quote> It says that Congress has the power
7024 <emphasis>to promote progress</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
7025 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
7026 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
7027 </para>
7028 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7029 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>as protection of creators</secondary></indexterm>
7030 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>history of American</secondary></indexterm>
7031 <para>
7032 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
7033 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="founders"/>,
7034 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
7035 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
7036 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
7037 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
7038 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
7039 copyrights extend <quote>to Authors</quote> only.
7040 </para>
7041 <indexterm><primary>Senate, U.S.</primary></indexterm>
7042 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>structural checks and balances of</secondary></indexterm>
7043 <indexterm><primary>electoral college</primary></indexterm>
7044 <para>
7045 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
7046 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
7047 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
7048 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
7049 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
7050 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
7051 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
7052 to reinforce the power of the states&mdash;including the Senate, whose
7053 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
7054 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
7055 case, a <emphasis>structure</emphasis> built checks and balances into
7056 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
7057 concentrations of power.
7058 </para>
7059 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='endofrange'/>
7060 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause' class='endofrange'/>
7061 <para>
7062 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call <quote>copyright</quote>
7063 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
7064 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
7065 <quote>copyright</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210
7066 years since they first struck its design.
7067 </para>
7068 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='endofrange'/>
7069 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='endofrange'/>
7070 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='endofrange'/>
7071 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on</secondary></indexterm>
7072 <para>
7073 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
7074 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
7075 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
7076 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
7077 started here:
7078 </para>
7079 <figure id="fig-1441">
7080 <title></title>
7081 <graphic fileref="images/1331.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7082 </figure>
7083 <para>
7084 We will end here:
7085 </para>
7086 <figure id="fig-1442">
7087 <title></title>
7088 <graphic fileref="images/1442.svg" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7089 </figure>
7090 <para>
7091 Let me explain how.
7092 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
7093 </para>
7094 </section>
7095 <section id="lawduration">
7096 <title>Law: Duration</title>
7097 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
7098 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7099 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7100 <indexterm><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>common law protections of</secondary></indexterm>
7101 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>balance of U.S. content in</secondary></indexterm>
7102 <para>
7103 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
7104 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
7105 the English had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws
7106 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
7107 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
7108 authorship.<footnote>
7109 <para>
7110 <!-- f8 -->
7111 William W. Crosskey, <citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
7112 the United States</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1,
7113 485&ndash;86: <quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
7114 Law of the Land,' <emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
7115 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law</emphasis></quote>
7116 (emphasis added).
7117 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.</primary></indexterm>
7118 </para></footnote>
7119 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
7120 States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
7121 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
7122 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
7123 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
7124 domain to reprint and distribute works.
7125 </para>
7126 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (1710)</primary></indexterm>
7127 <indexterm id='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>federal vs. state</secondary></indexterm>
7128 <para>
7129 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
7130 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
7131 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
7132 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
7133 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
7134 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
7135 </para>
7136 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>renewability of</secondary></indexterm>
7137 <para>
7138 In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
7139 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
7140 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
7141 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
7142 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
7143 </para>
7144 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='endofrange'/>
7145 <para>
7146 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
7147 ten years of the Republic, only 5 percent of the works were actually
7148 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
7149 in the United States both before 1790 and from 1790 through 1800, 95
7150 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
7151 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
7152 likely within fourteen years.<footnote><para>
7153 <!-- f9 -->
7154 Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790
7155 to 1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, <citetitle>A
7156 History of Book Publishing in the United States</citetitle>, vol. 1, <citetitle>The Creation
7157 of an Industry, 1630&ndash;1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000
7158 imprints recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
7159 1790 act; William J. Maher, <citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
7160 and the Copyright Law of 1790 in Historical Context</citetitle>, 7&ndash;10 (2002),
7161 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
7162 #25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
7163 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
7164 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
7165 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
7166 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
7167 Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124. </para></footnote>
7168 </para>
7169 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact' class='endofrange'/>
7170 <indexterm startref='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='endofrange'/>
7171 <para>
7172 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
7173 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
7174 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
7175 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
7176 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
7177 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
7178 copyright, either.
7179 </para>
7180 <para>
7181 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
7182 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
7183 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
7184 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
7185 domain.<footnote><para>
7186 <!-- f10 -->
7187 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
7188 instance, of the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were
7189 renewed in 1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
7190 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, <quote>Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright,</quote>
7191 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright</citetitle>, vol. 1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
7192 1963), 618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
7193 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote>
7194 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review</citetitle> 70 (2003): 471, 498&ndash;501, and
7195 accompanying figures. </para></footnote>
7196 </para>
7197 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='endofrange'/>
7198 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
7199 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
7200 <para>
7201 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
7202 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
7203 out of print after one year.<footnote><para>
7204 <!-- f11 -->
7205 See Ringer, ch. 9, n. 2. </para></footnote> When that happens, the
7206 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
7207 no longer <emphasis>effectively</emphasis> controlled by
7208 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
7209 is to sell the books as used books; that use&mdash;because it does not
7210 involve publication&mdash;is effectively free.
7211 </para>
7212 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
7213 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
7214 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
7215 <para>
7216 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
7217 changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28
7218 years to a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
7219 from 14 years to 28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
7220 the term increased once again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal
7221 term of 14 years to 28 years, setting a maximum term of 56 years.
7222 </para>
7223 <indexterm><primary>CTEA</primary><seealso>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</seealso></indexterm>
7224 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7225 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
7226 <para>
7227 Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
7228 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
7229 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
7230 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
7231 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
7232 In 1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
7233 And in 1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
7234 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
7235 </para>
7236 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
7237 <para>
7238 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
7239 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
7240 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
7241 years, or 70 percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years
7242
7243 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
7244 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
7245 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
7246 of the expiration of a copyright term.
7247 </para>
7248 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='endofrange'/>
7249 <para>
7250 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
7251 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
7252 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
7253 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
7254 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
7255 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
7256 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
7257 value.
7258 </para>
7259 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
7260 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>of natural authors vs. corporations</secondary></indexterm>
7261 <indexterm><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>copyright terms for</secondary></indexterm>
7262 <para>
7263 The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For
7264 all works created after 1978, there was only one copyright term&mdash;the
7265 maximum term. For <quote>natural</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
7266 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992,
7267 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
7268 before 1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
7269 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
7270 was ninety-five years.
7271 </para>
7272 <para>
7273 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
7274 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
7275 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
7276 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
7277 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
7278 that terms be <quote>limited,</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
7279 them.
7280 </para>
7281 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='endofrange'/>
7282 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
7283 <para>
7284 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
7285 dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to
7286 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
7287 in 1973 was just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
7288 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
7289 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95
7290 years.<footnote><para>
7291 <!-- f12 -->
7292 These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the
7293 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
7294 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
7295 Posner, <quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,</quote> loc. cit.
7296 </para></footnote>
7297 </para>
7298 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='endofrange'/>
7299 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='endofrange'/>
7300 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='endofrange'/>
7301 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='endofrange'/>
7302 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='endofrange'/>
7303 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
7304 </section>
7305 <section id="lawscope">
7306 <title>Law: Scope</title>
7307 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7308 <para>
7309 The <quote>scope</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
7310 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
7311 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
7312 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
7313 </para>
7314 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7315 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>historical shift in copyright coverage of</secondary></indexterm>
7316 <para>
7317 In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only <quote>maps,
7318 charts, and books.</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
7319 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
7320 the author the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> copyrighted works. That
7321 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
7322 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
7323 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
7324 did not extend to what lawyers call <quote>derivative works.</quote> It would not,
7325 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
7326 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
7327 (such as a drama based on a published book).
7328 </para>
7329 <para>
7330 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
7331 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
7332 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
7333 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
7334 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
7335 work not only the exclusive right to <quote>publish</quote> the work, but also the
7336 exclusive right of control over any <quote>copies</quote> of that work. And most
7337 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
7338 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
7339 <quote>derivative work</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
7340 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
7341 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
7342 on the initial creative work.
7343 </para>
7344 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>marking of</secondary></indexterm>
7345 <indexterm id='idxformalities' class='startofrange'><primary>formalities</primary></indexterm>
7346 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>registration requirement of</secondary></indexterm>
7347 <para>
7348 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
7349 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
7350 complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition
7351 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
7352 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
7353 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
7354 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
7355 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
7356 famous &copy; or the word <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>. And for most
7357 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
7358 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
7359 secured.
7360 </para>
7361 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='endofrange'/>
7362 <para>
7363 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
7364 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
7365 in the first ten years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible
7366 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
7367 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
7368 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
7369 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
7370 copyrighted&mdash;that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
7371 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
7372 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
7373 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
7374 original author.
7375 </para>
7376 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>European</secondary></indexterm>
7377 <para>
7378 All of these <quote>formalities</quote> were abolished in the American system when
7379 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
7380 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
7381 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
7382 a &copy;; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
7383 copy available for others to copy.
7384 </para>
7385 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='endofrange'/>
7386 <indexterm startref='idxformalities' class='endofrange'/>
7387 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='endofrange'/>
7388 <para>
7389 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
7390 differences.
7391 </para>
7392 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact2' class='startofrange'><primary>Copyright Act (1790)</primary></indexterm>
7393 <para>
7394 If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who
7395 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
7396 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
7397 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
7398 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were
7399 174 publishers in the United States.<footnote><para>
7400 <!-- f13 -->
7401 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, <quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
7402 Creation of American Literature,</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
7403 International Law and Politics</citetitle> 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
7404 Federal Copyright Records, 1790&ndash;1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987).
7405
7406 </para></footnote>
7407 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
7408 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
7409 the United States&mdash;publishers.
7410 </para>
7411 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7412 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7413 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7414 <para>
7415 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
7416 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
7417 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
7418 was totally unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made
7419 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
7420 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
7421 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
7422 were restrained.
7423 </para>
7424 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact2' class='endofrange'/>
7425 <para>
7426 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
7427 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
7428 every note to your spouse, every doodle, <emphasis>every</emphasis>
7429 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form&mdash;all of this is
7430 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
7431 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
7432 protect it.
7433 </para>
7434 <para>
7435 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
7436 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
7437 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
7438 </para>
7439 <para>
7440 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
7441 control
7442 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
7443 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of <quote>derivative
7444 rights.</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
7445 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7446 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7447 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7448 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7449 exclusive
7450 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7451 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7452 </para>
7453 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7454 <para>
7455 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7456 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7457 expansion
7458 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7459 copyright.
7460 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7461 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7462 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7463 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7464 </para>
7465 <para>
7466 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7467 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7468 within a free culture&mdash;at least, it's astonishing when you
7469 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7470 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7471 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7472 <emphasis>that</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7473 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7474 all&mdash;they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7475 not protect derivative rights at all.<footnote><para>
7476 <!-- f14 -->
7477 Jonathan Zittrain, <quote>The Copyright Cage,</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7478 Affairs</citetitle>, July/August 2003, available at
7479 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #26</ulink>.
7480 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
7481 </para></footnote>
7482 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7483 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7484 the wrong of direct piracy.
7485 </para>
7486 <para>
7487 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7488 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7489 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7490 of my book.<footnote><para>
7491 <!-- f15 -->
7492 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7493 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7494 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere <quote>copies</quote> and
7495 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld, <quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7496 Copyright's Constitutionality,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7497 Journal</citetitle> 112 (2002): 1&ndash;60 (see especially
7498 pp. 53&ndash;59).
7499 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb</primary></indexterm>
7500 </para></footnote>
7501 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7502 </para>
7503 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='endofrange'/>
7504 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
7505 <indexterm><primary>Mickey Mouse</primary></indexterm>
7506 <para>
7507 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7508 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7509 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7510 called <quote>Mickey Mouse,</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7511 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7512 created?
7513 </para>
7514 <para>
7515 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7516 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7517 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7518 the rights originally granted.
7519 </para>
7520 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7521 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='endofrange'/>
7522 </section>
7523 <section id="lawreach">
7524 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach</title>
7525 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7526 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>scope of</secondary></indexterm>
7527 <para>
7528 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7529 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7530 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7531 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.<footnote><para>
7532 <!-- f16 -->
7533 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7534 certainly regulates more than <quote>copies</quote>&mdash;a public performance of a
7535 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7536 per se doesn't make a copy; 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7537 106(4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a <quote>copy</quote>; 17
7538 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section 112(a). But the presumption under the
7539 existing law (which regulates <quote>copies;</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code</citetitle>, section
7540 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7541 </para></footnote>
7542 </para>
7543 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack</primary><secondary>on creative property rights</secondary></indexterm>
7544 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='startofrange'><primary>creative property</primary><secondary>other property rights vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7545 <para>
7546 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7547 <quote>Copies.</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7548 <emphasis>copy</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7549 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that <quote>creative
7550 property</quote> deserves the <quote>same rights</quote> as all other property, it is the
7551 <emphasis>obvious</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7552 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7553 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7554 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7555 copies should <emphasis>not</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7556 law. More precisely, they should not <emphasis>always</emphasis> be
7557 the trigger for copyright law.
7558 </para>
7559 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='endofrange'/>
7560 <para>
7561 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7562 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7563 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7564 the law of copyright automatically applies,<footnote><para>
7565 <!-- f17 -->
7566 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7567 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7568 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7569 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7570 technology.
7571 </para></footnote>
7572 because it is clear that the
7573 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7574 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7575 </para>
7576 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='endofrange'/>
7577 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='endofrange'/>
7578 <para>
7579 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7580 empty circle.
7581 </para>
7582 <figure id="fig-1521">
7583 <title></title>
7584 <graphic fileref="images/1521.svg" align="center" width="40%"></graphic>
7585 </figure>
7586 <indexterm id='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>three types of uses of</secondary></indexterm>
7587 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7588 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>copyright applicability altered by technology of</secondary></indexterm>
7589 <indexterm id='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='startofrange'><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright intent altered by</secondary></indexterm>
7590 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>piracy vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7591 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='startofrange'><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7592 <para>
7593 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7594 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7595 all its potential <emphasis>uses</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7596 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7597 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7598 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7599 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7600 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7601 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7602 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7603 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7604 acts do not make a copy.
7605 </para>
7606 <figure id="fig-1531">
7607 <title></title>
7608 <graphic fileref="images/1531.png" align="center" width="40%"></graphic>
7609 </figure>
7610 <para>
7611 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7612 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7613 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7614 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7615 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see
7616 diagram in figure <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-1541"/>).
7617 </para>
7618 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7619 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='endofrange'/>
7620 <figure id="fig-1541">
7621 <title></title>
7622 <graphic fileref="images/1541.svg" align="center" width="40%"></graphic>
7623 </figure>
7624 <indexterm id='idxfairuse' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary></indexterm>
7625 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7626 <para>
7627 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7628 that remain unregulated because the law considers these <quote>fair uses.</quote>
7629 </para>
7630 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7631 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
7632 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
7633 <para>
7634 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7635 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7636 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7637 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7638 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7639 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7640 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such <quote>fair uses</quote>
7641 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7642 </para>
7643 <figure id="fig-1542">
7644 <title></title>
7645 <graphic fileref="images/1542.svg" align="center" width="40%"></graphic>
7646 </figure>
7647 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7648 <para>
7649 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7650 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7651 sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that
7652 are nonetheless deemed <quote>fair</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7653 </para>
7654 <indexterm startref='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='endofrange'/>
7655 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7656 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>books on</secondary></indexterm>
7657 <indexterm><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7658 <para>
7659 Enter the Internet&mdash;a distributed, digital network where every use
7660 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.<footnote><para>
7661 <!-- f18 -->
7662 I don't mean <quote>nature</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7663 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7664 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7665 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7666 of copies remain.
7667 </para></footnote>
7668 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7669 digital network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses
7670 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7671 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7672 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7673 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7674 a copy&mdash;category 1 gets sucked into category 2. And those who
7675 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7676 exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7677 shift.
7678 </para>
7679 <indexterm startref='idxfairuse' class='endofrange'/>
7680 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='endofrange'/>
7681 <para>
7682 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7683 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7684 be no plausible <emphasis>copyright</emphasis>-related argument that
7685 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7686 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7687 the book once, ten times, or every
7688 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7689 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7690 use&mdash;reading&mdash; could be regulated by copyright law because
7691 none of those uses produced a copy.
7692 </para>
7693 <indexterm id='idxebooks' class='startofrange'><primary>e-books</primary></indexterm>
7694 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>technological developments and</secondary></indexterm>
7695 <para>
7696 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7697 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7698 only once or only once a month, then <emphasis>copyright
7699 law</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7700 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7701 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7702 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7703 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7704 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7705 copyright owner's wish.
7706 </para>
7707 <figure id="fig-1551">
7708 <title></title>
7709 <graphic fileref="images/1551.svg" align="center" width="40%"></graphic>
7710 </figure>
7711 <para>
7712 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7713 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7714 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7715 points also become clear:
7716 </para>
7717 <para>
7718 First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7719 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7720 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7721 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7722 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7723 part of free culture before the Internet.
7724 </para>
7725 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work</secondary></indexterm>
7726 <para>
7727 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7728 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7729 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7730 <emphasis>any</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7731 using a machine. <quote>Copy and paste</quote> and <quote>cut and paste</quote> become
7732 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7733 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7734 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7735 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7736 creative work.
7737 </para>
7738 <indexterm id='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on</secondary></indexterm>
7739 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7740 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='startofrange'><primary>derivative works</primary><secondary>fair use vs.</secondary></indexterm>
7741 <para>
7742 Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary
7743
7744 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7745 burden on category 3 (<quote>fair use</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7746 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7747 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7748 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7749 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7750 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7751 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7752 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7753 regulated.
7754 </para>
7755 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='endofrange'/>
7756 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='endofrange'/>
7757 <indexterm startref='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='endofrange'/>
7758 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='endofrange'/>
7759 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='endofrange'/>
7760 <para>
7761 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7762 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7763 depend upon fair use&mdash;never even addressing the earlier question
7764 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7765 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7766 <emphasis>unregulated</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7767 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7768 enough.
7769 </para>
7770 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='endofrange'/>
7771 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'/>
7772 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson2' class='endofrange'/>
7773 <indexterm startref='idxebooks' class='endofrange'/>
7774 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='endofrange'/>
7775 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='endofrange'/>
7776 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='endofrange'/>
7777 <indexterm id='idxvideopipeline' class='startofrange'><primary>Video Pipeline</primary></indexterm>
7778 <indexterm id='idxadvertising' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
7779 <indexterm id='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='startofrange'><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>trailer advertisements of</secondary></indexterm>
7780 <para>
7781 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7782 in the business of making <quote>trailer</quote> advertisements for movies available
7783 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7784 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7785 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7786 </para>
7787 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7788 <para>
7789 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began
7790 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7791 previews. The idea was to expand their <quote>selling by sampling</quote>
7792 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7793 <quote>browsing.</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7794 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7795 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7796 </para>
7797 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc2' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Inc.</primary></indexterm>
7798 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>fair use and</secondary></indexterm>
7799 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of</secondary></indexterm>
7800 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='startofrange'><primary>fair use</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against</secondary></indexterm>
7801 <para>
7802 In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7803 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7804 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7805 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7806 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7807 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter&mdash;he had built a
7808 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7809 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7810 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7811 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7812 <quote>fair use</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7813 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7814 their rights.
7815 </para>
7816 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising' class='endofrange'/>
7817 <indexterm startref='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='endofrange'/>
7818 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to</secondary></indexterm>
7819 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>willful infringement findings in</secondary></indexterm>
7820 <indexterm><primary>willful infringement</primary></indexterm>
7821 <para>
7822 Disney countersued&mdash;for $100 million in damages. Those damages
7823 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had <quote>willfully
7824 infringed</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7825 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7826 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7827 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7828 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7829 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $100 million.
7830 </para>
7831 <para>
7832 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7833 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7834 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7835 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7836 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7837 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7838 Disney's permission.
7839 </para>
7840 <indexterm><primary>first-sale doctrine</primary></indexterm>
7841 <para>
7842 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7843 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7844 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7845 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7846 was in the marketplace, the <quote>first-sale doctrine</quote> would free the
7847 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7848 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7849 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7850 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7851 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7852 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7853 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7854 </para>
7855 <indexterm startref='idxvideopipeline' class='endofrange'/>
7856 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc2' class='endofrange'/>
7857 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='endofrange'/>
7858 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='endofrange'/>
7859 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='endofrange'/>
7860 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='endofrange'/>
7861 <indexterm><primary>Barnes &amp; Noble</primary></indexterm>
7862 <indexterm><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
7863 <indexterm><primary>market competition</primary></indexterm>
7864 <para>
7865 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7866 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7867 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes &amp; Noble has the
7868 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7869 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7870 abuse. If Barnes &amp; Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7871 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7872 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7873 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7874 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7875 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7876 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7877 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7878 happening are quite slight.
7879 </para>
7880 <para>
7881 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7882 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7883 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7884 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7885 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7886 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7887 </para>
7888 </section>
7889 <section id="lawforce">
7890 <title>Architecture and Law: Force</title>
7891 <para>
7892 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7893 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7894 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7895 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7896 </para>
7897 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>technology as automatic enforcer of</secondary></indexterm>
7898 <indexterm><primary>technology</primary><secondary>copyright enforcement controlled by</secondary></indexterm>
7899 <para>
7900 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7901 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7902 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7903 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7904 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7905 your freedom.
7906 </para>
7907 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca</primary></indexterm>
7908 <indexterm id='idxmarxbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7909 <indexterm id='idxwarnerbrothers' class='startofrange'><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
7910 <para>
7911 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7912 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7913 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7914 <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7915 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7916 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7917 plan.<footnote><para>
7918 <!-- f19 -->
7919 See David Lange, <quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7920 Contemporary Problems</citetitle> 44 (1981): 172&ndash;73.
7921 </para></footnote>
7922 </para>
7923 <para>
7924 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7925 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers <quote>were brothers long before
7926 you were.</quote><footnote><para>
7927 <!-- f20 -->
7928 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
7929 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan, <citetitle>Copyrights and
7930 Copywrongs</citetitle>, 1&ndash;3.
7931 </para></footnote>
7932 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7933 <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7934 trying to control <citetitle>Casablanca</citetitle>, then the Marx
7935 Brothers would insist on control over <citetitle>brothers</citetitle>.
7936 </para>
7937 <para>
7938 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7939 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7940 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7941 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7942 </para>
7943 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
7944 <para>
7945 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7946 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7947 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7948 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7949 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7950 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7951 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7952 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7953 </para>
7954 <indexterm startref='idxwarnerbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7955 <indexterm startref='idxmarxbrothers' class='endofrange'/>
7956
7957 <indexterm id='idxadobeebookreader' class='startofrange'><primary>Adobe eBook Reader</primary></indexterm>
7958 <para>
7959 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7960 </para>
7961 <para>
7962 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7963 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7964 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7965 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7966 technology.
7967 </para>
7968 <figure id="fig-example-adobe-ebook-reader" float="1">
7969 <title></title>
7970 <graphic fileref="images/example-adobe-ebook-reader.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7971 </figure>
7972 <para>
7973 In figure
7974 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-example-adobe-ebook-reader"/>
7975 is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7976 </para>
7977 <para>
7978 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7979 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7980 public domain: <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, for example, is in
7981 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7982 public domain: My own book <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>
7983 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7984 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7985 copy of
7986 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7987 <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7988 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7989 </para>
7990 <para>
7991 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7992 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7993 </para>
7994 <figure id="fig-1612">
7995 <title></title>
7996 <graphic fileref="images/1612.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
7997 </figure>
7998 <para>
7999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
8000 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
8001 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
8002 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
8003 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
8004 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle>
8005 read aloud through the computer.
8006 </para>
8007 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle</primary></indexterm>
8008 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics</citetitle>, (Aristotle)</primary></indexterm>
8009 <para>
8010 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
8011 translation): Aristotle's <citetitle>Politics</citetitle>.
8012 </para>
8013 <figure id="fig-1621">
8014 <title></title>
8015 <graphic fileref="images/aristotele-ebook.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8016 </figure>
8017 <para>
8018 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
8019 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
8020 the book.
8021 </para>
8022 <figure id="fig-1622">
8023 <title></title>
8024 <graphic fileref="images/1622.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8025 </figure>
8026 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
8027 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
8028 <para>
8029 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
8030 original e-book version of my last book, <citetitle>The Future of
8031 Ideas</citetitle>:
8032 </para>
8033 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
8034 <figure id="fig-1631">
8035 <title></title>
8036 <graphic fileref="images/1631.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8037 </figure>
8038 <para>
8039 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
8040 </para>
8041 <para>
8042 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
8043 <quote>permissions</quote>&mdash; as if the publisher has the power to control how
8044 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
8045 certainly does have the power&mdash;up to the limits of the copyright
8046 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
8047 power.<footnote><para>
8048 <!-- f21 -->
8049 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
8050 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
8051 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
8052 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
8053 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
8054 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
8055 subsequently acquired the book.
8056 </para></footnote>
8057 When my e-book of <citetitle>Middlemarch</citetitle> says I have the
8058 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
8059 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
8060 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
8061 control that the law would enable.
8062 </para>
8063 <para>
8064 The control comes instead from the code&mdash;from the technology
8065 within which the e-book <quote>lives.</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
8066 permissions, they are not the sort of <quote>permissions</quote> that most of us
8067 deal with. When a teenager gets <quote>permission</quote> to stay out till
8068 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
8069 till 2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
8070 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
8071 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
8072 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
8073 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
8074 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
8075 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
8076 aloud&mdash;it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
8077 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
8078 won't read aloud.
8079 </para>
8080 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8081 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers</primary></indexterm>
8082 <para>
8083 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
8084 These are <emphasis>controls</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
8085 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
8086 you tried to type <quote>Warner Brothers,</quote> erased <quote>Brothers</quote> from the
8087 sentence.
8088 </para>
8089 <para>
8090 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
8091 <emphasis>law</emphasis> as copyright <emphasis>code</emphasis>. The
8092 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
8093 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
8094 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
8095 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
8096 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
8097 </para>
8098 <para>
8099 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
8100 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
8101 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
8102 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
8103 to defeat these protections as well?
8104 </para>
8105 <para>
8106 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
8107 eBook Reader.
8108 </para>
8109 <indexterm id='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='startofrange'><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)</primary></indexterm>
8110 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>e-book restrictions on</secondary></indexterm>
8111 <para>
8112 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
8113 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
8114 on the Adobe site was a copy of <citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
8115 Wonderland</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
8116 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
8117 following report:
8118 </para>
8119 <figure id="fig-1641">
8120 <title></title>
8121 <graphic fileref="images/1641.png" align="center" width="50%"></graphic>
8122 </figure>
8123 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164-->
8124 <para>
8125 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
8126 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
8127 <quote>permissions</quote> indicated, not allowed to <quote>read aloud</quote>!
8128 </para>
8129 <para>
8130 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
8131 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
8132 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
8133 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
8134 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
8135 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
8136 </para>
8137 <para>
8138 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
8139 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
8140 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
8141 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
8142 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
8143 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
8144 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
8145 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
8146 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
8147 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
8148 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
8149 </para>
8150 <indexterm startref='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='endofrange'/>
8151 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='endofrange'/>
8152 <para>
8153 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
8154 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
8155 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
8156 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
8157 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
8158 often crazy.
8159 </para>
8160 <indexterm startref='idxadobeebookreader' class='endofrange'/>
8161 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet2' class='endofrange'/>
8162 <para>
8163 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
8164 story of mine that makes the same point.
8165 </para>
8166 <indexterm id='idxaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8167 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog1' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8168 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo1' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8169 <para>
8170 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named <quote>Aibo.</quote> The Aibo
8171 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
8172 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
8173 </para>
8174 <para>
8175 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
8176 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
8177 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
8178 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
8179 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
8180 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
8181 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
8182 </para>
8183 <para>
8184 <quote>Teach</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
8185 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
8186 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
8187 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
8188 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
8189 their computer <quote>dog</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
8190 </para>
8191 <indexterm><primary>hacks</primary></indexterm>
8192 <para>
8193 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
8194 <citetitle>hack</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
8195 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
8196 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
8197 them, <citetitle>hack</citetitle> is a much more positive
8198 term. <citetitle>Hack</citetitle> just means code that enables the
8199 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
8200 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
8201 old computer doesn't run, or <quote>drive,</quote> the printer. If you discovered
8202 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
8203 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
8204 you just bought.
8205 </para>
8206 <para>
8207 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
8208 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
8209 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
8210 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
8211 ethically.
8212 </para>
8213 <para>
8214 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
8215 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
8216 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
8217 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
8218 than Sony had built.
8219 </para>
8220 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8221 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog1' class='endofrange'/>
8222 <indexterm startref='idxaibo1' class='endofrange'/>
8223 <para>
8224 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
8225 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
8226 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
8227 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
8228 the
8229
8230 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
8231 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
8232 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
8233 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
8234 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
8235 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
8236 thought, <emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
8237 a robot dog to dance?</emphasis>
8238 </para>
8239 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>government case against</secondary></indexterm>
8240 <para>
8241 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show&mdash;
8242 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
8243 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
8244 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
8245 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
8246 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
8247 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
8248 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
8249 into being silent about something he knew very well.
8250 </para>
8251 <para>
8252 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.<footnote><para>
8253 <!-- f22 -->
8254 See Pamela Samuelson, <quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,</quote>
8255 <citetitle>Science</citetitle> 293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, <quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
8256 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect</citetitle>,
8257 January 2002; <quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
8258 DMCA,</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter</citetitle>, 11 December 2001; Bill
8259 Holland, <quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,</quote> <citetitle>Billboard</citetitle>,
8260 May 2001; Janelle Brown, <quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?</quote> Salon.com,
8261 April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, <quote>Frequently Asked
8262 Questions about <citetitle>Felten and USENIX</citetitle> v. <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> Legal Case,</quote> available at
8263 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #27</ulink>.
8264 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
8265 </para></footnote>
8266 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
8267 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
8268 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
8269 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
8270 </para>
8271 <para>
8272 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
8273 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
8274 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
8275 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
8276 <quote>this music cannot be copied,</quote> and have a computer respect that
8277 command. The technology was to be part of a <quote>trusted system</quote> of
8278 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
8279 Internet much more.
8280 </para>
8281 <para>
8282 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
8283 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
8284 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
8285 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
8286 </para>
8287 <para>
8288 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
8289 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
8290 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
8291 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
8292 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
8293 </para>
8294 <para>
8295 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
8296 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
8297 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
8298 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
8299 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
8300 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
8301 </para>
8302 <para>
8303 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
8304 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
8305 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
8306 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
8307 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
8308 constituted, succeed.
8309 </para>
8310 <indexterm id='idxaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8311 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog2' class='startofrange'><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8312 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8313 <para>
8314 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
8315 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
8316 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
8317 wrote:
8318 </para>
8319 <blockquote>
8320 <para>
8321 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
8322 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
8323 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
8324 </para>
8325 </blockquote>
8326 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8327 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog2' class='endofrange'/>
8328 <indexterm startref='idxaibo2' class='endofrange'/>
8329 <para>
8330 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
8331 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
8332 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
8333 </para>
8334 <blockquote>
8335 <para>
8336 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
8337 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
8338 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
8339 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
8340 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (<quote>DMCA</quote>).
8341 </para>
8342 </blockquote>
8343 <para>
8344 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
8345 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
8346 spreading such information an offense.
8347 </para>
8348 <para>
8349 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
8350 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
8351 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
8352 These new technologies would be copyright protection
8353 technologies&mdash; technologies to control the replication and
8354 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
8355 <emphasis>code</emphasis> to modify the original
8356 <emphasis>code</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
8357 protection for copyright owners.
8358 </para>
8359 <para>
8360 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
8361 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
8362 <emphasis>legal code</emphasis> intended to buttress
8363 <emphasis>software code</emphasis> which itself was intended to
8364 support the <emphasis>legal code of copyright</emphasis>.
8365 </para>
8366 <para>
8367 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
8368 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
8369 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
8370 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
8371 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
8372 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
8373 have been a copyright violation.
8374 </para>
8375 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8376 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8377 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8378 <para>
8379 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
8380 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
8381 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
8382 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
8383 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
8384 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
8385 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
8386 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
8387 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
8388 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
8389 </para>
8390 <para>
8391 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
8392 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
8393 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
8394 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
8395 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
8396 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
8397 </para>
8398 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8399 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8400 <para>
8401 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
8402 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
8403 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
8404 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
8405 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
8406 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka <quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers</citetitle>,</quote>
8407 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
8408 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
8409 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8410 </para>
8411 <blockquote>
8412 <para>
8413 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
8414 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
8415 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
8416 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
8417 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
8418 <quote>Neighborhood</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the <quote>Neighborhood</quote>
8419 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
8420 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
8421 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
8422 broadcasting has always been <quote>You are an important person just the way
8423 you are. You can make healthy decisions.</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
8424 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
8425 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
8426 important.<footnote><para>
8427 <!-- f23 -->
8428 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
8429 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc</citetitle>., 464 U.S. 417,
8430 455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
8431 James Lardner, <citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
8432 the VCR</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270&ndash;71.
8433 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred</primary></indexterm>
8434 </para></footnote>
8435 </para>
8436 </blockquote>
8437 <para>
8438 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
8439 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
8440 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
8441 the VCR responsible.
8442 </para>
8443 <para>
8444 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon in figure
8445 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n"
8446 linkend="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/>, which we can adopt to the
8447 DMCA.
8448 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8449 </para>
8450 <para>
8451 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
8452 </para>
8453 <figure id="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig" float="1">
8454 <title>&mdash; On which item have the courts ruled that manufacturers and
8455 retailers be held responsible for having supplied the
8456 equipment?</title>
8457 <graphic fileref="images/vcr-comic.png" align="center" width="65%"></graphic>
8458 </figure>
8459 <para>
8460 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
8461 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
8462 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
8463 pirating of copyrighted material&mdash;a bad end. Or they can be used
8464 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
8465 would be considered fair use&mdash;a good end.
8466 </para>
8467 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'><primary>handguns</primary></indexterm>
8468 <para>
8469 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
8470 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
8471 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
8472 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
8473 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
8474 and bad uses.
8475 </para>
8476 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul</primary></indexterm>
8477 <para>
8478 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
8479 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
8480 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash: <emphasis>No one ever
8481 died from copyright circumvention</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
8482 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
8483 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
8484 </para>
8485 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'/>
8486 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'/>
8487 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8488 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog</primary></indexterm>
8489 <indexterm><primary>Sony</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by</secondary></indexterm>
8490 <para>
8491 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
8492 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
8493 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
8494 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
8495 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
8496 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
8497 </para>
8498 <para>
8499 This is how <emphasis>code</emphasis> becomes
8500 <emphasis>law</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
8501 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
8502 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
8503 law&mdash;increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
8504 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
8505 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
8506 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect&mdash;at
8507 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
8508 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
8509 </para>
8510 <para>
8511 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
8512 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
8513 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
8514 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
8515 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
8516 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
8517 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
8518 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
8519 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
8520 </para>
8521 <para>
8522
8523 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8524 For example, imagine you were part of a <citetitle>Star Trek</citetitle> fan club. You
8525 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8526 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8527 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8528 simply continue it.<footnote><para>
8529 <!-- f24 -->
8530 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, <quote>Legal Fictions,
8531 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8532 Entertainment Law Journal</citetitle> 17 (1997): 651.
8533 </para></footnote>
8534 </para>
8535 <para>
8536 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8537 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8538 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8539 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8540 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8541 </para>
8542 <indexterm><primary>bots</primary></indexterm>
8543 <para>
8544 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8545 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8546 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8547 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8548 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8549 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8550 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8551 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8552 </para>
8553 <para>
8554 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8555 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8556 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8557 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8558 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8559 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8560 </para>
8561 </section>
8562 <section id="marketconcentration">
8563 <title>Market: Concentration</title>
8564 <para>
8565 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically&mdash;tripled in
8566 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8567 well&mdash;from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8568 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8569 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8570 find better ways
8571 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8572 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8573 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8574 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8575 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8576 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8577 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8578 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8579 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8580 control.
8581 </para>
8582 <para>
8583 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8584 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8585 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8586 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8587 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8588 </para>
8589 <para>
8590 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8591 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8592 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8593 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8594 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8595 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8596 announced in June 2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8597 live in a world where just three companies control more than 85 percent
8598 of the media.
8599 </para>
8600 <para>
8601 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8602 nature.
8603 </para>
8604 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8605 <indexterm><primary>BMG</primary></indexterm>
8606 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
8607 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John</primary></indexterm>
8608 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8609 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group</primary></indexterm>
8610 <para>
8611 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8612 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8613 ownership, <quote>five companies control 85 percent of our media sources.</quote><footnote><para>
8614 <!-- f25 -->
8615 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8616 Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003)
8617 (statement of Senator John McCain). </para></footnote>
8618 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8619 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 percent of the
8620 U.S. music market.<footnote><para>
8621 <!-- f26 -->
8622 Lynette Holloway, <quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8623 Slide,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 23 December 2002.
8624 </para></footnote>
8625 The <quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8626 programming to 74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.</quote><footnote><para>
8627 <!-- f27 -->
8628 Molly Ivins, <quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette</citetitle>,
8629 31 May 2003.
8630 </para></footnote>
8631 </para>
8632 <indexterm id='idxradioownershipconsolidationin' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>ownership consolidation in</secondary></indexterm>
8633 <para>
8634 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8635 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8636 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8637 seventy-five stations. Today <emphasis>one</emphasis> company owns
8638 more than 1,200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8639 total number of radio owners dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most
8640 markets, the two largest broadcasters control 74 percent of that
8641 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control 90 percent of
8642 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8643 </para>
8644 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
8645 <para>
8646 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8647 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8648 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8649 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8650 the United States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all
8651 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent
8652 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8653 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8654 protected&mdash; by the market.
8655 </para>
8656 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8657 <para>
8658 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8659 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8660 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8661 </para>
8662 <blockquote>
8663 <para>
8664 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8665 unmatched in its integration. They supply content&mdash;Fox movies
8666 &hellip; Fox TV shows &hellip; Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8667 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8668 advertisers&mdash;in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8669 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8670 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8671 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8672 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8673 the same function in the United States.<footnote><para>
8674 <!-- f28 -->
8675 James Fallows, <quote>The Age of Murdoch,</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly</citetitle> (September
8676 2003): 89.
8677 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James</primary></indexterm>
8678 </para></footnote>
8679 </para>
8680 </blockquote>
8681 <indexterm startref='idxradioownershipconsolidationin' class='endofrange'/>
8682 <para>
8683 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8684 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8685 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8686 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8687 </para>
8688 <figure id="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8689 <title></title>
8690 <graphic fileref="images/pattern-modern-media-ownership.png" align="center" width="100%"></graphic>
8691 </figure>
8692 <para>
8693 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8694 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8695 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8696 distribute content?
8697 </para>
8698 <para>
8699 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8700 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8701 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8702 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8703 </para>
8704 <para>
8705 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8706 integration may matter.
8707 </para>
8708 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman</primary></indexterm>
8709 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8710 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8711 <para>
8712 In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle>. He took
8713 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8714 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8715 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8716 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8717 </para>
8718 <para>
8719 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8720 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8721 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8722 control.<footnote><para>
8723 <!-- f29 -->
8724 Leonard Hill, <quote>The Axis of Access,</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8725 Forum, <quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,</quote> St. Louis,
8726 Missouri, 3 April 2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8727 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #28</ulink>;
8728 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8729 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #29</ulink>).
8730 </para></footnote>
8731 </para>
8732 <para>
8733
8734 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8735 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8736 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8737 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8738 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992,
8739 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8740 television&mdash;75 percent of it&mdash;was <quote>independent</quote> of the
8741 networks.
8742 </para>
8743 <para>
8744 In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8745 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985,
8746 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8747 2002, only five independent television studios remained. <quote>In 1992,
8748 only 15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8749 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8750 controlled companies more than quintupled to 77 percent.</quote> <quote>In 1992, 16
8751 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8752 year there was one.</quote><footnote><para>
8753 <!-- f30 -->
8754 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8755 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st
8756 sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8757 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8758 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8759 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8760 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February
8761 2003.
8762 </para></footnote>
8763 In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8764 that ran it. <quote>In the ten-year period between 1992 and 2002, the number
8765 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8766 increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8767 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8768 63%.</quote><footnote><para>
8769 <!-- f31 -->
8770 Ibid.
8771 </para></footnote>
8772 </para>
8773 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family</primary></indexterm>
8774 <para>
8775 Today, another Norman Lear with another <citetitle>All in the Family</citetitle> would
8776 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8777 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8778 owned by the network.
8779 </para>
8780 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry</primary></indexterm>
8781 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill</primary></indexterm>
8782 <para>
8783 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8784 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8785 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8786 </para>
8787 <blockquote>
8788 <para>
8789 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8790 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8791 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8792 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8793 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8794 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8795 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8796 handful.<footnote><para>
8797 <!-- f32 -->
8798 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers</citetitle>, Bill
8799 Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at
8800 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #31</ulink>.
8801 </para></footnote>
8802 </para>
8803 </blockquote>
8804 <para>
8805 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8806 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8807 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8808 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8809 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8810 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8811 question without risk of consequence&mdash;not necessarily banishment
8812 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8813 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8814 democracy.
8815 </para>
8816 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.</primary></indexterm>
8817 <para>
8818 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8819 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the <quote>Innovator's
8820 Dilemma</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8821 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8822 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8823 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.<footnote><para>
8824 <!-- f33 -->
8825 Clayton M. Christensen, <citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8826 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business</citetitle>
8827 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press, 1997). Christensen
8828 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8829 Kim B. Clark, <quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8830 Concepts in Technological Evolution,</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy</citetitle> 14 (1985):
8831 235&ndash;51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8832 Kaplan, <citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8833 Underperform the Market&mdash;and How to Successfully Transform Them</citetitle>
8834 (New York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001). </para></footnote>
8835
8836 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8837 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8838 sprinting.
8839 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.</primary></indexterm>
8840 </para>
8841 <para>
8842 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8843 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8844 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8845 measure.
8846 </para>
8847 <para>
8848 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8849 suggest the concern.
8850 </para>
8851 <para>
8852 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8853 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8854 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8855 </para>
8856 <para>
8857 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8858 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8859 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8860
8861 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8862 wrecked by drugs&mdash;though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8863 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8864 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8865 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8866 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8867 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8868 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8869 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8870 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8871 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8872 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8873 outweigh these costs.
8874 </para>
8875 <para>
8876 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8877 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8878 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8879 these issues.
8880 </para>
8881 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8882 <indexterm id='idxcommercials' class='startofrange'><primary>commercials</primary></indexterm>
8883 <indexterm id='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='startofrange'><primary>television</primary><secondary>advertising on</secondary></indexterm>
8884 <indexterm><primary>Nick and Norm anti-drug campaign</primary></indexterm>
8885 <para>
8886 Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8887 a media campaign as part of the <quote>war on drugs.</quote> The campaign produced
8888 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8889 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8890 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8891 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8892 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8893 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8894 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8895 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8896 </para>
8897 <para>
8898 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8899 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8900 </para>
8901 <para>
8902 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8903 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8904 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8905 war. Can you do it?
8906 </para>
8907 <para>
8908 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8909 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8910 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8911 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8912 message will be heard then?
8913 </para>
8914 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>First Amendment to</secondary></indexterm>
8915 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment</primary></indexterm>
8916 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>on television advertising bans</secondary></indexterm>
8917 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>controversy avoided by</secondary></indexterm>
8918 <para>
8919 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8920 <quote>controversial</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8921 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8922 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8923 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8924 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8925 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8926 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8927 rights of the stations to be this biased.<footnote><para>
8928 <!-- f34 -->
8929 <indexterm><primary>ABC</primary></indexterm>
8930 <indexterm><primary>Comcast</primary></indexterm>
8931 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project</primary></indexterm>
8932 <indexterm><primary>NBC</primary></indexterm>
8933 <indexterm><primary>WJOA</primary></indexterm>
8934 <indexterm><primary>WRC</primary></indexterm>
8935 <indexterm><primary>advertising</primary></indexterm>
8936 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads
8937 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8938 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as <quote>against
8939 [their] policy.</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8940 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8941 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8942 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8943 Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8944 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives, <quote>On the
8945 Issue of an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV
8946 Networks,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 13 March
8947 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time there is very little
8948 that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to even the playing
8949 field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown, <quote>Ad Hoc Access:
8950 The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8951 Radio,</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review</citetitle> 6
8952 (1988): 449&ndash;79, and for a more recent summary of the stance of
8953 the FCC and the courts, see <citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors
8954 Association</citetitle> v. <citetitle>FCC</citetitle>, 184 F. 3d 872
8955 (D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8956 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8957 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8958 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross, <quote>Antidiesel Group
8959 Fuming After Muni Rejects Ad,</quote> SFGate.com, 16 June 2003,
8960 available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8961 #32</ulink>. The ground was that the criticism was <quote>too
8962 controversial.</quote>
8963 </para></footnote>
8964 </para>
8965 <indexterm startref='idxcommercials' class='endofrange'/>
8966 <indexterm startref='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='endofrange'/>
8967 <para>
8968 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well&mdash;if we lived
8969 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8970 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8971 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8972 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8973 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8974 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8975 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8976 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8977 </para>
8978 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'/>
8979 </section>
8980 <section id="together">
8981 <title>Together</title>
8982 <para>
8983 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8984 copyright warriors that the government should <quote>protect my property.</quote>
8985 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8986 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8987 </para>
8988 <para>
8989 But when we see how dramatically this <quote>property</quote> has changed&mdash;
8990 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8991 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8992 cultivate our culture is dramatically different&mdash;the claim begins
8993 to seem
8994
8995 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8996 less innocent and obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to
8997 supplement the law's control, and (2) the power of concentrated
8998 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8999 the massively expanded <quote>property</quote> rights granted by copyright
9000 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
9001 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
9002 be redefined.
9003 </para>
9004 <para>
9005 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
9006 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
9007 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
9008 our culture today.
9009 </para>
9010 <para>
9011 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
9012 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
9013 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
9014 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
9015 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
9016 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
9017 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
9018 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
9019 traditionally defined copyright's regulation&mdash;a weakening of that
9020 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
9021 </para>
9022 <para>
9023 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
9024 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
9025 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
9026 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
9027 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
9028 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
9029 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
9030 future. And these changes have to be <emphasis>reductions</emphasis>
9031 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
9032 in control that technology and the market enable.
9033 </para>
9034 <para>
9035 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
9036 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
9037 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
9038 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
9039 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
9040 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
9041 more of the development of our culture than now</emphasis>.
9042 </para>
9043 <para>
9044 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
9045 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
9046 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
9047 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
9048 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
9049 were independent of the networks. <emphasis>Never</emphasis> has
9050 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
9051 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
9052 regulation&mdash;a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
9053 energy of a nation at the founding&mdash;is now a massive regulation
9054 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
9055 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
9056 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
9057 known.<footnote><para>
9058 <!-- f35 -->
9059 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva</primary></indexterm>
9060 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his <quote>four surrenders</quote> of
9061 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan, 159&ndash;60.
9062 </para></footnote>
9063 </para>
9064 <para>
9065 <emphasis role='strong'>This has been</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
9066 point can now be briefly stated.
9067 </para>
9068 <para>
9069 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
9070 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
9071 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
9072 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
9073 that copyright law has undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this:
9074 </para>
9075
9076 <informaltable id="t2">
9077 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9078 <thead>
9079 <row>
9080 <entry></entry>
9081 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9082 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9083 </row>
9084 </thead>
9085 <tbody>
9086 <row>
9087 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9088 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9089 <entry>Free</entry>
9090 </row>
9091 <row>
9092 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9093 <entry>Free</entry>
9094 <entry>Free</entry>
9095 </row>
9096 </tbody>
9097 </tgroup>
9098 </informaltable>
9099
9100 <para>
9101 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
9102 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
9103 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
9104
9105 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
9106 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
9107 noncommercial work was also free.
9108 </para>
9109 <para>
9110 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
9111 </para>
9112
9113 <informaltable id="t3">
9114 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9115 <thead>
9116 <row>
9117 <entry></entry>
9118 <entry>PUBLISH</entry>
9119 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9120 </row>
9121 </thead>
9122 <tbody>
9123 <row>
9124 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9125 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9126 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9127 </row>
9128 <row>
9129 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9130 <entry>Free</entry>
9131 <entry>Free</entry>
9132 </row>
9133 </tbody>
9134 </tgroup>
9135 </informaltable>
9136
9137 <para>
9138 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law&mdash;if
9139 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
9140 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
9141 transformation were still essentially free.
9142 </para>
9143 <para>
9144 In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
9145 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
9146 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
9147 expanded. Thus by 1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
9148 we could say the law began to look like this:
9149 </para>
9150
9151 <informaltable id="t4">
9152 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9153 <thead>
9154 <row>
9155 <entry></entry>
9156 <entry>COPY</entry>
9157 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9158 </row>
9159 </thead>
9160 <tbody>
9161 <row>
9162 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9163 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9164 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9165 </row>
9166 <row>
9167 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9168 <entry>&copy; / Free</entry>
9169 <entry>Free</entry>
9170 </row>
9171 </tbody>
9172 </tgroup>
9173 </informaltable>
9174
9175 <para>
9176 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
9177 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
9178 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
9179 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
9180 that the law now looks like this:
9181 </para>
9182
9183 <informaltable id="t5">
9184 <tgroup cols="3" align="left">
9185 <thead>
9186 <row>
9187 <entry></entry>
9188 <entry>COPY</entry>
9189 <entry>TRANSFORM</entry>
9190 </row>
9191 </thead>
9192 <tbody>
9193 <row>
9194 <entry>Commercial</entry>
9195 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9196 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9197 </row>
9198 <row>
9199 <entry>Noncommercial</entry>
9200 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9201 <entry>&copy;</entry>
9202 </row>
9203 </tbody>
9204 </tgroup>
9205 </informaltable>
9206
9207 <para>
9208 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
9209 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
9210 creativity&mdash;
9211 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
9212 commercial or not, transformative or not&mdash;with the same rules
9213 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
9214 </para>
9215 <para>
9216 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
9217 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
9218 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
9219 these domains actually does any good.
9220 </para>
9221 <para>
9222 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
9223 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
9224 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
9225 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
9226 reasons sketched especially in chapters
9227 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/> and
9228 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>, one
9229 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
9230 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
9231 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
9232 </para>
9233 <para>
9234 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
9235 course copyright is a kind of <quote>property,</quote> and of course, as with any
9236 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
9237 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
9238 property rights<footnote><para>
9239 <!-- f36 -->
9240 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement</primary></indexterm>
9241 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
9242 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
9243 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, <quote>The
9244 Disintegration of Property,</quote> in <citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property</citetitle>, J. Roland
9245 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
9246 Press, 1980).
9247 </para></footnote>)
9248 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
9249 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
9250 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
9251 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the <quote>copyright</quote>
9252 did not control <emphasis>at all</emphasis> the freedom of others to
9253 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
9254 free, and for almost 180 years our country consistently protected a
9255 vibrant and rich free culture.
9256 </para>
9257 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
9258 <para>
9259 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
9260 limits on the scope of the interests protected by <quote>property.</quote> The very
9261 birth of <quote>copyright</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
9262 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
9263 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9264 linkend="founders"/>). The tradition of <quote>fair use</quote> is
9265 animated by a similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the
9266 costs of exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the
9267 story of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9268 linkend="recorders"/>). Adding
9269 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
9270 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
9271 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter <xref
9272 xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="transformers"/>). And
9273 granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect, claims of
9274 property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing the soul
9275 of a culture (chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
9276 linkend="collectors"/>). Free cultures, like free markets, are built
9277 with property. But the nature of the property that builds a free
9278 culture is very different from the extremist vision that dominates the
9279 debate today.
9280 </para>
9281 <para>
9282 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
9283 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
9284 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
9285 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
9286 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
9287 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
9288 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
9289 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
9290 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
9291 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
9292 lawyer.
9293 </para>
9294 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
9295 </section>
9296 </chapter>
9297 </part>
9298 <part id="c-puzzles">
9299 <title>Puzzles</title>
9300
9301 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
9302 <chapter label="11" id="chimera">
9303 <title>Chapter Eleven: Chimera</title>
9304 <indexterm id='idxchimera' class='startofrange'><primary>chimeras</primary></indexterm>
9305 <indexterm id='idxwells' class='startofrange'><primary>Wells, H. G.</primary></indexterm>
9306 <indexterm id='idxtcotb' class='startofrange'><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The</quote> (Wells)</primary></indexterm>
9307
9308 <para>
9309 <emphasis role='strong'>In a well-known</emphasis> short story by
9310 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
9311 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
9312 Andes.<footnote><para>
9313 <!-- f1. -->
9314 H. G. Wells, <quote>The Country of the Blind</quote> (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells,
9315 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
9316 York: Oxford University Press, 1996).
9317 </para></footnote>
9318 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with <quote>sweet water, pasture,
9319 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
9320 that bore an excellent fruit.</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
9321 takes this as an opportunity. <quote>In the Country of the Blind,</quote> he tells
9322 himself, <quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.</quote> So he resolves to live with the
9323 villagers to explore life as a king.
9324 </para>
9325 <para>
9326 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
9327 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
9328 <quote>blind.</quote> They don't have the word <citetitle>blind</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
9329 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
9330 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
9331 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated. <quote>`You
9332 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
9333 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
9334 alone!'</quote>
9335 </para>
9336 <para>
9337 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
9338 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
9339 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
9340 affection, a young woman who to him seems <quote>the most beautiful thing in
9341 the whole of creation,</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
9342 description of what he sees <quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
9343 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
9344 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
9345 indulgence.</quote> <quote>She did not believe,</quote> Wells tells us, and <quote>she could
9346 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.</quote>
9347 </para>
9348 <para>
9349 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his <quote>mysteriously delighted</quote>
9350 love, the father and the village object. <quote>You see, my dear,</quote> her
9351 father instructs, <quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
9352 anything right.</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
9353 </para>
9354 <para>
9355 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. <quote>His brain
9356 is affected,</quote> he reports.
9357 </para>
9358 <para>
9359 <quote>What affects it?</quote> the father asks. <quote>Those queer things that are
9360 called the eyes &hellip; are diseased &hellip; in such a way as to affect
9361 his brain.</quote>
9362 </para>
9363 <para>
9364 The doctor continues: <quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
9365 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
9366 simple and easy surgical operation&mdash;namely, to remove these
9367 irritant bodies [the eyes].</quote>
9368 </para>
9369 <para>
9370 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
9371 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
9372 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
9373 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
9374 </para>
9375 <para>
9376 <emphasis role='strong'>It sometimes</emphasis> happens that the eggs
9377 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
9378 <quote>chimera.</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
9379 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
9380 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
9381
9382 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
9383 plot for murder mysteries. <quote>But the DNA shows with 100 percent
9384 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
9385 scene. &hellip;</quote>
9386 </para>
9387 <indexterm startref='idxtcotb' class='endofrange'/>
9388 <indexterm startref='idxwells' class="endofrange"/>
9389 <para>
9390 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
9391 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
9392 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
9393 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
9394 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
9395 understanding of a <quote>person</quote> should reflect this reality.
9396 </para>
9397 <para>
9398 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
9399 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
9400 unfairly enough, <quote>the copyright wars,</quote> the more I think we're dealing
9401 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question <quote>What is
9402 p2p file sharing?</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
9403 wrong. One side says, <quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
9404 others' records&mdash;the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
9405 thirty years without any question at all.</quote> That's true, at least in
9406 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
9407 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
9408 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
9409 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
9410 </para>
9411 <para>
9412 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
9413 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
9414 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
9415 <quote>friends</quote> beyond recognition to say <quote>my ten thousand best friends</quote> can
9416 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
9417 what <quote>we have always been allowed to do,</quote> we have not always been
9418 allowed to share music with <quote>our ten thousand best friends.</quote>
9419 </para>
9420 <para>
9421 Likewise, when the other side says, <quote>File sharing is just like walking
9422 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
9423 with it,</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
9424 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
9425 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
9426 from Tower.
9427 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9428 </para>
9429 <para>
9430
9431 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
9432 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
9433 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
9434 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
9435 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
9436 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
9437 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
9438 $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
9439 CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.)
9440 </para>
9441 <para>
9442 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
9443 that it is both&mdash;both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
9444 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
9445 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
9446 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
9447 </para>
9448 <para>
9449 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
9450 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
9451 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
9452 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
9453 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
9454 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
9455 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
9456 implemented.<footnote><para>
9457 <!-- f2. -->
9458 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9459 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
9460 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
9461 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003,
9462 available at
9463 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9464 #33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
9465 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
9466 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
9467 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, <quote>House Bill Aims to Up
9468 Stakes on Piracy,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 17 July 2003, available at
9469 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #34</ulink>. Civil
9470 penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied song. For a recent
9471 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
9472 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 songs
9473 through a family computer, see <citetitle>RIAA</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
9474 re. Verizon Internet Services)</citetitle>, 240 F. Supp. 2d 24
9475 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $90
9476 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
9477 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
9478 $12,000 to $17,500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
9479 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $98
9480 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
9481 Elizabeth Young, <quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,</quote> redandblack.com,
9482 August 2003, available at
9483 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #35</ulink>. For an
9484 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
9485 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
9486 identities, see James Collins, <quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
9487 Name Students,</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 8 August 2003, D3, available at
9488 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #36</ulink>.
9489 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.</primary></indexterm>
9490 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
9491 </para></footnote>
9492
9493 </para>
9494 <indexterm startref='idxchimera' class='endofrange'/>
9495 <para>
9496 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
9497 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
9498 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
9499 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
9500 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
9501 </para>
9502 <para>
9503 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
9504 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
9505 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
9506 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
9507 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
9508 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe <emphasis>either</emphasis> extreme
9509 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
9510 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
9511 </para>
9512 <para>
9513
9514 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
9515 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
9516 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
9517 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
9518 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
9519 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
9520 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
9521 </para>
9522 <para>
9523 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to <quote>steal</quote> music. My
9524 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
9525 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
9526 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
9527 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
9528 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
9529 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
9530 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
9531 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
9532 protection for copyrighted material,
9533 </para>
9534 <blockquote>
9535 <para>
9536 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
9537 material, and we want to protect those rights.
9538 </para>
9539 <para>
9540 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9541 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9542 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9543 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9544 produce a totally different industry model.
9545 </para>
9546 <para>
9547 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9548 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9549 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9550 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9551 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9552 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9553 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9554 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9555 interests.<footnote><para>
9556 <!-- f3. -->
9557 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9558 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9559 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9560 House Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter
9561 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9562 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9563 Congressional Testimony File. </para></footnote>
9564 </para>
9565 </blockquote>
9566 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9567 <para>
9568 In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9569 one of <quote>the major labels.</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9570 changed.
9571 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9572 </para>
9573 <para>
9574 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9575 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9576 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9577 </para>
9578
9579 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9580 </chapter>
9581 <chapter label="12" id="harms">
9582 <title>Chapter Twelve: Harms</title>
9583 <para>
9584 <emphasis role='strong'>To fight</emphasis> <quote>piracy,</quote> to
9585 protect <quote>property,</quote> the content industry has launched a
9586 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9587 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9588 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9589 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9590 </para>
9591 <para>
9592 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9593 particular, the consequences for <quote>free culture.</quote> But my aim now is to
9594 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9595 justified?
9596 </para>
9597 <para>
9598 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9599 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9600 power of the property called <quote>intellectual property</quote> is at its greatest in
9601 our history.
9602 </para>
9603 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
9604 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
9605 <para>
9606 Yet <quote>common sense</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9607 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9608 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9609 rejection of <quote>piracy</quote> still has play.
9610 </para>
9611 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
9612 <para>
9613 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9614 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9615 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9616 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9617 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9618 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9619 </para>
9620 <section id="constrain">
9621 <title>Constraining Creators</title>
9622 <para>
9623 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9624 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9625 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9626 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9627 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9628 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9629 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9630 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9631 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9632 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9633 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9634 weave together a string&mdash;a mash-up&mdash; of songs from your
9635 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9636 </para>
9637 <para>
9638 This digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> is in part an extension of the
9639 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9640 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9641 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9642 of digital <quote>capturing and sharing</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9643 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9644 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9645 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9646 the culture all around.
9647 </para>
9648 <para>
9649 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9650 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9651
9652 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9653
9654 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9655 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9656 storytelling extended across the globe.
9657 </para>
9658 <para>
9659 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9660 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9661 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9662 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9663 that catalog cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9664 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9665 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9666 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9667 work is presumptively illegal.
9668 </para>
9669 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom</primary></indexterm>
9670 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9671 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9672 <indexterm><primary>doctors malpractice claims against</primary></indexterm>
9673 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse</primary></indexterm>
9674 <para>
9675 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9676 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9677 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9678 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9679 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9680 by the RIAA (Jesse Jordan of chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9681 labelnumber" linkend="catalogs"/> was just one) were threatened with a
9682 $98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted songs
9683 to be copied. Yet World-Com&mdash;which defrauded investors of $11
9684 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization of
9685 over $200 billion&mdash;received a fine of a mere $750
9686 million.<footnote><para>
9687 <!-- f1. -->
9688 See Lynne W. Jeter, <citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom</citetitle>
9689 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley &amp; Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of
9690 the settlement, see MCI press release, <quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9691 Approval for SEC Settlement</quote> (7 July 2003), available at
9692 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #37</ulink>.
9693 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom</primary></indexterm>
9694 </para></footnote>
9695 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9696 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9697 no more than $250,000 in damages for pain and
9698 suffering.<footnote>
9699 <para>
9700 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9701 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For
9702 an overview, see Tanya Albert, <quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9703 Say Tort Reformers,</quote> amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at
9704 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #38</ulink>,
9705 and <quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,</quote> CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003,
9706 available at
9707 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9708 recent months.
9709 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.</primary></indexterm>
9710 </para></footnote>
9711 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9712 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9713 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9714 </para>
9715 <indexterm><primary>art, underground</primary></indexterm>
9716 <para>
9717 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9718 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9719 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9720 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9721 Disneys <quote>pirates.</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9722 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9723 designed to
9724
9725 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9726 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9727 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9728 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9729 we will begin to see a world of underground art&mdash;not because the
9730 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9731 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9732 fraught. Already, exhibits of <quote>illegal art</quote> tour the United
9733 States.<footnote><para>
9734 <!-- f3. -->
9735
9736 See Danit Lidor, <quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,</quote> <citetitle>Wired</citetitle>, 7 July
9737 2003, available at
9738 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9739 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #41</ulink>.
9740 </para></footnote>
9741 In what does their <quote>illegality</quote> consist?
9742 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9743 critical or reflective.
9744 </para>
9745 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
9746 <para>
9747 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9748 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9749 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. But an
9750 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9751 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9752 discovered in 2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9753 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9754 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9755 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9756 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9757 </para>
9758 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of</primary></indexterm>
9759 <para>
9760 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9761 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9762 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9763 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9764 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9765 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9766 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9767 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9768 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9769 </para>
9770 <para>
9771 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9772 described in chapter
9773 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="recorders"/>, in
9774 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9775 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9776 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9777 use.
9778 </para>
9779 <para>
9780
9781 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9782 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9783 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9784 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad&mdash;in
9785 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9786 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9787 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9788 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9789 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9790 </para>
9791 <para>
9792 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9793 <quote>breathing room</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9794 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9795 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9796 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9797 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9798 journalists&mdash; these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9799 these rules have little relationship to the <quote>law</quote> with which judges
9800 comfort themselves.
9801 </para>
9802 <para>
9803 For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful
9804 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9805 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9806 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9807 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak&mdash;in that
9808 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9809 <quote>copyright</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9810 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9811 culture that is free.
9812 </para>
9813 <para>
9814 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9815 </para>
9816 <blockquote>
9817 <para>
9818 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9819 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9820 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9821 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made &hellip; you're not
9822 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9823 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9824 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying, <quote>This has been
9825 cleared.</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9826 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9827 </para>
9828 </blockquote>
9829 </section>
9830 <section id="innovators">
9831 <title>Constraining Innovators</title>
9832 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>innovation hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
9833 <indexterm id='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='startofrange'><primary>innovation</primary><secondary>industry establishment opposed to</secondary></indexterm>
9834 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='startofrange'><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism</secondary></indexterm>
9835 <para>
9836 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9837 story&mdash;creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9838 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9839 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9840 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9841 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9842 </para>
9843 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints2' class='startofrange'><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
9844 <para>
9845 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9846 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9847 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9848 one at that, <xref xrefstyle="select: pagenumber"
9849 linkend="innovators"/> pages into a book like this), then you
9850 can see this other aspect by substituting <quote>free market</quote>
9851 every place I've spoken of <quote>free culture.</quote> The point is
9852 the same, even if the interests affecting culture are more
9853 fundamental.
9854 </para>
9855 <para>
9856 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9857 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9858 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary&mdash;at
9859 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9860 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9861 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9862 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9863 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9864 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9865 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9866 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9867 </para>
9868 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints2' class='endofrange'/>
9869 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9870 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
9871 <para>
9872 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9873 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9874 strategy that I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select:
9875 labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9876 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9877 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9878 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9879 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9880 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9881 lesson. That lesson&mdash;what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9882 <quote>nuclear pall</quote> that has fallen over the Valley&mdash;has been learned.
9883 </para>
9884 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)</primary></indexterm>
9885 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary></indexterm>
9886 <para>
9887 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9888 I told in <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9889 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9890 </para>
9891 <indexterm id='idxmpcom' class='startofrange'><primary>MP3.com</primary></indexterm>
9892 <indexterm id='idxmympcom' class='startofrange'><primary>my.mp3.com</primary></indexterm>
9893 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael</primary></indexterm>
9894 <para>
9895 In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9896 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9897 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9898 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9899 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9900 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9901 </para>
9902 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
9903 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>preference data on</secondary></indexterm>
9904 <para>
9905 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9906 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9907 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9908 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9909 Raitt. And so on.
9910 </para>
9911 <para>
9912 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9913 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9914 preference data. In January 2000, the company launched a service
9915 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9916 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9917 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9918 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9919 wherever you were&mdash;at work or at home&mdash;you could get access
9920 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9921 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9922 </para>
9923 <para>
9924 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9925 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9926
9927 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9928 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9929 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9930 the kind of content the users liked.
9931 </para>
9932 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'/>
9933 <para>
9934 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000
9935 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9936 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9937 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9938 therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9939 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9940 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9941 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was 50,000
9942 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers something
9943 they had already bought.
9944 </para>
9945 <indexterm id='idxvivendiuniversal' class='startofrange'><primary>Vivendi Universal</primary></indexterm>
9946 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9947 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of</secondary></indexterm>
9948 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>in recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
9949 <indexterm><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of</secondary></indexterm>
9950 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by</secondary></indexterm>
9951 <indexterm><primary>regulation</primary><secondary>outsize penalties of</secondary></indexterm>
9952 <para>
9953 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9954 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9955 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9956 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9957 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9958 MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9959 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $54 million. Vivendi
9960 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9961 </para>
9962 <para>
9963 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9964 </para>
9965 <para>
9966 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9967 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9968 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9969 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9970 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9971 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9972 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9973 demanded.
9974 </para>
9975 <indexterm startref='idxvivendiuniversal' class='endofrange'/>
9976 <para>
9977 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9978 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9979 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9980 clients in this
9981 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9982 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9983 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9984 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9985 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9986 </para>
9987 <indexterm startref='idxmpcom' class='endofrange'/>
9988 <indexterm startref='idxmympcom' class='endofrange'/>
9989 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='endofrange'/>
9990 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9991 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in</secondary></indexterm>
9992 <indexterm id='idxbmw' class='startofrange'><primary>BMW</primary></indexterm>
9993 <indexterm id='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='startofrange'><primary>cars, MP3 sound systems in</primary></indexterm>
9994 <indexterm><primary>EMI</primary></indexterm>
9995 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John</primary></indexterm>
9996 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank</primary></indexterm>
9997 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad</primary></indexterm>
9998 <indexterm><primary>MP3 players</primary></indexterm>
9999 <indexterm><primary>Napster</primary><secondary>venture capital for</secondary></indexterm>
10000 <indexterm id='idxneedlemanrafe' class='startofrange'><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
10001 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group</primary></indexterm>
10002 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists</primary></indexterm>
10003 <para>
10004 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003,
10005 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
10006 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
10007 its development, its cofounder (John Hummer), and general partner
10008 (Hank Barry).<footnote><para>
10009 <!-- f4. -->
10010 See Joseph Menn, <quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
10011 Times</citetitle>, 23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
10012 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, <quote>The Music
10013 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,</quote> Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available
10014 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #42</ulink>.
10015 See also Jon Healey, <quote>Online Music Services Besieged,</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
10016 Times</citetitle>, 28 May 2001.
10017 </para></footnote>
10018 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
10019 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
10020 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
10021 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
10022 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
10023 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
10024 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
10025 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
10026 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
10027 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
10028 <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
10029 discussion with BMW:
10030 </para>
10031 <blockquote>
10032 <para>
10033 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
10034 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
10035 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
10036 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
10037 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
10038 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
10039 United States with bona fide MP3 players. &hellip; <footnote>
10040 <para>
10041 <!-- f5. -->
10042 Rafe Needleman, <quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,</quote> <citetitle>Business 2.0</citetitle>, 16 June
10043 2003, available at
10044 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #43</ulink>. I am grateful
10045 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
10046 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe</primary></indexterm>
10047 </para></footnote>
10048 </para>
10049 </blockquote>
10050 <indexterm startref='idxbmw' class='endofrange'/>
10051 <indexterm startref='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='endofrange'/>
10052 <indexterm startref='idxneedlemanrafe' class='endofrange'/>
10053 <para>
10054 This is the world of the mafia&mdash;filled with <quote>your money or your
10055 life</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
10056 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
10057 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
10058 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
10059 constantly threatened by litigation.
10060 </para>
10061 <para>
10062
10063 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
10064 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
10065 enterprises. The point is the definition of <quote>illegal.</quote> The law is a
10066 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
10067 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
10068 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
10069 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
10070 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
10071 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
10072 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
10073 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
10074 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
10075 much less creativity.
10076 </para>
10077 <indexterm><primary>market constraints</primary></indexterm>
10078 <para>
10079 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
10080 use. Whatever the <quote>real</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
10081 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
10082 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
10083 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
10084 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
10085 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
10086 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
10087 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
10088 produce an overregulated-regulated market.
10089 </para>
10090 <para>
10091 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
10092 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
10093 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
10094 culture&mdash;a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
10095 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
10096 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
10097 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
10098 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
10099 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
10100 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
10101 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
10102 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
10103 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
10104 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
10105 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
10106 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
10107 result.
10108 </para>
10109 <para>
10110 <emphasis role='strong'>The uncertainty</emphasis> of the law is one
10111 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
10112 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
10113 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
10114 better protects their content.
10115 </para>
10116 <para>
10117 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
10118 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
10119 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
10120 this feature is a <quote>bug.</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
10121 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
10122 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
10123 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables <quote>piracy,</quote> then,
10124 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
10125 </para>
10126 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10127 <para>
10128 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
10129 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
10130 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
10131 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.<footnote><para>
10132 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> GartnerG2 and
10133 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
10134 (2003), 33&ndash;35, available at
10135 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10136 </para></footnote>
10137 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
10138 <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
10139 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
10140 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
10141 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
10142 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
10143 copyright violators and disable their machines.<footnote><para>
10144 <!-- f7. -->
10145 GartnerG2, 26&ndash;27.
10146 </para></footnote>
10147 </para>
10148 <para>
10149 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
10150 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
10151 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
10152 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
10153 and costs on
10154 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
10155 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
10156 those requirements.
10157 </para>
10158 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
10159 <para>
10160 In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
10161 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
10162 would impose.<footnote><para>
10163 <!-- f8. -->
10164 See David McGuire, <quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,</quote> Newsbytes,
10165 February 2002 (Entertainment).
10166 </para></footnote>
10167 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
10168 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
10169 harm than good.
10170 </para>
10171 <para>
10172 <emphasis role='strong'>There is one</emphasis> more obvious way in
10173 which this war has harmed innovation&mdash;again, a story that will be
10174 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
10175 </para>
10176 <para>
10177 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
10178 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
10179 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
10180 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
10181 </para>
10182 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
10183 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
10184 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses</primary></indexterm>
10185 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in</secondary></indexterm>
10186 <para>
10187 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10188 linkend="property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
10189 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
10190 Jessica Litman in her book <citetitle>Digital
10191 Copyright</citetitle>,<footnote><para>
10192 <!-- f9. -->
10193 Jessica Litman, <citetitle>Digital Copyright</citetitle> (Amherst,
10194 N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001).
10195 <indexterm><primary>Digital Copyright (Litman)</primary></indexterm>
10196 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica</primary></indexterm>
10197 </para></footnote>
10198 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter
10199 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/> details,
10200 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
10201 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
10202 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
10203 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
10204 </para>
10205 <para>
10206 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
10207 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
10208 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
10209 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
10210 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
10211 </para>
10212 <indexterm id='idxinternetradioon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>radio on</secondary></indexterm>
10213 <indexterm id='idxradiooninternet' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>on Internet</secondary></indexterm>
10214 <para>
10215 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.<footnote><para>
10216 <!-- f10. -->
10217 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.</primary></indexterm>
10218 The only circuit court exception is found in <citetitle>Recording Industry
10219 Association of America (RIAA)</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems</citetitle>, 180 F. 3d
10220 1072 (9th Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
10221 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
10222 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
10223 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
10224 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
10225 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
10226 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc</citetitle>. v. <citetitle>Grokster, Ltd</citetitle>., 259 F. Supp. 2d
10227 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the link between the
10228 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
10229 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
10230 liability.
10231 </para></footnote>
10232 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
10233 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
10234 here.<footnote><para>
10235 <!-- f11. -->
10236 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy</primary></indexterm>
10237 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.</primary></indexterm>
10238 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz</primary></indexterm>
10239 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag</primary></indexterm>
10240 For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
10241 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize
10242 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
10243 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
10244 August 2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
10245 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
10246 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a <quote>broadcast flag</quote> that
10247 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
10248 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
10249 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
10250 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2, <quote>Copyright and
10251 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,</quote> 27 June 2003, 33&ndash;34,
10252 available at
10253 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #44</ulink>.
10254 </para></footnote>
10255 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
10256 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
10257 </para>
10258 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10259 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.</primary></indexterm>
10260 <indexterm><primary>Monroe, Marilyn</primary></indexterm>
10261 <indexterm id='idxradiomusicrecordingsplayedon2' class='startofrange'><primary>radio</primary><secondary>music recordings played on</secondary></indexterm>
10262 <para>
10263
10264 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
10265 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
10266 linkend="pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
10267 artist doesn't get paid for that <quote>radio performance</quote> unless he or she
10268 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
10269 version of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote>&mdash;to memorialize her famous
10270 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden&mdash;
10271 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
10272 copyright owners of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> would get some money, whereas
10273 Marilyn Monroe would not.
10274 </para>
10275 <para>
10276 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
10277 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
10278 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
10279 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
10280 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
10281 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
10282 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
10283 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
10284 recording artists.
10285 </para>
10286 <indexterm startref='idxradiomusicrecordingsplayedon2' class='endofrange'/>
10287 <para>
10288 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
10289 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
10290 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
10291 spectrum. Thus, I can <quote>tune in</quote> to an Internet radio station in
10292 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
10293 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
10294 metropolitan area.
10295 </para>
10296 <para>
10297 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
10298 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
10299 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
10300 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
10301 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
10302 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
10303 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
10304 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
10305 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
10306 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
10307 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
10308 </para>
10309 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard</primary></indexterm>
10310 <para>
10311
10312 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
10313 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
10314 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
10315 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
10316 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
10317 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
10318 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
10319 FM radio,
10320 </para>
10321 <blockquote>
10322 <para>
10323 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
10324 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
10325 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
10326 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
10327 than by technical restrictions. &hellip; Armstrong likened the situation
10328 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
10329 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
10330 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
10331 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
10332 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
10333 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
10334 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
10335 shackles.<footnote><para>
10336 <!-- f12. -->
10337 Lessing, 239.
10338 </para></footnote>
10339 </para>
10340 </blockquote>
10341 <para>
10342 This potential for FM radio was never realized&mdash;not
10343 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
10344 underestimated the power of <quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
10345 legislation</quote><footnote><para>
10346 <!-- f13. -->
10347 Ibid., 229.
10348 </para></footnote>
10349 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
10350 </para>
10351 <para>
10352 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
10353 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
10354 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
10355 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
10356 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
10357 radio?
10358 </para>
10359 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10360 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on copyright laws</secondary></indexterm>
10361 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on radio</secondary></indexterm>
10362 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>on recording industry</secondary></indexterm>
10363 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10364 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and</secondary></indexterm>
10365 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>Internet radio hampered by</secondary></indexterm>
10366 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10367 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>lobbying power of</secondary></indexterm>
10368 <para>
10369 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
10370 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
10371
10372 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
10373 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
10374 of Internet radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
10375 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
10376 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
10377 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
10378 of <quote>Happy Birthday</quote> on the air, <emphasis>Internet radio
10379 does</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
10380 radio&mdash;the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
10381 burdens terrestrial radio.
10382 </para>
10383 <para>
10384 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
10385 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
10386 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
10387 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
10388 over $1 million a year.<footnote>
10389 <para>
10390 <!-- f14. -->
10391 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
10392 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
10393 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
10394 iLaw (Stanford), 3 July 2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
10395 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
10396 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
10397 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP
10398 DTRA 1 and 2, available at
10399 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #45</ulink>.
10400 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
10401 C. Picker, <quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
10402 Distribution,</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin</citetitle> (Summer/Fall 2002): 461: <quote>This was
10403 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
10404 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
10405 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
10406 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
10407 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.</quote>
10408 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)</primary></indexterm>
10409 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.</primary></indexterm>
10410 </para></footnote>
10411 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
10412 equivalent fee.
10413 </para>
10414 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='endofrange'/>
10415 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='endofrange'/>
10416 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='endofrange'/>
10417 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='endofrange'/>
10418 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='endofrange'/>
10419 <para>
10420 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
10421 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
10422 station) would have to collect the following data from <emphasis>every
10423 listening transaction</emphasis>:
10424 </para>
10425 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
10426 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
10427 <listitem><para>
10428 name of the service;
10429 </para></listitem>
10430 <listitem><para>
10431 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
10432 </para></listitem>
10433 <listitem><para>
10434 type of program (archived/looped/live);
10435 </para></listitem>
10436 <listitem><para>
10437 date of transmission;
10438 </para></listitem>
10439 <listitem><para>
10440 time of transmission;
10441 </para></listitem>
10442 <listitem><para>
10443 time zone of origination of transmission;
10444 </para></listitem>
10445 <listitem><para>
10446 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
10447 </para></listitem>
10448 <listitem><para>
10449 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
10450 </para></listitem>
10451 <listitem><para>
10452 sound recording title;
10453 </para></listitem>
10454 <listitem><para>
10455 ISRC code of the recording;
10456 </para></listitem>
10457 <listitem><para>
10458 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
10459 </para></listitem>
10460 <listitem><para>
10461 featured recording artist;
10462 </para></listitem>
10463 <listitem><para>
10464 retail album title;
10465 </para></listitem>
10466 <listitem><para>
10467 recording label;
10468 </para></listitem>
10469 <listitem><para>
10470 UPC code of the retail album;
10471 </para></listitem>
10472 <listitem><para>
10473 catalog number;
10474 </para></listitem>
10475 <listitem><para>
10476 copyright owner information;
10477 </para></listitem>
10478 <listitem><para>
10479 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
10480 </para></listitem>
10481 <listitem><para>
10482 name of the service or entity;
10483 </para></listitem>
10484 <listitem><para>
10485 channel or program;
10486 </para></listitem>
10487 <listitem><para>
10488 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
10489 </para></listitem>
10490 <listitem><para>
10491 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
10492 </para></listitem>
10493 <listitem><para>
10494 time zone where the signal was received (user);
10495 </para></listitem>
10496 <listitem><para>
10497 unique user identifier;
10498 </para></listitem>
10499 <listitem><para>
10500 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
10501 </para></listitem>
10502 </orderedlist>
10503 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress</primary></indexterm>
10504 <para>
10505 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
10506 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
10507 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
10508 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
10509 Internet radio has to pay a <emphasis>type of copyright fee</emphasis>
10510 that terrestrial radio does not.
10511 </para>
10512 <para>
10513 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
10514 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
10515 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
10516 </para>
10517 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
10518 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
10519 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='startofrange'><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees</secondary></indexterm>
10520 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10521 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='startofrange'><primary>recording industry</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in</secondary></indexterm>
10522 <para>
10523 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
10524 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
10525 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
10526 </para>
10527 <blockquote>
10528 <para>
10529 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
10530 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
10531 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
10532 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
10533 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
10534 webcasters asked the RIAA, &hellip; <quote>How do you come up with a
10535
10536 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
10537 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
10538 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
10539 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
10540 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
10541 business. &hellip;</quote>
10542 </para>
10543 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
10544 <para>
10545 And the RIAA experts said, <quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
10546 industry with thousands of webcasters, <emphasis>we think it should be
10547 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
10548 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market</emphasis>.</quote> (Emphasis
10549 added.)
10550 </para>
10551 </blockquote>
10552 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'/>
10553 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='endofrange'/>
10554 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='endofrange'/>
10555 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='endofrange'/>
10556 <para>
10557 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
10558 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
10559 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
10560 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
10561 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
10562 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
10563 effective to prevent it.
10564 </para>
10565 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10566 <indexterm startref='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='endofrange'/>
10567 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='endofrange'/>
10568 <indexterm startref='idxinternetradioon' class='endofrange'/>
10569 <indexterm startref='idxradiooninternet' class='endofrange'/>
10570 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='endofrange'/>
10571 </section>
10572 <section id="corruptingcitizens">
10573 <title>Corrupting Citizens</title>
10574 <para>
10575 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
10576 dinosaurs
10577 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
10578 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
10579 </para>
10580 <para>
10581 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
10582 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
10583 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
10584 </para>
10585 <para>
10586 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
10587 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
10588 large number of citizens. According to <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, 43 million
10589 Americans downloaded music in May 2002.<footnote><para>
10590 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, <quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,</quote> Pew
10591 Internet and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at
10592 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #46</ulink>.
10593 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that 37 million
10594 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early 2001.
10595 </para></footnote>
10596 According to the RIAA,
10597 the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
10598 set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As the
10599
10600 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
10601 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
10602 the world, but against students building search engines, and
10603 increasingly
10604 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
10605 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10606 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10607 extreme
10608 response by the other.
10609 </para>
10610 <para>
10611 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10612 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10613 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10614 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10615 ($15,000,000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10616 paying all the money in the world in damages ($250,000 in legal fees)
10617 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10618 ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10619 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September 2003, the RIAA
10620 sued 261 individuals&mdash;including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10621 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10622 was.<footnote><para>
10623 <!-- f16. -->
10624 Alex Pham, <quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,</quote> <citetitle>Los
10625 Angeles Times</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, Business.
10626 </para></footnote>
10627 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10628 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10629 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000
10630 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10631 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10632 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10633 they oppose.
10634 </para>
10635 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition</primary></indexterm>
10636 <para>
10637 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10638 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10639 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10640 consumption of alcohol was 1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10641 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just 30 percent
10642 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10643 consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition
10644 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10645 number were criminals.<footnote><para>
10646 <!-- f17. -->
10647 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, <quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10648 Prohibition,</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review</citetitle> 81, no. 2 (1991): 242.
10649 </para></footnote>
10650 We have
10651 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10652 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10653 narcotics that 7 percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.<footnote><para>
10654 <!-- f18. -->
10655 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10656 Reform Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of
10657 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10658 </para></footnote>
10659 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of
10660 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10661 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10662 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10663 cheat.<footnote><para>
10664 <!-- f19. -->
10665 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, <quote>Tax
10666 Compliance,</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature</citetitle> 36 (1998): 818 (survey of
10667 compliance literature).
10668 </para></footnote>
10669 We pride ourselves on our <quote>free society,</quote> but an endless array of
10670 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10671 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10672 </para>
10673 <indexterm><primary>law schools</primary></indexterm>
10674 <para>
10675 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10676 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10677 students about the importance of <quote>ethics.</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10678 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10679 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10680 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10681 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10682 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10683 teach them how to behave ethically&mdash;how to say no to bribes, or
10684 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10685 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10686 Americans&mdash;more significantly in some parts of America than in
10687 others, but still, everywhere in America today&mdash;can't live their
10688 lives both normally and legally, since <quote>normally</quote> entails a certain
10689 degree of illegality.
10690 </para>
10691 <para>
10692 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10693 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10694 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10695 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10696 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10697 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10698 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10699 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10700 to consider the alternative.
10701 </para>
10702 <para>
10703
10704 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10705 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10706 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10707 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10708 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10709 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10710 </para>
10711 <para>
10712 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10713 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10714 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10715 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10716 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10717 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10718 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10719 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10720 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10721 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10722 introduced this different idea of <quote>sharing.</quote> We need to be able to
10723 call these twenty million Americans <quote>citizens,</quote> not <quote>felons.</quote>
10724 </para>
10725 <para>
10726 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10727 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10728 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10729 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10730 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10731 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10732 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10733 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10734 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10735 a nation of felons?
10736 </para>
10737 <para>
10738 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10739 </para>
10740 <para>
10741 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10742 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10743 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10744 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10745 used
10746
10747 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10748 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That <quote>use</quote> of the
10749 recordings is free.
10750 </para>
10751 <para>
10752 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10753 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10754 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am <quote>free</quote> to copy,
10755 or <quote>rip,</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10756 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that <quote>freedom</quote> was a
10757 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the <quote>Rip, Mix, Burn</quote>
10758 capacities of digital technologies.
10759 </para>
10760 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda</primary></indexterm>
10761 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>mix technology and</secondary></indexterm>
10762 <para>
10763 This <quote>use</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10764 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10765 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10766 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10767 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10768 Others&mdash;the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10769 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10770 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10771 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10772 </para>
10773 <para>
10774 This use is enabled by unprotected media&mdash;either CDs or records.
10775 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10776 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10777 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10778 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10779 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10780 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10781 on people's machines.
10782 </para>
10783 <para>
10784 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10785 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10786 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10787 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10788 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10789 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10790
10791 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10792 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10793 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10794 plastic or were part of a massively complex <quote>digital rights
10795 management</quote> system.
10796 </para>
10797 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'/>
10798 <para>
10799 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10800 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10801 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10802 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10803 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10804 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10805 freedom to move content easily?
10806 </para>
10807 <para>
10808 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10809 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10810 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10811 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10812 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10813 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10814 alternative&mdash;namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10815 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10816 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10817 </para>
10818 <para>
10819 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10820 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10821 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10822 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10823 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10824 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10825 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10826 </para>
10827 <para>
10828 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10829 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10830 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10831 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10832 </para>
10833 <para>
10834 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10835 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10836
10837 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10838
10839 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10840 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10841 </para>
10842 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation</primary></indexterm>
10843 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by</primary></indexterm>
10844 <para>
10845 <emphasis role='strong'>There's one more</emphasis> aspect to this
10846 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10847 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10848 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10849 <quote>collateral damage</quote> that <quote>arises whenever you turn
10850 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.</quote> This
10851 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10852 </para>
10853 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10854 <para>
10855 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,</quote> von Lohmann
10856 explains,
10857 </para>
10858 <blockquote>
10859 <para>
10860 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10861 evaporate to one degree or another. &hellip; If you're a copyright
10862 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10863 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10864 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10865 access? &hellip; Our sensibilities change as soon as we think, <quote>Oh, well,
10866 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.</quote> Well, what this campaign
10867 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10868 American Internet-using population into <quote>lawbreakers.</quote>
10869 </para>
10870 </blockquote>
10871 <para>
10872 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10873 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10874 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10875 </para>
10876 <para>
10877 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA
10878 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10879 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10880 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10881 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10882 an Internet user is revealed.
10883 </para>
10884 <para>
10885 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10886 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10887 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10888 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10889 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10890 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10891 the family could be liable for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10892 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10893 Jesse Jordan.<footnote><para>
10894 <!-- f20. -->
10895 See Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10896 Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,</quote>
10897 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, <quote>Worried Parents
10898 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10899 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10900 Being Sued,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson
10901 Graham, <quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 15 September
10902 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, <quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10903 Fan, Either,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 25 September 2003, C1; Margo Varadi, <quote>Is
10904 Brianna a Criminal?</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star</citetitle>, 18 September 2003, P7.
10905 </para></footnote>
10906
10907 </para>
10908 <para>
10909 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10910 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10911 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.<footnote><para>
10912 <!-- f21. -->
10913 See <quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10914 Some Methods Used,</quote> CNN.com, available at
10915 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #47</ulink>.
10916 </para></footnote>
10917 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10918 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10919 one of those MP3s will have the same <quote>fingerprint.</quote>
10920 </para>
10921 <para>
10922 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10923 friend gives a CD to your daughter&mdash;a collection of songs just
10924 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10925 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10926 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10927 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10928 network is <quote>cooperating</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10929 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10930 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10931 as a <quote>criminal.</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10932 to deploy,<footnote><para>
10933 <!-- f22. -->
10934 See Jeff Adler, <quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,</quote>
10935 <citetitle>Boston Globe</citetitle>, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, <quote>Four
10936 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10937 Colleges,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10938 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10939 Monitor</citetitle>, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas, <quote>Music
10940 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10941 Lawsuit Possible,</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 16 July 2003, 1C; Beth Cox, <quote>RIAA
10942 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,</quote> <citetitle>Internet News</citetitle>, 30 January
10943 2003, available at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10944 #48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista, <quote>Download Warning 101: Freshman
10945 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10946 Sharing,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 11 August 2003, E11; <quote>Raid, Letters
10947 Are Weapons at Universities,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 26 September 2000, 3D.
10948 </para></footnote>
10949 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10950 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10951 </para>
10952 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'/>
10953 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred</primary></indexterm>
10954 <para>
10955 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10956 a lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10957 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10958 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10959 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10960 this <quote>contraband</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10961 college students
10962
10963 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10964 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10965 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10966 Says von Lohmann,
10967 </para>
10968 <blockquote>
10969 <para>
10970 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10971 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10972 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10973 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10974 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10975 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10976 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10977 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10978 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10979 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10980 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10981 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10982 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10983 larger number of Americans than drug use. &hellip; If forty to sixty
10984 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10985 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10986 million of them.
10987 </para>
10988 </blockquote>
10989 <para>
10990 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered <quote>criminals</quote> under
10991 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective&mdash;
10992 securing rights to authors&mdash;without these millions being
10993 considered <quote>criminals,</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10994 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10995 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10996 </para>
10997
10998 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10999 </section>
11000 </chapter>
11001 </part>
11002 <part id="c-balances">
11003 <title>Balances</title>
11004 <partintro>
11005
11006 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
11007 <para>
11008 <emphasis role='strong'>So here's</emphasis> the picture: You're
11009 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
11010 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
11011 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
11012 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
11013 </para>
11014 <para>
11015 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
11016 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
11017 stop&mdash;or before she understands just why she should
11018 stop&mdash;the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
11019 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
11020 everything around.
11021 </para>
11022 <para>
11023 <emphasis role='strong'>A war</emphasis> about copyright rages all
11024 around&mdash;and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
11025 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
11026 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
11027 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
11028 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
11029 that if let alone would burn itself out.
11030 </para>
11031 <para>
11032 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
11033 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
11034 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
11035 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
11036 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
11037 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
11038 made that is happening all around.
11039 </para>
11040 <para>
11041 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
11042 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
11043 gasoline onto this fire.
11044 </para>
11045 <para>
11046 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
11047 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
11048 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
11049 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
11050 </para>
11051 <para>
11052 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
11053 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
11054 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
11055 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
11056 success will require.
11057 </para>
11058 </partintro>
11059
11060 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
11061 <chapter label="13" id="eldred">
11062 <title>Chapter Thirteen: Eldred</title>
11063 <indexterm id='idxeldrederic' class='startofrange'><primary>Eldred, Eric</primary></indexterm>
11064 <indexterm id='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='startofrange'><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel</primary></indexterm>
11065 <para>
11066 <emphasis role='strong'>In 1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
11067 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
11068 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
11069 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
11070 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
11071 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
11072 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
11073 </para>
11074 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>of public-domain literature</secondary></indexterm>
11075 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>library of works derived from</secondary></indexterm>
11076 <para>
11077 It didn't work&mdash;at least for his daughters. They didn't find
11078 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
11079 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
11080 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
11081 them available for free.
11082 </para>
11083 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt5' class='startofrange'><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11084 <indexterm><primary>Grimm fairy tales</primary></indexterm>
11085 <para>
11086 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
11087 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
11088 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
11089 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
11090 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
11091 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
11092 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
11093 many others, into a form more accessible&mdash;technically
11094 accessible&mdash;today.
11095 </para>
11096 <indexterm><primary>Scarlet Letter, The (Hawthorne)</primary></indexterm>
11097 <para>
11098 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
11099 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's <citetitle>Scarlet Letter</citetitle> had passed into the
11100 public domain in 1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
11101 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
11102 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
11103 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
11104 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
11105 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (<citetitle>Cinderella</citetitle>), sometimes not
11106 (<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame</citetitle>, <citetitle>Treasure Planet</citetitle>). These are all
11107 commercial publications of public domain works.
11108 </para>
11109 <indexterm startref='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='endofrange'/>
11110 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt5' class='endofrange'/>
11111 <para>
11112 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
11113 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
11114 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
11115 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
11116 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
11117 call the <quote>noncommercial publishing industry,</quote> which before the
11118 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
11119 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
11120 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
11121 generally.<footnote><para>
11122 <!-- f1. -->
11123 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
11124 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
11125 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
11126 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers&mdash;people who
11127 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
11128 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
11129 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
11130 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
11131 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
11132 Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on
11133 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
11134 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
11135 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
11136 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
11137 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
11138 protect noncommercial pornographers.</para></footnote>
11139 </para>
11140 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by</secondary></indexterm>
11141 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11142 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>term extensions in</secondary></indexterm>
11143 <indexterm><primary>Frost, Robert</primary></indexterm>
11144 <indexterm><primary>New Hampshire (Frost)</primary></indexterm>
11145 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>in public domain</secondary></indexterm>
11146 <indexterm id='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in</secondary></indexterm>
11147 <para>
11148 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's
11149 collection of poems <citetitle>New Hampshire</citetitle> was slated to
11150 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
11151 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
11152 in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
11153 linkend="property-i"/>, in 1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
11154 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights&mdash;this time by
11155 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
11156 than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
11157 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
11158 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
11159 more than 1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
11160 </para>
11161 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='endofrange'/>
11162 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='endofrange'/>
11163 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11164 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11165 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>in perpetuity</secondary></indexterm>
11166 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='startofrange'><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11167 <para>
11168
11169 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
11170 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
11171 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
11172 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
11173 <quote>copyrights should be forever.</quote><footnote><para>
11174 <!-- f2. -->
11175 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary</primary></indexterm>
11176 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny</primary></indexterm>
11177 The full text is: <quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
11178 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
11179 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
11180 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
11181 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
11182 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
11183 Congress,</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998).
11184 </para></footnote>
11185 </para>
11186 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'/>
11187 <indexterm><primary>copyright law</primary><secondary>felony punishment for infringement of</secondary></indexterm>
11188 <indexterm><primary>NET (No Electronic Theft) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11189 <indexterm><primary>No Electronic Theft (NET) Act (1998)</primary></indexterm>
11190 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing</primary><secondary>felony punishments for</secondary></indexterm>
11191 <para>
11192 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
11193 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
11194 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
11195 second law passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
11196 of publishing would make Eldred a felon&mdash;whether or not anyone
11197 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
11198 to undertake.
11199 </para>
11200 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='endofrange'/>
11201 <indexterm id='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='startofrange'><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
11202 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
11203 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause2' class='startofrange'><primary>Progress Clause</primary></indexterm>
11204 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11205 <para>
11206 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
11207 constitutional
11208 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
11209 interpretation.
11210 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
11211 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
11212 importantly
11213 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
11214 </para>
11215 <blockquote>
11216 <para>
11217 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science &hellip;
11218 by securing for limited Times to Authors &hellip; exclusive Right to
11219 their &hellip; Writings. &hellip;
11220 </para>
11221 </blockquote>
11222 <indexterm startref='idxeldrederic' class='endofrange'/>
11223 <para>
11224 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
11225 clause of Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
11226 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
11227 something&mdash;for example, to regulate <quote>commerce among the several
11228 states</quote> or <quote>declare War.</quote> But here, the <quote>something</quote> is something quite
11229 specific&mdash;to <quote>promote &hellip; Progress</quote>&mdash;through means that
11230 are also specific&mdash; by <quote>securing</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights</quote> (i.e.,
11231 copyrights) <quote>for limited Times.</quote>
11232 </para>
11233 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='endofrange'/>
11234 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause2' class='endofrange'/>
11235 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='endofrange'/>
11236 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
11237 <para>
11238 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
11239 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
11240 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
11241 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be <quote>limited</quote> will have
11242 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
11243 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
11244 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
11245 what the Constitution plainly forbids&mdash;perpetual terms <quote>on the
11246 installment plan,</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
11247 </para>
11248 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='endofrange'/>
11249 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='endofrange'/>
11250 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of</secondary></indexterm>
11251 <para>
11252 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
11253 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
11254 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
11255 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
11256 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
11257 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
11258 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
11259 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
11260 this gravy train going.
11261 </para>
11262 <para>
11263 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
11264 government. <quote>Corruption</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
11265 bribed. Rather, <quote>corruption</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
11266 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
11267 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
11268 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
11269 do&mdash;and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
11270 </para>
11271 <para>
11272 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
11273 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
11274 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
11275 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry
11276 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
11277 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
11278 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
11279 published by anyone for free.
11280 </para>
11281 <para>
11282 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from
11283 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
11284 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
11285 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
11286 report:
11287 </para>
11288 <para>
11289 <quote>Next year,</quote> the adviser announces, <quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
11290
11291 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
11292 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
11293 receiving the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of
11294 those works.</quote>
11295 </para>
11296 <para>
11297 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,</quote> she continues, <quote>that
11298 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
11299 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
11300 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.</quote>
11301 </para>
11302 <para>
11303 <quote>Hope?</quote> a fellow board member says. <quote>Can't we be doing something
11304 about it?</quote>
11305 </para>
11306 <para>
11307 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>We could contribute
11308 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
11309 they support the bill.</quote>
11310 </para>
11311 <para>
11312 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
11313 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it. <quote>How much
11314 would we get if this extension were passed?</quote> you ask the adviser. <quote>How
11315 much is it worth?</quote>
11316 </para>
11317 <para>
11318 <quote>Well,</quote> the adviser says, <quote>if you're confident that you will continue
11319 to get at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
11320 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent),
11321 then this law would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate.</quote>
11322 </para>
11323 <para>
11324 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
11325 correct conclusion:
11326 </para>
11327 <para>
11328 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
11329 $1,000,000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
11330 contributions
11331 would assure that the bill was passed?</quote>
11332 </para>
11333 <para>
11334 <quote>Absolutely,</quote> the adviser responds. <quote>It is worth it to you to
11335 contribute
11336 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
11337 copyrights. Which for us means over $1,000,000.</quote>
11338 </para>
11339 <para>
11340 You quickly get the point&mdash;you as the member of the board and, I
11341 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
11342 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
11343 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
11344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
11345 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
11346 copyrights
11347 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
11348 the copyright term extended.
11349 </para>
11350 <para>
11351 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
11352 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
11353 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
11354 </para>
11355 <para>
11356 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
11357 Copyright
11358 Term Extension Act, this <quote>theory</quote> about incentives was proved
11359 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
11360 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
11361 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
11362 contributions.<footnote><para>
11363 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press, <quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
11364 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years,</quote>
11365 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune</citetitle>, 17 October 1998, 22.
11366 </para></footnote>
11367 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
11368 $1.5 million lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more
11369 than $200,000 in campaign contributions.<footnote><para>
11370 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown, <quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
11371 Age,</quote> available at
11372 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #49</ulink>.
11373 </para></footnote>
11374 Disney is estimated to have
11375 contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in the
11376 cycle.<footnote><para>
11377 <!-- f5. -->
11378 Alan K. Ota, <quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,</quote>
11379 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week</citetitle>, 8 August 1990, available at
11380 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #50</ulink>.
11381 </para></footnote>
11382
11383 </para>
11384 <para>
11385 <emphasis role='strong'>Constitutional law</emphasis> is not oblivious
11386 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
11387 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
11388 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
11389 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
11390 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
11391 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
11392 constitutional requirement that terms be <quote>limited.</quote> If
11393 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
11394 again.
11395 </para>
11396 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='endofrange'/>
11397 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='endofrange'/>
11398 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='endofrange'/>
11399 <para>
11400 It was also my judgment that <emphasis>this</emphasis> Supreme Court
11401 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
11402 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
11403 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
11404 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
11405 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
11406 Supreme Court's
11407
11408 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
11409 decision in 1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
11410 guns near schools.
11411 </para>
11412 <para>
11413 Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
11414 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
11415 power to regulate only <quote>commerce among the several states</quote> (aka
11416 <quote>interstate
11417 commerce</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
11418 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
11419 interstate
11420 commerce.
11421 </para>
11422 <para>
11423 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
11424 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
11425 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
11426 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
11427 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
11428 </para>
11429 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
11430 <para>
11431 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
11432 that in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The government had
11433 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
11434 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
11435 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
11436 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
11437 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
11438 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
11439 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
11440 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
11441 position to second-guess Congress.
11442 </para>
11443 <para>
11444 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,</quote>
11445 the Chief Justice wrote.<footnote><para>
11446 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995).
11447 </para></footnote>
11448 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
11449 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
11450 Congress's power. The decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
11451 later in <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>.<footnote><para>
11452 <!-- f7. -->
11453 <citetitle>United States</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Morrison</citetitle>, 529 U.S. 598 (2000).
11454 </para></footnote>
11455 </para>
11456 <para>
11457 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
11458 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.<footnote><para>
11459 <!-- f8. -->
11460 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
11461 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
11462 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
11463 by the government would allow the government unending power to
11464 regulate commerce&mdash;the limitation to interstate commerce
11465 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
11466 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
11467 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights&mdash;the
11468 limitation to <quote>limited times</quote> notwithstanding.
11469 </para></footnote>
11470 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
11471 yield the conclusion that Congress
11472 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
11473 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
11474 term, then there would be no <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power over
11475 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
11476 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
11477 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
11478 term of existing copyrights.
11479 </para>
11480 <para>
11481 <emphasis>If</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
11482 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> stood for
11483 politics&mdash;a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
11484 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
11485 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
11486 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
11487 demonstrating the <quote>fidelity</quote> in such an interpretation of the
11488 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
11489 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
11490 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
11491 were going to be petty politicians.
11492 </para>
11493 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in</secondary></indexterm>
11494 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of</secondary></indexterm>
11495 <indexterm><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>duration of</secondary></indexterm>
11496 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt</primary></indexterm>
11497 <para>
11498 <emphasis role='strong'>Now let's pause</emphasis> for a moment to
11499 make sure we understand what the argument in
11500 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
11501 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
11502 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
11503 piracy&mdash;piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
11504 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
11505 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
11506 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
11507 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
11508 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
11509 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
11510 power&mdash;expressed through the power of lobbyists' money&mdash;to
11511 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
11512 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
11513 piracy that affects us all.
11514 </para>
11515 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association</primary></indexterm>
11516 <para>
11517 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
11518
11519 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
11520 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
11521 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than <quote>legal piracy.</quote><footnote><para>
11522 <!-- f9. -->
11523 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11524 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available
11525 at <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #51</ulink>.
11526 </para></footnote>
11527 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
11528 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
11529 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
11530 charter.
11531 </para>
11532 <para>
11533 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
11534 copyright
11535 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
11536 influence
11537 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
11538 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
11539 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
11540 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
11541 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
11542 bought to extend them again.
11543 </para>
11544 <para>
11545 <emphasis role='strong'>It is valuable</emphasis> copyrights that are
11546 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
11547 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.</quote> These works are too valuable for
11548 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
11549 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
11550 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
11551 the 1920s and 1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
11552 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
11553 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
11554 and no longer available as a result.
11555 </para>
11556 <para>
11557 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to
11558 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
11559 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
11560 copyright holders for that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
11561 But the law and its effect were not limited to that 2 percent. The law
11562 extended the terms of copyright generally.<footnote><para>
11563 <!-- f10. --> The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
11564 Congressional
11565 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
11566 of Petitioners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 7, available at
11567 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #52</ulink>.
11568 </para></footnote>
11569
11570 </para>
11571 <indexterm><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
11572 <para>
11573 Think practically about the consequence of this
11574 extension&mdash;practically,
11575 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
11576
11577 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
11578 work. In 1930, 10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those
11579 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
11580 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
11581 remaining
11582 9,873. What would you have to do?
11583 </para>
11584 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11585 <para>
11586 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were
11587 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
11588 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
11589 titles and authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration
11590 and renewal records for works published in 1930. That will produce a
11591 list of books still under copyright.
11592 </para>
11593 <para>
11594 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
11595 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
11596 </para>
11597 <para>
11598 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
11599 owners
11600 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
11601 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
11602 being at least a list?
11603 </para>
11604 <para>
11605 But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in
11606 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
11607 practically
11608 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
11609 thousands
11610 of such records&mdash;especially since the person who registered is
11611 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930!
11612 </para>
11613 <para>
11614 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,</quote> the
11615 apologists for the system respond. <quote>Why should there be a list of
11616 copyright owners?</quote>
11617 </para>
11618 <para>
11619 Well, actually, if you think about it, there <emphasis>are</emphasis>
11620 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
11621 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
11622 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
11623 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
11624 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
11625 what tangible property.
11626 </para>
11627 <para>
11628 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
11629 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
11630 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
11631
11632 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
11633 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
11634 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
11635 happen
11636 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
11637 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
11638 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
11639 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
11640 know quite well who owns what property.
11641 </para>
11642 <para>
11643 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
11644 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
11645 already
11646 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
11647 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
11648 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11649 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11650 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11651 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11652 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11653 </para>
11654 <para>
11655 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11656 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11657 consequence
11658 for other creative works is much more dire.
11659 </para>
11660 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'><primary>Agee, Michael</primary></indexterm>
11661 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
11662 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films</primary></indexterm>
11663 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The</primary></indexterm>
11664 <para>
11665 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11666 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11667 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11668 made between 1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, <citetitle>The Lucky Dog</citetitle>, is
11669 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923
11670 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11671 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11672 money. According to one estimate, <quote>Roach has sold about 60,000
11673 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11674 films.</quote><footnote><para>
11675 <!-- f11. -->
11676 See David G. Savage, <quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,</quote>
11677 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times</citetitle>, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, <quote>Classic Movies,
11678 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11679 Down Copyright Extension,</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune</citetitle>, 9 October 2002.
11680 </para></footnote>
11681 </para>
11682 <para>
11683 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11684 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11685 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11686 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11687 </para>
11688 <para>
11689 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11690
11691 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11692 any continuing commercial value. The rest&mdash;to the extent it
11693 survives at all&mdash;sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11694 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11695 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11696 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11697 work available for distribution.
11698 </para>
11699 <para>
11700 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11701 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11702 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11703 it cost more than $10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11704 film in 1993, it can now cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of
11705 8 mm film.<footnote><para>
11706 <!-- f12. -->
11707 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11708 Supporting the Petitoners, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
11709 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11710 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive, <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle>
11711 v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, available at
11712 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #53</ulink>.
11713 </para></footnote>
11714
11715 </para>
11716 <para>
11717 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11718 important.
11719 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11720 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11721 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11722 locate the copyright owner.
11723 </para>
11724 <para>
11725 Or more accurately, <emphasis>owners</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11726 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11727 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11728 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11729 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11730 to these films is exceptionally high.
11731 </para>
11732 <para>
11733 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11734 copyright owner when she shows up?</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11735 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11736 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11737 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11738 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11739 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11740 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11741 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11742 </para>
11743 <para>
11744 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11745
11746 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11747 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11748 benefit
11749 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11750 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11751 the copyright expires.
11752 </para>
11753 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'/>
11754 <para>
11755 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11756 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11757 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11758 canisters
11759 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11760 than dust.
11761 </para>
11762 <para>
11763 <emphasis role='strong'>Of all the</emphasis> creative work produced
11764 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11765 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11766 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11767 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11768 the copyright acts as an <quote>engine of free expression.</quote>
11769 </para>
11770 <para>
11771 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11772 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11773 indicated,
11774 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11775 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11776 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11777 distributors,
11778 the commercial life ends.
11779 </para>
11780 <para>
11781 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11782 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes &amp; Noble, and
11783 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11784 between
11785 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11786 Friday
11787 night watching a 1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11788 of culture is important and valuable&mdash;for entertainment but also, and
11789 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11790 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11791 have, we need to have access to this history.
11792 </para>
11793 <para>
11794 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11795
11796 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11797 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11798 this context do no good.
11799 </para>
11800 <para>
11801 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11802 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11803 <emphasis>copyright-related use</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11804 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11805 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11806 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11807 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11808 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11809 was independent of copyright law.
11810 </para>
11811 <para>
11812 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11813 a film&mdash;the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs&mdash;were
11814 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11815 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11816 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11817 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11818 market didn't have more to offer.
11819 </para>
11820 <para>
11821 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11822 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11823 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11824 would not have interfered with anything.
11825 </para>
11826 <para>
11827 But this situation has now changed.
11828 </para>
11829 <indexterm id='idxkahlebrewster2' class='startofrange'><primary>Kahle, Brewster</primary></indexterm>
11830 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'><primary>archives, digital</primary></indexterm>
11831 <para>
11832 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11833 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11834 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11835 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11836 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11837 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11838 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11839 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11840 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11841 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11842 </para>
11843 <para>
11844 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11845 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11846 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11847 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11848 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11849 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11850 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11851 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11852 written for a radically different context.
11853 </para>
11854 <para>
11855 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11856 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11857 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11858 <emphasis>copyright</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11859 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11860 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11861 context, copyright is serving no purpose <emphasis>at all</emphasis>
11862 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11863 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11864 </para>
11865 <para>
11866 You may well ask, <quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11867 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11868 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11869 culture widely?</quote>
11870 </para>
11871 <indexterm startref='idxkahlebrewster2' class='endofrange'/>
11872 <para>
11873 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11874 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes &amp; Noble
11875 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11876 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11877 of a library is to serve what <quote>the market</quote> would demand. But if you
11878 think the role of a library is bigger than this&mdash;if you think its
11879 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11880 particular bit of that culture or not&mdash;then we can't count on the
11881 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11882 </para>
11883 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'/>
11884 <para>
11885 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11886 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11887 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11888 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11889
11890 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11891 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11892 culture, 94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11893 1923 and 1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11894 commercial market, if access is a value, then 6 percent is a failure
11895 to provide that value.<footnote><para>
11896 <!-- f13. -->
11897 Jason Schultz, <quote>The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,</quote> 20
11898 December 2002, available at
11899 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #54</ulink>.
11900 </para></footnote>
11901
11902 </para>
11903 <para>
11904 <emphasis role='strong'>In January 1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11905 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11906 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11907 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (1)
11908 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11909 <quote>limited Times</quote> requirement, and (2) that extending terms
11910 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11911 </para>
11912 <para>
11913 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11914 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11915 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11916 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11917 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11918 </para>
11919 <para>
11920 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11921 copyrights be for <quote>limited Times</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11922 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11923 <quote>stopping point</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11924 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11925 terms that are <quote>limited.</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11926 to interpret the term <quote>limited Times</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11927 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11928 power to extend existing terms.
11929 </para>
11930 <para>
11931 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11932 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11933 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11934 whole, where the court will sit <quote>en banc</quote> to hear the case.
11935 </para>
11936 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David</primary></indexterm>
11937 <para>
11938 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11939 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11940
11941 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11942 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11943 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11944 overstepped its bounds.
11945 </para>
11946 <para>
11947 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11948 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11949 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11950 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11951 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11952 </para>
11953 <para>
11954 But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11955 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11956 was set for October of 2002. The summer would be spent writing
11957 briefs and preparing for argument.
11958 </para>
11959 <para>
11960 <emphasis role='strong'>It is over</emphasis> a year later as I write
11961 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11962 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11963 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11964 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11965 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11966 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11967 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11968 client, Eric Eldred.
11969 </para>
11970 <para>
11971 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11972 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11973 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11974 mistake lost it.
11975 </para>
11976 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11977 <indexterm id='idxjonesdayreavisandpoguejonesday' class='startofrange'><primary>Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue (Jones Day)</primary></indexterm>
11978 <para>
11979 <emphasis role='strong'>The mistake</emphasis> was made early, though
11980 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11981 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11982 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11983 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11984 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11985 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11986 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11987 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11988 </para>
11989 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
11990 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan</primary></indexterm>
11991 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey</primary></indexterm>
11992 <para>
11993 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11994 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11995 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11996 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11997 told me, if we could make the issue seem <quote>important</quote> to the Supreme
11998 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11999 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against <quote>the
12000 most powerful media companies in the world.</quote>
12001 </para>
12002 <indexterm startref='idxjonesdayreavisandpoguejonesday' class='endofrange'/>
12003 <para>
12004 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
12005 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
12006 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
12007 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
12008 <quote>right</quote> as in <quote>true,</quote> I thought, but it is <quote>wrong</quote> as in <quote>it just shouldn't be
12009 that way.</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
12010 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
12011 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
12012 interpretation
12013 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
12014 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
12015 unconstitutional,
12016 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
12017 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
12018 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
12019 Constitution,
12020 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
12021 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
12022 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
12023 </para>
12024 <para>
12025 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
12026 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
12027 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
12028 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
12029 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
12030 why it was unconstitutional.
12031 </para>
12032 <para>
12033 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
12034
12035 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
12036 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
12037 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
12038 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
12039 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
12040 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
12041 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
12042 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
12043 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
12044 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
12045 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
12046 <emphasis>law</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
12047 the widest range of credible critics&mdash;credible not because they
12048 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
12049 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
12050 </para>
12051 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
12052 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis</primary></indexterm>
12053 <para>
12054 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
12055 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
12056 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
12057 Congress. In November 1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
12058 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
12059 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
12060 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
12061 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
12062 to get bogged down?</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
12063 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
12064 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
12065 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
12066 </para>
12067 <para>
12068 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
12069 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
12070 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
12071 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
12072 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
12073 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
12074 </para>
12075 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12076 <indexterm><primary>Intel</primary></indexterm>
12077 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
12078 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum</primary></indexterm>
12079 <para>
12080 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
12081 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
12082
12083 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
12084 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/Linux
12085 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
12086 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
12087 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
12088 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
12089 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
12090 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
12091 </para>
12092 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries</primary></indexterm>
12093 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union</primary></indexterm>
12094 <para>
12095 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
12096 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
12097 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
12098 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
12099 </para>
12100 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios</primary></indexterm>
12101 <para>
12102 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
12103 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
12104 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
12105 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
12106 clear.
12107 </para>
12108 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George</primary></indexterm>
12109 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth</primary></indexterm>
12110 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James</primary></indexterm>
12111 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12112 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton</primary></indexterm>
12113 <para>
12114 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
12115 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
12116 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
12117 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
12118 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
12119 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
12120 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
12121 nothing more than <quote>rent-seeking</quote>&mdash;the fancy term economists use
12122 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
12123 </para>
12124 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12125 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan</primary></indexterm>
12126 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen</primary></indexterm>
12127 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12128 <indexterm><primary>Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue (Jones Day)</primary></indexterm>
12129 <para>
12130 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
12131 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
12132 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
12133 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
12134 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
12135 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
12136 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
12137 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
12138
12139 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
12140 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
12141 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
12142 </para>
12143 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12144 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of</secondary></indexterm>
12145 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.</primary><secondary>Commerce Clause of</secondary></indexterm>
12146 <para>
12147 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
12148 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
12149 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
12150 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
12151 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
12152 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
12153 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
12154 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
12155 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
12156 confidence in our argument.
12157 </para>
12158 <para>
12159 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
12160 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these <quote>friends</quote> included
12161 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
12162 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
12163 copyright holders.
12164 </para>
12165 <para>
12166 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
12167 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either&mdash;they
12168 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
12169 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
12170 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
12171 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
12172 wanted to control.
12173 </para>
12174 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George</primary></indexterm>
12175 <indexterm><primary>Porgy and Bess</primary></indexterm>
12176 <indexterm><primary>pornography</primary></indexterm>
12177 <para>
12178 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
12179 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
12180 Dr. Seuss's work&mdash; better than allowing it to fall into the
12181 public domain&mdash;because if this creativity were in the public
12182 domain, then people could use it to <quote>glorify drugs or to create
12183 pornography.</quote><footnote><para>
12184 <!-- f14. -->
12185 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, 537
12186 U.S. (2003) (No. 01-618), 19.
12187 </para></footnote>
12188 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
12189 <quote>protection</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
12190 to license <citetitle>Porgy and Bess</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
12191 Americans in the cast.<footnote><para>
12192 <!-- f15. -->
12193 Dinitia Smith, <quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
12194 Mouse Joins the Fray,</quote> <citetitle>New York Times</citetitle>, 28 March 1998, B7.
12195 </para></footnote>
12196 That's
12197 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
12198 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
12199 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
12200 </para>
12201 <para>
12202 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
12203 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
12204 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
12205 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
12206 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say, <quote>Give us twenty years
12207 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
12208 better with them than anyone else.</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
12209 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
12210 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
12211 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
12212 </para>
12213 <para>
12214 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
12215 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
12216 copyrights&mdash;extensions that would further concentrate the market;
12217 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
12218 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
12219 </para>
12220 <para>
12221 <emphasis role='strong'>Between February</emphasis> and October, there
12222 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
12223 I set the strategy.
12224 </para>
12225 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.</primary></indexterm>
12226 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12227 <para>
12228 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
12229 called <quote>the Conservatives.</quote> The other we called <quote>the Rest.</quote> The
12230 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
12231 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
12232 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
12233 five who had supported the <citetitle>Lopez/Morrison</citetitle> line
12234 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
12235 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
12236 </para>
12237 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12238 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12239 <para>
12240 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
12241 Congress's power. These four&mdash;Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
12242 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer&mdash;had repeatedly argued that
12243 the Constitution
12244 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
12245 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
12246 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
12247 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
12248 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
12249 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
12250 </para>
12251 <para>
12252 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
12253 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
12254 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
12255 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
12256 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
12257 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
12258 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
12259 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
12260 sense.
12261 </para>
12262 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12263 <para>
12264 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
12265 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
12266 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
12267 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
12268 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
12269 these retrospective extensions.
12270 </para>
12271 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'/>
12272 <para>
12273 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
12274 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
12275 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
12276 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
12277 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
12278 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
12279 </para>
12280 <para>
12281 This analysis of <quote>the Rest</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
12282 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
12283 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
12284 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
12285 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation&mdash;the
12286 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
12287 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
12288 powers have limits.
12289 </para>
12290 <para>
12291 This then was the core of our strategy&mdash;a strategy for which I am
12292 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
12293 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>
12294 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
12295 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
12296 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
12297 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
12298 supposed to be <quote>limited.</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
12299 reconcile <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> with
12300 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
12301 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
12302 be limited.
12303 </para>
12304 <para>
12305 <emphasis role='strong'>The argument</emphasis> on the government's
12306 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
12307 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
12308 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
12309 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
12310 that practice is unconstitutional.
12311 </para>
12312 <para>
12313 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
12314 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in 1831
12315 and in 1909. And of course, in 1962, Congress began extending
12316 existing
12317 terms regularly&mdash;eleven times in forty years.
12318 </para>
12319 <para>
12320 But this <quote>consistency</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
12321 extended
12322 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
12323 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
12324 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
12325 existing
12326 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
12327 restraint
12328 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
12329 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
12330 hesitated
12331 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
12332 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
12333 </para>
12334 <para>
12335 <emphasis role='strong'>Oral argument</emphasis> was scheduled for the
12336 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
12337 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
12338 <quote>mooted</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
12339
12340 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
12341 help in the case. Such <quote>moots</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
12342 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
12343 </para>
12344 <para>
12345 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
12346 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
12347 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
12348 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
12349 Congress
12350 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
12351 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
12352 this central idea.
12353 </para>
12354 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12355 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
12356 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12357 <indexterm><primary>Jones, Day, Reavis and Pogue (Jones Day)</primary></indexterm>
12358 <para>
12359 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
12360 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
12361 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
12362 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
12363 </para>
12364 <para>
12365 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
12366 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
12367 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
12368 the harm&mdash;passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
12369 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.</quote>
12370 </para>
12371 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12372 <para>
12373 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
12374 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
12375 right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
12376 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
12377 does the right thing&mdash;not because of politics but because it is right. As
12378 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
12379 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
12380 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
12381 </para>
12382 <para>
12383 <emphasis role='strong'>The night before</emphasis> the argument, a
12384 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
12385 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
12386 culture. Hundreds stood in line
12387
12388 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
12389 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
12390 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
12391 </para>
12392 <para>
12393 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
12394 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
12395 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
12396 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
12397 congressmen
12398 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
12399 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
12400 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
12401 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
12402 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
12403 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
12404 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
12405 family of the Justices.
12406 </para>
12407 <para>
12408 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
12409 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
12410 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
12411 those enumerated powers had any limit.
12412 </para>
12413 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day</primary></indexterm>
12414 <para>
12415 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
12416 The history was bothering her.
12417 </para>
12418 <blockquote>
12419 <para>
12420 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
12421 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
12422 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
12423 practice that began with the very first act.
12424 </para>
12425 </blockquote>
12426 <para>
12427 She was quite willing to concede <quote>that this flies directly in the face
12428 of what the framers had in mind.</quote> But my response again and again
12429 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
12430 </para>
12431 <blockquote>
12432 <para>
12433 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
12434 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
12435 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
12436 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
12437 is yes.
12438 </para>
12439 </blockquote>
12440 <para>
12441 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
12442 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
12443 Kennedy, who observed,
12444 </para>
12445 <blockquote>
12446 <para>
12447 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
12448 the '76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
12449 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
12450 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
12451 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
12452 </para>
12453 </blockquote>
12454 <para>
12455 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
12456 student,
12457 I answered,
12458 </para>
12459 <blockquote>
12460 <para>
12461 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
12462 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
12463 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
12464 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
12465 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
12466 </para>
12467 </blockquote>
12468 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12469 <para>
12470 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
12471 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
12472 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
12473 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
12474 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
12475 </para>
12476 <para>
12477 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
12478 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> ruling,
12479 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
12480 </para>
12481 <para>
12482 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
12483 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
12484
12485 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
12486 </para>
12487 <blockquote>
12488 <para>
12489 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
12490 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
12491 </para>
12492 <para>
12493 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
12494 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
12495 domain
12496 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
12497 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
12498 into the Copyright Clause.
12499 </para>
12500 </blockquote>
12501 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.</primary></indexterm>
12502 <para>
12503 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
12504 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
12505 asked Solicitor General Olson,
12506 </para>
12507 <blockquote>
12508 <para>
12509 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12510 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
12511 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
12512 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12513 time.
12514 </para>
12515 </blockquote>
12516 <para>
12517 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
12518 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
12519 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
12520 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
12521 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
12522 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
12523 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
12524 Patent Clause&mdash; indeed, the very first case striking a law of
12525 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
12526 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
12527 Court to my side.
12528 </para>
12529 <para>
12530 <emphasis role='strong'>As I left</emphasis> the court that day, I
12531 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
12532 hundred questions I wished I had
12533
12534 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
12535 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
12536 optimistic.
12537 </para>
12538 <para>
12539 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
12540 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
12541 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
12542 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
12543 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
12544 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
12545 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
12546 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
12547 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
12548 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
12549 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court&mdash;in particular,
12550 the Conservatives&mdash;would feel itself constrained by the rule of
12551 law that it had established elsewhere.
12552 </para>
12553 <para>
12554 <emphasis role='strong'>The morning</emphasis> of January 15, 2003, I
12555 was five minutes late to the office and missed the 7:00 A.M. call from
12556 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
12557 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
12558 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
12559 majority. There were two dissents.
12560 </para>
12561 <para>
12562 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
12563 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
12564 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
12565 </para>
12566 <para>
12567 My <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
12568 money in the world against <emphasis>reasoning</emphasis>. And here
12569 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
12570 reasoning.
12571 </para>
12572 <para>
12573 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
12574 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
12575 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
12576 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
12577 even appear in the Court's opinion.
12578 </para>
12579 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader</primary></indexterm>
12580 <para>
12581
12582 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
12583 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
12584 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
12585 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
12586 </para>
12587 <para>
12588 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable&mdash;for her, and for Justice
12589 Souter. Neither believes in <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
12590 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
12591 they had worked so hard to defeat.
12592 </para>
12593 <para>
12594 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
12595 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
12596 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
12597 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
12598 reconcile the two simply <emphasis>by not addressing the
12599 argument</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
12600 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
12601 followed from the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
12602 be limited, but in this context it would not.
12603 </para>
12604 <para>
12605 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
12606 they would respect? By what right did they&mdash;the silent
12607 five&mdash;get to select the part of the Constitution they would
12608 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
12609 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
12610 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
12611 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
12612 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
12613 the system we have.
12614 </para>
12615 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12616 <para>
12617 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
12618 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
12619 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
12620 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
12621 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
12622 the Court discounted the parallel&mdash;without explaining how the
12623 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
12624 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
12625 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
12626 </para>
12627 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen</primary></indexterm>
12628 <para>
12629 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
12630 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
12631 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
12632 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
12633 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8
12634 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
12635 that the actual number was 99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
12636 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
12637 <quote>limited,</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
12638 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
12639 </para>
12640 <para>
12641 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
12642 because neither believed in the <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
12643 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
12644 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
12645 Sentelle. It was <citetitle>Hamlet</citetitle> without the Prince.
12646 </para>
12647 <para>
12648 <emphasis role='strong'>Defeat brings depression</emphasis>. They say
12649 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
12650 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
12651 sorts.
12652 </para>
12653 <indexterm><primary>originalism</primary></indexterm>
12654 <para>
12655 It was first anger with the five <quote>Conservatives.</quote> It would have been
12656 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> didn't
12657 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
12658 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12659 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12660 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12661 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is <quote>originalism</quote>&mdash;to
12662 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12663 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12664 <citetitle>Lopez</citetitle> and many other <quote>originalist</quote> rulings. Where was their
12665 <quote>originalism</quote> now?
12666 </para>
12667 <para>
12668 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12669 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12670 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12671 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12672
12673 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12674 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12675 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12676 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12677 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12678 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12679 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12680 own principles.
12681 </para>
12682 <para>
12683 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12684 myself.
12685 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12686 the law as it is.
12687 </para>
12688 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12689 <para>
12690 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12691 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12692 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12693 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12694 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12695 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12696 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12697 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12698 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12699 </para>
12700 <para>
12701 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12702 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12703 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12704 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12705 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12706 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12707 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12708 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12709 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12710 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12711 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12712 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12713 effort to persuade; but I
12714 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12715 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12716 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12717 should decide the issue.
12718 </para>
12719 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12720 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles</primary></indexterm>
12721 <para>
12722 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12723 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12724 Kathleen Sullivan?
12725 </para>
12726 <para>
12727 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12728 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12729 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12730 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12731 </para>
12732 <para>
12733 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12734 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12735 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12736 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12737 have persuaded.
12738 </para>
12739 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter</primary></indexterm>
12740 <para>
12741 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12742 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12743 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12744 case was a mistake. <quote>The Court is not ready,</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12745 issue should not be raised until it is.
12746 </para>
12747 <para>
12748 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12749 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12750 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12751 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12752 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12753 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12754 this case&mdash;a decision I had made four years before&mdash;was wrong.
12755 </para>
12756 <para>
12757 <emphasis role='strong'>While the reaction</emphasis> to the Sonny
12758 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12759 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12760 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12761 that battle over ideas. Where
12762
12763 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12764 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12765 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12766 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12767 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12768 harmful law. <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12769 </para>
12770 <blockquote>
12771 <para>
12772 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12773 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12774 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12775 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12776 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12777 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12778 </para>
12779 </blockquote>
12780 <para>
12781 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12782 hilarious images&mdash;of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12783 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced in figure
12784 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-18"/>. The <quote>powerful
12785 and wealthy</quote> line is a bit unfair. But the punch in the face
12786 felt exactly like that.
12787 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12788 </para>
12789 <figure id="fig-18" float="1">
12790 <title></title>
12791 <graphic fileref="images/tom-the-dancing-bug.png" align="center" width="100%"></graphic>
12792 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben</primary></indexterm>
12793 </figure>
12794 <para>
12795 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12796 quote from <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>. That <quote>grand experiment</quote> we call the
12797 <quote>public domain</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think, <quote>Honey,
12798 I shrunk the Constitution.</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12799 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12800 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12801 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12802 </para>
12803 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12804 </chapter>
12805 <chapter label="14" id="eldred-ii">
12806 <title>Chapter Fourteen: Eldred II</title>
12807 <para>
12808 <emphasis role='strong'>The day</emphasis>
12809 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12810 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12811 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> was denied&mdash;meaning the case was
12812 really finally over&mdash;fate would have it that I was giving a
12813 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12814 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12815 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12816 wrote an op-ed piece.
12817 </para>
12818 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don</primary></indexterm>
12819 <para>
12820 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12821 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12822 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12823 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12824 Justice Kennedy: <quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12825 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12826 that.</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12827 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12828 </para>
12829 <para>
12830 <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12831 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12832 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12833 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12834 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12835 the work passed into the public domain.
12836 </para>
12837 <para>
12838 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12839 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12840 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12841 </para>
12842 <para>
12843 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12844 is either the <quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act</quote> or the <quote>Copyright
12845 Term Deregulation Act.</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12846 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12847 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12848 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $1. But for
12849 everything else, let the content go.
12850 </para>
12851 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
12852 <para>
12853 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12854 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12855 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12856 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12857 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12858 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12859 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12860 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12861 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12862 the stupid harm of the present system.
12863 </para>
12864 <para>
12865 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12866 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12867 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12868 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12869 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12870 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12871 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12872 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12873 where copyright owners could be identified.
12874 </para>
12875 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12876 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12877 <para>
12878 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12879 As I described in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
12880 linkend="property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12881 removed in 1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12882 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.<footnote><para>
12883 <!-- f1. -->
12884 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law</primary></indexterm>
12885 Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12886 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12887 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12888 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act,
12889 every text of the Convention has provided that <quote>the enjoyment and the
12890 exercise</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention <quote>shall not be subject
12891 to any formality.</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12892 embodied in Article 5(2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12893 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12894 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12895 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12896 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12897 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12898 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12899 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12900 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>International
12901 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12902 Press, 2001), 153&ndash;54. </para></footnote>
12903 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a <quote>natural right.</quote> Natural
12904 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12905 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12906 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12907 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12908 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12909 </para>
12910 <para>
12911 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12912 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12913 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12914 <quote>Walt Disney creativity</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12915 know what's protected and what's not.
12916 </para>
12917 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (1908)</primary></indexterm>
12918 <para>
12919 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12920 Berlin in 1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12921 Convention in 1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12922 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12923 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12924 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12925 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an <citetitle>i</citetitle> or cross a
12926 <citetitle>t</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12927 </para>
12928 <para>
12929 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12930 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12931 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12932 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12933 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12934 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12935 </para>
12936 <para>
12937 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12938 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12939 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12940 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12941 burden
12942 imposed upon creators.
12943 </para>
12944 <para>
12945 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was
12946 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12947
12948 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12949 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12950 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12951 the government. He has a property right over the table <quote>naturally,</quote>
12952 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12953 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12954 table.
12955 </para>
12956 <para>
12957 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12958 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12959 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12960 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12961 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12962 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12963 spread.
12964 </para>
12965 <para>
12966 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12967 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12968 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12969 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12970 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12971 important reason to secure registration&mdash;both because it makes
12972 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12973 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12974 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12975 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12976 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12977 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12978 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12979 system of protection for property generally.
12980 </para>
12981 <para>
12982 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12983 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12984 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12985 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12986 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12987 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12988 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12989 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12990
12991 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12992 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12993 <emphasis>lawyer</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12994 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle</primary></indexterm>
12995 </para>
12996 <para>
12997 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12998 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12999 didn't <quote>get.</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
13000 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
13001 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be, <quote>short,</quote> then this
13002 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
13003 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
13004 be presumptively uncontrolled.
13005 </para>
13006 <para>
13007 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
13008 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
13009 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
13010 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
13011 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
13012 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
13013 seen before <emphasis>because there are no formalities</emphasis>.
13014 </para>
13015 <para>
13016 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
13017 it is worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
13018 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
13019 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
13020 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
13021 </para>
13022 <para>
13023 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
13024 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
13025 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
13026 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
13027 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you.
13028 </para>
13029 <para>
13030 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
13031 registering the work mean that the $1 is really misleading? Isn't the
13032 hassle worth more than $1? Isn't that the real problem with
13033 registration?
13034 </para>
13035 <para>
13036 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
13037 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
13038 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
13039
13040 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
13041 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
13042 address the real problem of <emphasis>governments</emphasis> standing
13043 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
13044 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
13045 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
13046 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
13047 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
13048 upon historical data, that system would move up to 98 percent of
13049 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
13050 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
13051 </para>
13052 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve</primary></indexterm>
13053 <para>
13054 <emphasis role='strong'>When Steve Forbes</emphasis> endorsed the
13055 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
13056 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
13057 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
13058 willing to take the first step.
13059 </para>
13060 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe</primary></indexterm>
13061 <para>
13062 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
13063 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
13064 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
13065 possible. In May 2003, it looked as if the bill would be
13066 introduced. On May 16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog, <quote>we are
13067 close.</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
13068 something good might happen here.
13069 </para>
13070 <para>
13071 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
13072 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
13073 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
13074 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
13075 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
13076 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
13077 </para>
13078 <para>
13079 The MPAA argued first that Congress had <quote>firmly rejected the central
13080 concept in the proposed bill</quote>&mdash;that copyrights be renewed. That
13081 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's <quote>firm rejection</quote> had occurred
13082 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
13083 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
13084 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
13085 owners&mdash;apparently those who could not afford the $1 fee. Third,
13086 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
13087 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
13088 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
13089 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
13090 off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
13091 argued that the bill would impose <quote>enormous</quote> costs, since a
13092 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
13093 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
13094 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
13095 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
13096 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
13097 film is a valid derivative use.
13098 </para>
13099 <para>
13100 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
13101 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
13102 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
13103 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
13104 or not&mdash;a controversial claim in any case&mdash;unless they know
13105 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
13106 </para>
13107 <para>
13108 <emphasis role='strong'>At the beginning</emphasis> of this book, I
13109 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
13110 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
13111 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
13112 opposition&mdash;the power of the side that fought to defend the
13113 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
13114 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
13115 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
13116 </para>
13117 <para>
13118 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
13119 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
13120 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
13121 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
13122 sense?
13123 </para>
13124 <para>
13125
13126 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
13127 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
13128 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
13129 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
13130 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
13131 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
13132 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
13133 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
13134 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
13135 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
13136 </para>
13137 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin</primary></indexterm>
13138 <para>
13139 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
13140 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
13141 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
13142 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
13143 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
13144 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the <quote>Dark
13145 Content</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
13146 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
13147 </para>
13148 <para>
13149 What does this industry really want?
13150 </para>
13151 <para>
13152 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
13153 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
13154 protecting <emphasis>their</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
13155 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
13156 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
13157 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
13158 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
13159 content that doesn't require <emphasis>their</emphasis> permission
13160 first.
13161 </para>
13162 <para>
13163 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
13164 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
13165 its aim not the protection of <quote>property</quote> but the rejection of a
13166 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
13167 theirs. <emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
13168 theirs</emphasis>.
13169 </para>
13170 <para>
13171 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
13172 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
13173
13174 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
13175 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
13176 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
13177 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
13178 and to share its own creation.
13179 </para>
13180 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13181 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13182 <para>
13183 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
13184 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
13185 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
13186 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
13187 block the progress of others.
13188 </para>
13189 <para>
13190 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
13191 <quote>property</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
13192 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
13193 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing <quote>permission
13194 society.</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
13195 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
13196 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
13197 </para>
13198 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
13199 </chapter>
13200 </part>
13201 <chapter label="" id="c-conclusion">
13202 <title>Conclusion</title>
13203 <indexterm id='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='startofrange'><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in</primary></indexterm>
13204 <indexterm id='idxaidsmedications' class='startofrange'><primary>AIDS medications</primary></indexterm>
13205 <indexterm id='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='startofrange'><primary>antiretroviral drugs</primary></indexterm>
13206 <indexterm id='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='startofrange'><primary>developing countries, foreign patent costs in</primary></indexterm>
13207 <indexterm id='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='startofrange'><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13208 <indexterm id='idxhivaidstherapies' class='startofrange'><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies</primary></indexterm>
13209 <para>
13210 <emphasis role='strong'>There are more</emphasis> than 35 million
13211 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
13212 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
13213 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
13214 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
13215 </para>
13216 <para>
13217 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
13218 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
13219 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
13220 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
13221 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
13222 the disease almost invisible.
13223 </para>
13224 <para>
13225 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
13226 United States, they cost between $10,000 and $15,000 per person per
13227 year. Today, some cost $25,000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
13228 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
13229 population:
13230 $15,000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
13231 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.<footnote><para>
13232 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, <quote>Final Report: Integrating
13233 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy</quote> (London, 2002),
13234 available at
13235 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
13236 release
13237 issued 9 July 2002, only 230,000 of the 6 million who need drugs in
13238 the developing world receive them&mdash;and half of them are in Brazil.
13239 </para></footnote>
13240 </para>
13241 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='startofrange'><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13242 <indexterm id='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>pharmaceutical patents</primary></indexterm>
13243 <para>
13244 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
13245 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
13246 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
13247 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
13248 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
13249 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
13250 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
13251 </para>
13252 <para>
13253 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
13254 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
13255 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
13256 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
13257 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
13258 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
13259 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
13260 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
13261 changes.
13262 </para>
13263 <para>
13264 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
13265 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
13266 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
13267 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
13268 costs significantly below the market price.
13269 </para>
13270 <indexterm id='idxinternationallaw2' class='startofrange'><primary>international law</primary></indexterm>
13271 <indexterm id='idxparallelimportation' class='startofrange'><primary>parallel importation</primary></indexterm>
13272 <indexterm id='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='startofrange'><primary>South Africa, Republic of, pharmaceutical imports by</primary></indexterm>
13273 <para>
13274 In 1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
13275 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
13276 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
13277 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
13278 Africa from India. This is called <quote>parallel importation,</quote> and it is
13279 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
13280 permitted within the European Union.<footnote>
13281 <para>
13282 <!-- f2. -->
13283 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
13284 Owns the Knowledge Economy?</citetitle> (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37.
13285 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13286 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13287 </para></footnote>
13288 </para>
13289 <indexterm><primary>United States Trade Representative (USTR)</primary></indexterm>
13290 <para>
13291 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
13292 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
13293 characterized it, <quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa &hellip;
13294 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
13295 imports.</quote><footnote><para>
13296 <!-- f3. -->
13297 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13298 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13299 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13300 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 14, available at
13301 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #56</ulink>. For a
13302 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
13303 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
13304 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess.,
13305 Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150&ndash;57 (statement of James
13306 Love).
13307 </para></footnote>
13308 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
13309 government asked South Africa to change the law&mdash;and to add
13310 pressure to that request, in 1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
13311 possible trade sanctions.
13312 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
13313 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
13314 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
13315 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
13316 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
13317 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
13318 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
13319 patent&mdash; pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
13320 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
13321 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
13322 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.<footnote><para>
13323 <!-- f4. -->
13324 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), <citetitle>Patent
13325 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13326 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13327 Organization</citetitle> (Washington, D.C., 2000), 15. </para></footnote>
13328 </para>
13329 <indexterm startref='idxparallelimportation' class='endofrange'/>
13330 <para>
13331 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
13332 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
13333 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
13334 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
13335 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
13336 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
13337 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
13338 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
13339 </para>
13340 <para>
13341 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
13342 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
13343 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
13344 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
13345 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
13346 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save 15 to 30 million lives.
13347 </para>
13348 <para>
13349 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
13350 profits of United States drug companies&mdash;at least, not substantially. It
13351 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
13352 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
13353 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
13354 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
13355 by U.S. companies.
13356 </para>
13357 <para>
13358 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
13359 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
13360 argument
13361 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
13362 about the sanctity of property.<footnote><para>
13363 <!-- f5. -->
13364 See Sabin Russell, <quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
13365 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle</citetitle>, 24
13366 May 1999, A1, available at
13367 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #57</ulink>
13368 (<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
13369 system of intellectual property protection</quote>); Robert Weissman, <quote>AIDS
13370 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
13371 Medicines,</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus</citetitle> 4:23 (August 1999), available at
13372 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #58</ulink>
13373 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, <quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
13374 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
13375 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
13376 Symposium Journal</citetitle> (Spring 2001): 175.
13377 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
13378 </para></footnote>
13379 It was because <quote>intellectual property</quote> would be violated that these
13380 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
13381 importance of <quote>intellectual property</quote> that led these government actors
13382 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
13383 </para>
13384 <indexterm startref='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='endofrange'/>
13385 <para>
13386 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
13387 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
13388 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
13389 direct cost would be to speed the death of 15 to 30 million Africans,
13390 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the <quote>sanctity</quote> of an
13391 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
13392 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
13393 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
13394 </para>
13395 <indexterm id='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='startofrange'><primary>corporations</primary><secondary>in pharmaceutical industry</secondary></indexterm>
13396 <para>
13397 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
13398 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
13399 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
13400 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
13401 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system&mdash;
13402 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
13403 </para>
13404 <para>
13405 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
13406 drug companies would love&mdash;they say, and I believe them&mdash;to
13407 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
13408 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
13409 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
13410 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
13411 </para>
13412 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>of drug patents</secondary></indexterm>
13413 <para>
13414 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
13415 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
13416 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask, <quote>How
13417 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $1 a pill, but the same
13418 drug would cost an American $1,500?</quote> Because there is no <quote>sound
13419 bite</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
13420 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
13421 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
13422 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
13423 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
13424 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
13425 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal&mdash;the sanctity of an
13426 idea called <quote>intellectual property.</quote>
13427 </para>
13428 <indexterm startref='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='endofrange'/>
13429 <indexterm startref='idxaidsmedications' class='endofrange'/>
13430 <indexterm startref='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='endofrange'/>
13431 <indexterm startref='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='endofrange'/>
13432 <indexterm startref='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='endofrange'/>
13433 <indexterm startref='idxhivaidstherapies' class='endofrange'/>
13434 <indexterm startref='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='endofrange'/>
13435 <para>
13436 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
13437 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
13438 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
13439 What is the argument?
13440 </para>
13441 <para>
13442 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
13443 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
13444 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
13445 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
13446 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
13447 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
13448 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
13449 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
13450 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
13451 were balanced in just this sense.
13452 </para>
13453 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='endofrange'/>
13454 <indexterm startref='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13455 <indexterm startref='idxinternationallaw2' class='endofrange'/>
13456 <para>
13457 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
13458 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
13459 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
13460 our tradition, now reigns in this culture&mdash;bizarrely, and with
13461 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
13462 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
13463 </para>
13464 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='endofrange'/>
13465 <para>
13466 <emphasis role='strong'>A simple idea</emphasis> blinds us, and under
13467 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
13468 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
13469 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
13470 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
13471 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
13472 control of that property removes our
13473 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
13474 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
13475 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
13476 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
13477 this common sense open its eyes.
13478 </para>
13479 <para>
13480 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
13481 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
13482 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
13483 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
13484 to fight <quote>piracy,</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
13485 the idea of <quote>creative property,</quote> while transforming real creators into
13486 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
13487 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
13488 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
13489 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
13490 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
13491 produce the <quote>perfect storm</quote> for free culture.
13492 </para>
13493 <indexterm><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
13494 <indexterm><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13495 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13496 <indexterm><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
13497 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13498 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
13499 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
13500 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>public projects in</secondary></indexterm>
13501 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)</primary></indexterm>
13502 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust</primary></indexterm>
13503 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13504 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web</primary></indexterm>
13505 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System</primary></indexterm>
13506 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald</primary></indexterm>
13507 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'><primary>biomedical research</primary></indexterm>
13508 <para>
13509 <emphasis role='strong'>In August 2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
13510 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
13511 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.<footnote><para>
13512 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>,
13513 August 2003, E1, available at
13514 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #59</ulink>; William New, <quote>Global Group's
13515 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13516 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13517 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #60</ulink>; William New, <quote>U.S. Official
13518 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13519 Daily</citetitle>, 19 August 2003, available at
13520 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #61</ulink>.
13521 </para></footnote>
13522 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
13523 a meeting to discuss <quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
13524 goods.</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
13525 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
13526 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
13527 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
13528 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
13529 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
13530 that I describe in chapter
13531 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="c-afterword"/>. It
13532 included a project to develop single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs),
13533 which are thought to have great significance in biomedical
13534 research. (That nonprofit project comprised a consortium of the
13535 Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and technological companies,
13536 including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
13537 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
13538 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
13539 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
13540 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
13541 in the early 1980s. And it included <quote>open source and free software.</quote>
13542 </para>
13543 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'/>
13544 <para>
13545 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
13546 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
13547 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
13548 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
13549 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
13550 </para>
13551 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='startofrange'><primary>Lessig, Lawrence</primary><secondary>in international debate on intellectual property</secondary></indexterm>
13552 <para>
13553 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.<footnote><para>
13554 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
13555 meeting.
13556 </para></footnote>
13557 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
13558 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
13559 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
13560 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
13561 property issues.
13562 </para>
13563 <indexterm id='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='startofrange'><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13564 <para>
13565 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
13566 about WIPO. In February 2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
13567 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
13568 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
13569 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
13570 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
13571 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
13572 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
13573 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
13574 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
13575 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
13576 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
13577 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
13578 talk about an <quote>Information Society</quote> unless one also talked about the
13579 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
13580 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
13581 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
13582 stuff of
13583 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
13584 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
13585 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
13586 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
13587 </para>
13588 <para>
13589 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
13590 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
13591 thus the meeting about <quote>open and collaborative projects to create
13592 public goods</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
13593 </para>
13594 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='endofrange'/>
13595 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='endofrange'/>
13596 <indexterm startref='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='endofrange'/>
13597 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
13598 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
13599 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='startofrange'><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>on free software</secondary></indexterm>
13600 <para>
13601 But there is one project within that list that is highly
13602 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is <quote>open source
13603 and free software.</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
13604 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
13605 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
13606 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
13607 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
13608 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
13609 rather than <quote>proprietary software,</quote> for their own internal uses.
13610 </para>
13611 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft</quote> licenses</primary></indexterm>
13612 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13613 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
13614 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
13615 <para>
13616 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
13617 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
13618 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
13619 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
13620 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
13621 operating system, the most famous bit of <quote>free software</quote>&mdash;and IBM
13622 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support <quote>open source and
13623 free software</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
13624 to support a mode of software development that is different from
13625 Microsoft's.<footnote><para>
13626 <!-- f8. -->
13627 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
13628 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
13629 <quote>open source</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
13630 principal opposition is to <quote>free software</quote> licensed under a <quote>copyleft</quote>
13631 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
13632 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith, <quote>The Future
13633 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
13634 Toward Open Source Software</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
13635 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
13636 Public Policy Research, 2002), 69, available at
13637 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #62</ulink>. See also
13638 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president, <citetitle>The Commercial Software
13639 Model</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (3
13640 May 2001), available at
13641 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #63</ulink>.
13642 </para></footnote>
13643 </para>
13644 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='endofrange'/>
13645 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)</primary></indexterm>
13646 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)</primary></indexterm>
13647 <para>
13648 More important for our purposes, to support <quote>open source and free
13649 software</quote> is not to oppose copyright. <quote>Open source and free software</quote>
13650 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
13651 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
13652 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
13653 by
13654 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
13655 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
13656 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
13657 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
13658 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
13659 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
13660 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
13661 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
13662 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
13663 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
13664 </para>
13665 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='startofrange'><primary>intellectual property rights</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of</secondary></indexterm>
13666 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='startofrange'><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)</primary></indexterm>
13667 <indexterm id='idxkrimjonathan' class='startofrange'><primary>Krim, Jonathan</primary></indexterm>
13668 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by</secondary></indexterm>
13669 <para>
13670 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
13671 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
13672 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
13673 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
13674 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
13675 <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
13676 States government to veto the meeting.<footnote><para>
13677 <!-- f9. -->
13678 Krim, <quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,</quote> available at <ulink
13679 url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #64</ulink>.
13680 </para></footnote>
13681 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
13682 </para>
13683 <para>
13684 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
13685 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
13686 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
13687 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
13688 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
13689 its lobbying efforts.
13690 </para>
13691 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='endofrange'/>
13692 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13693 <indexterm id='idxpatentandtrademarkofficeus' class='startofrange'><primary>Patent and Trademark Office, U.S.</primary></indexterm>
13694 <para>
13695 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
13696 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
13697 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
13698 Office, explained that <quote>open-source software runs counter to the
13699 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.</quote>
13700 She is quoted as saying, <quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13701 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13702 goals of WIPO.</quote>
13703 </para>
13704 <indexterm startref='idxkrimjonathan' class='endofrange'/>
13705 <para>
13706 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13707 </para>
13708 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='endofrange'/>
13709 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13710 <para>
13711 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13712 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13713 right called <quote>copyright</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13714 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it <quote>runs counter</quote> to the mission
13715 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13716 in understanding&mdash;the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13717 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13718 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13719 </para>
13720 <indexterm><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)</primary></indexterm>
13721 <indexterm><primary>drugs</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical</secondary></indexterm>
13722 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs</primary></indexterm>
13723 <indexterm><primary>patents</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals</secondary></indexterm>
13724 <para>
13725 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to <quote>promote</quote>
13726 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13727 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13728 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13729 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13730 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13731 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13732 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13733 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13734 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13735 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13736 </para>
13737 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill</primary></indexterm>
13738 <para>
13739 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13740 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13741 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13742 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13743 <emphasis>their</emphasis> rights. If they want to <quote>waive</quote> or
13744 <quote>disclaim</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13745 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $20 billion to do
13746 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13747 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13748 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13749 to do with <emphasis>their</emphasis> property.
13750 </para>
13751 <indexterm id='idxbolandlois' class='startofrange'><primary>Boland, Lois</primary></indexterm>
13752 <para>
13753 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13754 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,</quote> she's
13755 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13756 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13757 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13758 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from <quote>waiving</quote> or
13759 <quote>disclaiming</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13760 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13761 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13762 way possible.
13763 </para>
13764 <indexterm id='idxfeudalsystem' class='startofrange'><primary>feudal system</primary></indexterm>
13765 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='startofrange'><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>feudal system of</secondary></indexterm>
13766 <para>
13767 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13768 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called <quote>feudalism.</quote> Under
13769 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13770 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13771 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13772 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13773 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13774 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13775 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13776 that control.
13777 </para>
13778 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13779 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John</primary></indexterm>
13780 <para>
13781 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13782 choice we are now making about intellectual property.<footnote><para>
13783 <!-- f10. -->
13784 See Drahos with Braithwaite, <citetitle>Information Feudalism</citetitle>, 210&ndash;20.
13785 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter</primary></indexterm>
13786 </para></footnote>
13787 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13788 choice now is whether that information society will be
13789 <emphasis>free</emphasis> or <emphasis>feudal</emphasis>. The trend is
13790 toward the feudal.
13791 </para>
13792 <indexterm startref='idxfeudalsystem' class='endofrange'/>
13793 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='endofrange'/>
13794 <para>
13795 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13796 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13797 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13798 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13799 </para>
13800 <blockquote>
13801 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='endofrange'/>
13802 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='endofrange'/>
13803 <para>
13804 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13805 it should be (<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13806 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13807 not simply to promote intellectual property rights</quote>), not as it is. If
13808 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13809 say anything wrong. But in the world
13810 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13811 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13812 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13813 </para>
13814 </blockquote>
13815 <para>
13816 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13817 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13818 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13819 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13820 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13821 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13822 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13823 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13824 </para>
13825 <indexterm startref='idxbolandlois' class='endofrange'/>
13826 <para>
13827 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13828 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13829 <quote>goal</quote> of a government should be <quote>to promote the right balance</quote> of
13830 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13831 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism. <quote>Typical for
13832 an academic,</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13833 </para>
13834 <para>
13835 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13836 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13837 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13838 our own country's history).
13839 </para>
13840 <para>
13841 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13842 government should be to <quote>seek balance,</quote> then count me with the silly,
13843 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13844 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13845 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13846 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13847 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13848 not lies is just na&iuml;ve, then who have we, the most powerful
13849 democracy in the world, become?
13850 </para>
13851 <para>
13852 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13853 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13854 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13855 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13856 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13857 been part of our tradition for most of our history&mdash;free culture.
13858 </para>
13859 <indexterm startref='idxpatentandtrademarkofficeus' class='endofrange'/>
13860 <para>
13861 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13862 </para>
13863 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace</primary></indexterm>
13864 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William</primary></indexterm>
13865 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted</primary></indexterm>
13866 <para>
13867 <emphasis role='strong'>There are moments</emphasis> of hope in this
13868 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13869 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13870 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13871 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13872 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13873 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13874 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing 700,000 letters were
13875 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13876 </para>
13877 <para>
13878 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13879 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13880 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13881 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13882 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13883 concentration in the media.
13884 </para>
13885 <para>
13886 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13887 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13888 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13889 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13890 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13891 </para>
13892 <para>
13893 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13894 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13895 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13896 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13897 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13898 range of rights&mdash;property rights of a historically extreme
13899 form&mdash;that makes their bigness bad.
13900 </para>
13901 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13902 <para>
13903 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13904 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13905 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13906 Americans have a long history of fighting <quote>big,</quote> wisely or not. That
13907 we could be motivated to fight <quote>big</quote> again is not something new.
13908 </para>
13909 <para>
13910 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13911 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13912 the idea of <quote>intellectual property.</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13913 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13914 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13915 called <quote>property</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13916 </para>
13917 <para>
13918 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13919 of our tragedy.
13920 </para>
13921 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob</primary></indexterm>
13922 <para>
13923 <emphasis role='strong'>As I write</emphasis> these final words, the
13924 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13925 three hundred individuals.<footnote><para>
13926 <!-- f11. -->
13927 John Borland, <quote>RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers,</quote> CNET News.com, September
13928 2003, available at
13929 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #65</ulink>; Paul
13930 R. La Monica, <quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,</quote> CNN/Money, 8 September
13931 2003, available at
13932 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #66</ulink>; Soni
13933 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty, <quote>Sued for a Song,
13934 N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among 261 Cited as Sharers,</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News</citetitle>, 9
13935 September 2003, 3; Frank Ahrens, <quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13936 Targets; Single Mother in Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13937 Defendants,</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 10 September 2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13938 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,</quote> <citetitle>Wired News</citetitle>, 10 September 2003,
13939 available at
13940 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #67</ulink>.
13941 </para></footnote>
13942 Eminem has just been sued for <quote>sampling</quote> someone else's
13943 music.<footnote><para>
13944 <!-- f12. -->
13945 Jon Wiederhorn, <quote>Eminem Gets Sued &hellip; by a Little Old Lady,</quote>
13946 mtv.com, 17 September 2003, available at
13947 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #68</ulink>.
13948 </para></footnote>
13949 The story about Bob Dylan <quote>stealing</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13950 finished making the rounds.<footnote><para>
13951 <!-- f13. -->
13952 Kenji Hall, Associated Press, <quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13953 Dylan Songs,</quote> Kansascity.com, 9 July 2003, available at
13954 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #69</ulink>.
13955 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13956 </para></footnote>
13957 An insider from Hollywood&mdash;who insists he must remain
13958 anonymous&mdash;reports <quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13959 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13960 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13961 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13962 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.</quote> Congressmen are
13963 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13964 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13965 kids who use a computer to share content.
13966 </para>
13967 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee</primary></indexterm>
13968 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie</primary></indexterm>
13969 <indexterm><primary>BBC</primary></indexterm>
13970 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in</primary></indexterm>
13971 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
13972 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto</primary></indexterm>
13973 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom</primary><secondary>public creative archive in</secondary></indexterm>
13974 <para>
13975 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13976 that it will build a <quote>Creative Archive,</quote> from which British citizens can
13977 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.<footnote><para>
13978 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,</quote> BBC press release,
13979 24 August 2003, available at
13980 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #70</ulink>.
13981 </para></footnote>
13982 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13983 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13984 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13985 country.<footnote><para>
13986 <!-- f15. -->
13987 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,</quote> Creative Commons Weblog, 6 August 2003,
13988 available at
13989 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #71</ulink>.
13990 </para></footnote>
13991 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13992 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13993 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13994 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13995 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13996 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13997 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13998 day into the Causbys.
13999 </para>
14000 <para>
14001 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
14002 potential is ever to be realized.
14003
14004 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
14005
14006 </para>
14007 </chapter>
14008 <chapter label="" id="c-afterword">
14009 <title>Afterword</title>
14010 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightvoluntaryreformeffortson' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>voluntary reform efforts on</secondary></indexterm>
14011 <para>
14012
14013 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
14014 <emphasis role='strong'>At least some</emphasis> who have read this
14015 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
14016 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
14017 </para>
14018 <para>
14019 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
14020 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
14021 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
14022 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
14023 </para>
14024 <para>
14025 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
14026 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
14027 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists&mdash;all to tell this
14028 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
14029 is so important.
14030 </para>
14031 <indexterm><primary>RCA</primary></indexterm>
14032 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightvoluntaryreformeffortson' class='endofrange'/>
14033 <para>
14034 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
14035 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
14036 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
14037 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
14038 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
14039 </para>
14040 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
14041
14042 <section id="usnow">
14043 <title>Us, now</title>
14044 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightvoluntaryreformeffortson2' class='startofrange'><primary>copyright</primary><secondary>voluntary reform efforts on</secondary></indexterm>
14045 <para>
14046 <emphasis role='strong'>Common sense</emphasis> is with the copyright
14047 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
14048 extremes&mdash;as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
14049 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
14050 choice, then the warriors should win.
14051 </para>
14052 <para>
14053 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
14054 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
14055 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright&mdash;<quote>All Rights
14056 Reserved</quote>&mdash; and those who reject copyright&mdash;<quote>No Rights
14057 Reserved.</quote> The <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
14058 permission before you <quote>use</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The <quote>No
14059 Rights Reserved</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
14060 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
14061 </para>
14062 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>development of</secondary></indexterm>
14063 <indexterm id='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>initial free character of</secondary></indexterm>
14064 <para>
14065 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
14066 tilted in the <quote>no rights reserved</quote> direction. Content could be copied
14067 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
14068 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
14069 the
14070
14071 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
14072 original design of the Internet was <quote>no rights reserved.</quote> Content was
14073 <quote>taken</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
14074 unprotected.
14075 </para>
14076 <para>
14077 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
14078 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
14079 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
14080 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
14081 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
14082 architecture made the effective default <quote>no rights reserved,</quote> the
14083 future architecture will make the effective default <quote>all rights
14084 reserved.</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
14085 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
14086 content requires permission. The <quote>cut and paste</quote> world that defines
14087 the Internet today will become a <quote>get permission to cut and paste</quote>
14088 world that is a creator's nightmare.
14089 </para>
14090 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='endofrange'/>
14091 <indexterm startref='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='endofrange'/>
14092 <para>
14093 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle&mdash;neither
14094 <quote>all rights reserved</quote> nor <quote>no rights reserved</quote> but <quote>some rights
14095 reserved</quote>&mdash; and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
14096 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
14097 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
14098 before.
14099 </para>
14100 <section id="examples">
14101 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples</title>
14102 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='startofrange'><primary>free culture</primary><secondary>restoration efforts on previous aspects of</secondary></indexterm>
14103 <indexterm id='idxbrowsing' class='startofrange'><primary>browsing</primary></indexterm>
14104 <indexterm id='idxprivacyrights2' class='startofrange'><primary>privacy rights</primary></indexterm>
14105 <para>
14106 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
14107 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
14108 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
14109 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
14110 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
14111 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
14112 to your neighbors or boss. The <quote>privacy</quote> of your browsing habits was
14113 assured.
14114 </para>
14115 <para>
14116 What made it assured?
14117 </para>
14118 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
14119 <para>
14120 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
14121 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="property-i"/>, your
14122 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
14123 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
14124 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
14125 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
14126 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
14127 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
14128 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
14129 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
14130 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
14131 (there is no law protecting <quote>privacy</quote> in public places), and in many
14132 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
14133 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
14134 </para>
14135 <indexterm id='idxamazon' class='startofrange'><primary>Amazon</primary></indexterm>
14136 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet</primary></indexterm>
14137 <indexterm id='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='startofrange'><primary>Internet</primary><secondary>privacy protection on</secondary></indexterm>
14138 <para>
14139 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
14140 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
14141 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
14142 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
14143 <quote>recently viewed</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
14144 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
14145 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any <quote>privacy</quote>
14146 protected by the friction disappears, too.
14147 </para>
14148 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>privacy rights in use of</secondary></indexterm>
14149 <para>
14150 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
14151 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
14152 people should have the <quote>right</quote> to browse in a library without the
14153 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
14154 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
14155 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
14156 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
14157 disappears.
14158 </para>
14159 <indexterm startref='idxbrowsing' class='endofrange'/>
14160 <indexterm startref='idxamazon' class='endofrange'/>
14161 <para>
14162 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define <quote>privacy</quote>
14163 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
14164 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
14165 friction did.<footnote><para>
14166 <!-- f1. -->
14167
14168 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, <quote>Fair Information Practices and the
14169 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
14170 Law Review</citetitle> 1 (2001): par. 6&ndash;18, available at
14171
14172 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>
14173 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
14174 also Jeffrey Rosen, <citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
14175 in an Anxious Age</citetitle> (New York: Random House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs
14176 between technology and privacy).</para></footnote>
14177 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
14178 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
14179
14180 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
14181 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
14182 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
14183 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
14184 </para>
14185 <indexterm startref='idxprivacyrights2' class='endofrange'/>
14186 <indexterm startref='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='endofrange'/>
14187 <indexterm><primary>Data General</primary></indexterm>
14188 <indexterm><primary>IBM</primary></indexterm>
14189 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='startofrange'><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)</primary></indexterm>
14190 <para>
14191 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
14192 movement. When computers with software were first made available
14193 commercially, the software&mdash;both the source code and the
14194 binaries&mdash; was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
14195 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
14196 care much about controlling their software.
14197 </para>
14198 <indexterm id='idxstallmanrichard' class='startofrange'><primary>Stallman, Richard</primary></indexterm>
14199 <para>
14200 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
14201 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
14202 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
14203 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
14204 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
14205 people's work.
14206 </para>
14207 <para>
14208 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
14209 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
14210 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
14211 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
14212 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
14213 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
14214 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
14215 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
14216 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
14217 anything else?
14218 </para>
14219 <indexterm id='idxproprietarycode' class='startofrange'><primary>proprietary code</primary></indexterm>
14220 <para>
14221 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
14222 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
14223 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
14224 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
14225 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
14226 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
14227 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
14228 </para>
14229 <para>
14230 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
14231 early 1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
14232 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
14233 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
14234 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
14235 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
14236 fundamentally weakened.
14237 </para>
14238 <indexterm startref='idxproprietarycode' class='endofrange'/>
14239 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus</primary></indexterm>
14240 <para>
14241 Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
14242 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
14243 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's <quote>Linux</quote>
14244 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
14245 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14246 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system</primary></indexterm>
14247 </para>
14248 <para>
14249 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
14250 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
14251 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
14252 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
14253 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
14254 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
14255 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
14256 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
14257 byproduct.
14258 </para>
14259 <para>
14260 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
14261 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
14262 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
14263 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
14264 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
14265 what before had been passively guaranteed.
14266 </para>
14267 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='endofrange'/>
14268 <indexterm startref='idxstallmanrichard' class='endofrange'/>
14269 <indexterm id='idxacademicjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>academic journals</primary></indexterm>
14270 <indexterm id='idxscientificjournals' class='startofrange'><primary>scientific journals</primary></indexterm>
14271 <para>
14272 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
14273 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
14274 scientific journals are produced.
14275 </para>
14276 <indexterm id='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='startofrange'><primary>Lexis and Westlaw</primary></indexterm>
14277 <indexterm id='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='startofrange'><primary>law</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in</secondary></indexterm>
14278 <indexterm><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14279 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.</primary><secondary>access to opinions of</secondary></indexterm>
14280 <para>
14281 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
14282 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
14283 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
14284 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
14285 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
14286 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
14287 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
14288 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
14289 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
14290 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
14291 and Westlaw are also free
14292 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
14293 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
14294 Court opinion through their respective services.
14295 </para>
14296 <indexterm><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>access fees for material in</secondary></indexterm>
14297 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='startofrange'><primary>public domain</primary><secondary>license system for rebuilding of</secondary></indexterm>
14298 <para>
14299 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
14300 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
14301 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
14302 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
14303 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
14304 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
14305 access to material that is not in the public domain.
14306 </para>
14307 <indexterm startref='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='endofrange'/>
14308 <indexterm startref='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='endofrange'/>
14309 <para>
14310 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
14311 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
14312 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
14313 </para>
14314 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='startofrange'><primary>libraries</primary><secondary>journals in</secondary></indexterm>
14315 <para>
14316 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
14317 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
14318 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
14319 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
14320 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
14321 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
14322 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
14323 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
14324 the technology of paper journals (architecture)&mdash;namely, that it
14325 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
14326 </para>
14327 <para>
14328 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
14329 that libraries not give the general public access to the
14330 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
14331 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
14332 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
14333 granted before.
14334 </para>
14335 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)</primary></indexterm>
14336 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)</primary></indexterm>
14337 <para>
14338 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
14339 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
14340 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
14341 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
14342 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
14343 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
14344 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
14345 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
14346 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
14347 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
14348 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
14349 </para>
14350 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='endofrange'/>
14351 <para>
14352 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
14353 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
14354 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
14355 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
14356 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
14357 presumptively a good&mdash;especially when it helps spread knowledge
14358 and science.
14359 </para>
14360 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='endofrange'/>
14361 <indexterm startref='idxacademicjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14362 <indexterm startref='idxscientificjournals' class='endofrange'/>
14363 </section>
14364 <section id="oneidea">
14365 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea</title>
14366 <indexterm id='idxcreativecommons' class='startofrange'><primary>Creative Commons</primary></indexterm>
14367 <para>
14368 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
14369 increasing control effected through law and technology.
14370 </para>
14371 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University</primary></indexterm>
14372 <para>
14373 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
14374 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
14375 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
14376 <emphasis>reasonable</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
14377 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
14378 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
14379 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
14380 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
14381 make this possible.
14382 </para>
14383 <para>
14384 <emphasis>Simple</emphasis>&mdash;which means without a middleman, or
14385 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
14386 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
14387 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
14388 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
14389 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
14390 shared. These three expressions together&mdash;a legal license, a
14391 human-readable description, and
14392 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
14393 machine-readable tags&mdash;constitute a Creative Commons license. A
14394 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
14395 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
14396 that the person associated with the license believes in something
14397 different than the <quote>All</quote> or <quote>No</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
14398 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
14399 certain freedoms are given.
14400 </para>
14401 <para>
14402 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
14403 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
14404 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
14405 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
14406 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
14407 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (<quote>share and share
14408 alike</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
14409 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
14410 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
14411 </para>
14412 <para>
14413 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
14414 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
14415 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
14416 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
14417 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
14418 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
14419 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
14420 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
14421 a public domain.
14422 </para>
14423 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia</primary></indexterm>
14424 <para>
14425 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
14426 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
14427 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
14428 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
14429 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
14430 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
14431 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
14432 of content (<quote>content conducers,</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
14433 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
14434 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
14435 </para>
14436 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas</primary></indexterm>
14437 <para>
14438 The aim is not to fight the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote> sorts. The aim is to
14439 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
14440 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
14441 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
14442 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
14443 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
14444 the background of digital technologies. New rules&mdash;with different
14445 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
14446 them&mdash;are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
14447 to begin to build those rules.
14448 </para>
14449 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'><primary>books</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of</secondary></indexterm>
14450 <para>
14451 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
14452 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
14453 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel, <citetitle>Down and Out in
14454 the Magic Kingdom</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
14455 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
14456 </para>
14457 <para>
14458 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
14459 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1)
14460 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
14461 and (2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
14462 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (1) will download
14463 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2)
14464 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
14465 them (2)-goods. If there are more (2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the
14466 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
14467 <emphasis>increase</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
14468 </para>
14469 <para>
14470 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
14471 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
14472 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
14473 was a total success.
14474 </para>
14475 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)</primary></indexterm>
14476 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter</primary></indexterm>
14477 <para>
14478 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
14479 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
14480 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
14481 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled <citetitle>Free for All</citetitle>,
14482 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
14483 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
14484 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
14485 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
14486 well.
14487 </para>
14488 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'/>
14489 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter</primary></indexterm>
14490 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy</primary></indexterm>
14491 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightvoluntaryreformeffortson2' class='endofrange'/>
14492 <indexterm><primary>rap music</primary></indexterm>
14493 <para>
14494 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
14495 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
14496 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
14497 reasons. Many who use the <quote>sampling license</quote> do so because anything
14498 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
14499 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
14500 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
14501 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
14502 art&mdash;they, too, sample from others. Because the
14503 <emphasis>legal</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
14504 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
14505 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not <quote>allow</quote>
14506 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
14507 high<footnote><para>
14508 <!-- f2. -->
14509 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
14510 Culture Wars</citetitle> (2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
14511 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
14512 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #72</ulink>.
14513 </para></footnote>),
14514 these artists release into the creative environment content
14515 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
14516 </para>
14517 <para>
14518 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
14519 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
14520 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
14521 you are effectively saying you believe in the <quote>All Rights Reserved</quote>
14522 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
14523 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
14524 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
14525 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
14526 this notion of <quote>Some Rights Reserved,</quote> and gives many the chance to
14527 say it to others.
14528 </para>
14529 <para>
14530 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
14531 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
14532 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
14533 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
14534
14535 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
14536 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
14537 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
14538 </para>
14539 <para>
14540 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
14541 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
14542 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
14543 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
14544 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
14545 steps are possible.
14546 </para>
14547 <para>
14548 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
14549 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
14550 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
14551 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
14552 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
14553 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
14554 creativity to spread more easily.
14555 </para>
14556 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='endofrange'/>
14557 <indexterm startref='idxcreativecommons' class='endofrange'/>
14558 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
14559 </section>
14560 </section>
14561 <section id="themsoon">
14562 <title>Them, soon</title>
14563 <para>
14564 <emphasis role='strong'>We will</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
14565 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
14566 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
14567 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
14568 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
14569 </para>
14570 <para>
14571 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
14572 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
14573 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
14574 to our end.
14575 </para>
14576
14577 <section id="formalities">
14578 <title>1. More Formalities</title>
14579 <para>
14580 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
14581 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
14582 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
14583 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
14584 </para>
14585 <para>
14586 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
14587 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
14588 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
14589 protected.
14590 </para>
14591 <para>
14592 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
14593 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
14594 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
14595 default is control, and <quote>formalities</quote> are banished.
14596 </para>
14597 <para>
14598 Why?
14599 </para>
14600 <para>
14601 As I suggested in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
14602 linkend="property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
14603 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
14604 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
14605 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
14606 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
14607 formalities were getting in the way.
14608 </para>
14609 <para>
14610 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
14611 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
14612 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
14613 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
14614 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
14615 trace&mdash; there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
14616 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
14617 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
14618 past. And thus, the <emphasis>lack</emphasis> of formalities forces
14619 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
14620 </para>
14621 <para>
14622 The law should therefore change this requirement<footnote><para>
14623 <!-- f1. -->
14624 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
14625 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
14626 adopted by other countries as well.</para></footnote>&mdash;but it
14627 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
14628 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
14629 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
14630 </para>
14631 <para>
14632 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
14633 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
14634 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
14635 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
14636 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
14637 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
14638 developed by others.
14639 </para>
14640
14641 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
14642
14643 <section id="registration">
14644 <title>Registration and renewal</title>
14645 <para>
14646 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
14647 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
14648 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
14649 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
14650 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
14651 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
14652 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
14653 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
14654 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
14655 panic&mdash;nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
14656 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
14657 </para>
14658 <para>
14659 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
14660 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
14661 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
14662 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
14663 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
14664 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
14665 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
14666 </para>
14667 <para>
14668 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
14669 There are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world.
14670 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
14671 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
14672 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
14673 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
14674 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
14675 with which registration occurs up.
14676 </para>
14677 <para>
14678 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
14679 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
14680 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
14681 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
14682 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
14683 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
14684 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
14685 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
14686 formality&mdash;while producing a database
14687 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
14688 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
14689 </para>
14690
14691 </section>
14692 <section id="marking">
14693 <title>Marking</title>
14694 <para>
14695 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
14696 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
14697 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule&mdash;akin to
14698 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
14699 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
14700 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
14701 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
14702 uniformly across all media.
14703 </para>
14704 <para>
14705 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
14706 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
14707 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
14708 use the work.
14709 </para>
14710 <para>
14711 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
14712 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
14713 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
14714 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
14715 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
14716 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
14717 signal from the failure to mark&mdash;not the loss of the copyright, but the
14718 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
14719 </para>
14720 <para>
14721 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
14722 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
14723 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
14724 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
14725 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
14726 doesn't give permission.<footnote><para>
14727 <!-- f2. -->
14728 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
14729 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
14730 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
14731 </para></footnote>
14732 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be <quote>use unless someone
14733 complains.</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
14734 stop using the work in any new
14735 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
14736 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
14737 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
14738 their work.
14739 </para>
14740 <para>
14741 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
14742 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
14743 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
14744 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
14745 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
14746 </para>
14747 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>copyright marking of</secondary></indexterm>
14748 <para>
14749 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14750 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14751 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14752 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14753 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14754 <emphasis>solely</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14755 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14756 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14757 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14758 other important functions.
14759 </para>
14760 <para>
14761 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14762 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14763 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14764 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14765 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14766 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14767 </para>
14768 <para>
14769 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14770 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14771 make things unclear.
14772 </para>
14773 <para>
14774 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14775 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14776 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14777 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14778 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14779 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14780 </para>
14781
14782 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14783 </section>
14784 </section>
14785 <section id="shortterms">
14786 <title>2. Shorter Terms</title>
14787 <para>
14788 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14789 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14790 natural authors.
14791 </para>
14792 <para>
14793 In <citetitle>The Future of Ideas</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14794 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14795 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14796 <citetitle>Eldred</citetitle> v. <citetitle>Ashcroft</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14797 radical. <citetitle>The Economist</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14798 copyright term.<footnote><para>
14799
14800 <!-- f3. -->
14801 <quote>A Radical Rethink,</quote> <citetitle>Economist</citetitle>, 366:8308 (25 January 2003): 15,
14802 available at
14803 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #74</ulink>.
14804 </para></footnote>
14805 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14806 </para>
14807 <para>
14808 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14809 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14810 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14811 terms.
14812 </para>
14813 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
14814 <listitem><para>
14815 <!-- (1) -->
14816 <emphasis>Keep it short:</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14817 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14818 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14819 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14820 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14821 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14822 </para></listitem>
14823 <listitem><para>
14824 <!-- (2) -->
14825 <emphasis>Keep it simple:</emphasis> The line between the public
14826 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14827 fuzziness of <quote>fair use,</quote> and the distinction between <quote>ideas</quote> and
14828 <quote>expression.</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14829 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14830 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14831 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14832 <quote>lawyer-free zone</quote> makes the complexities of <quote>fair use</quote> and
14833 <quote>idea/expression</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14834 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14835 </para></listitem>
14836 <listitem>
14837 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions</primary></indexterm>
14838 <para>
14839 <!-- (3) -->
14840 <emphasis>Keep it alive:</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14841 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14842 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14843 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14844 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14845 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14846 pension.<footnote><para>
14847 <!-- f4. -->
14848 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14849 and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001),
14850 available at
14851 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #75</ulink>.
14852 </para></footnote>
14853 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14854 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14855 single form.
14856 </para></listitem>
14857 <listitem><para>
14858 <!-- (4) -->
14859 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14860 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14861 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14862 in 1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14863 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14864 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in 1923 than we
14865 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14866 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14867 the number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase
14868 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14869 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14870 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14871 creativity in 1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14872 we can do about that now. </para></listitem>
14873 </orderedlist>
14874 <para>
14875 These changes together should produce an <emphasis>average</emphasis>
14876 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until 1976,
14877 the average term was just 32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14878 same.
14879 </para>
14880 <para>
14881 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas <quote>radical.</quote> (After all, I
14882 call them <quote>extremists.</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14883 than the term under Richard Nixon. How <quote>radical</quote> can it be to ask for
14884 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14885 </para>
14886
14887 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14888
14889 </section>
14890 <section id="freefairuse">
14891 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use</title>
14892 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and</primary></indexterm>
14893 <indexterm><primary>property rights</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.</secondary></indexterm>
14894 <para>
14895 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14896 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14897 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14898 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14899 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14900 the emergence of that new technology.
14901 </para>
14902 <para>
14903 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors <quote>exclusive
14904 right</quote> to <quote>their writings.</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14905 right to <quote>their writings</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14906 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14907 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14908 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14909 though that movie is not <quote>my writing.</quote>
14910 </para>
14911 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin</primary></indexterm>
14912 <para>
14913 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it
14914 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14915 control translations and dramatizations of a work.<footnote><para>
14916 <!-- f5. -->
14917 Benjamin Kaplan, <citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14918 University Press, 1967), 32.
14919 </para></footnote>
14920 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14921 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14922 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14923 </para>
14924 <blockquote>
14925 <para>
14926 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14927 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14928 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14929 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.<footnote><para>
14930 <!-- f6. --> Ibid., 56.
14931 </para></footnote>
14932 </para>
14933 </blockquote>
14934 <para>
14935 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14936 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14937 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14938 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14939 Consider each limitation in turn.
14940 </para>
14941 <para>
14942 <emphasis>Term:</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14943 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14944 sense to protect John
14945
14946 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14947 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14948 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14949 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14950 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14951 after the creative work is done.
14952 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John</primary></indexterm>
14953 </para>
14954 <para>
14955 <emphasis>Scope:</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14956 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14957 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14958 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14959 material. When all <quote>reuse</quote> of creative material was within the control
14960 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14961 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14962 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14963 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14964 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14965 the creative process. Smothers it.
14966 </para>
14967 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex</primary></indexterm>
14968 <para>
14969 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14970 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14971 foreseeable derivative rights&mdash;turning a book into a movie, or a
14972 poem into a musical score&mdash;it doesn't make sense to require
14973 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14974 much more sense.
14975 </para>
14976 <para>
14977 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14978 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14979 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14980 Paul Goldstein.<footnote>
14981 <para>
14982 <!-- f7. -->
14983 Paul Goldstein, <citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14984 Jukebox</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187&ndash;216.
14985 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul</primary></indexterm>
14986 </para></footnote>
14987 His view is that the law should be written so that
14988 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14989 </para>
14990 <para>
14991 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14992 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14993 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14994 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14995 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14996 </para>
14997 <para>
14998 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
15000 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
15001 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
15002 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
15003 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
15004 </para>
15005 </section>
15006
15007 <section id="liberatemusic">
15008 <title>4. Liberate the Music&mdash;Again</title>
15009 <para>
15010 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
15011 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
15012 is, to most people, most pressing&mdash;music. There is no other
15013 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
15014 battles around the sharing of music.
15015 </para>
15016 <para>
15017 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
15018 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
15019 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
15020 killer app&mdash;possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
15021 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
15022 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
15023 innovation on the network.
15024 </para>
15025 <para>
15026 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
15027 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
15028 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
15029 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
15030 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
15031 </para>
15032 <para>
15033 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
15034 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
15035 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
15036 <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber" linkend="piracy"/>, they enable
15037 four different kinds of sharing:
15038 </para>
15039 <orderedlist numeration="upperalpha">
15040 <listitem><para>
15041 <!-- A. -->
15042 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
15043 for purchasing CDs.
15044 </para></listitem>
15045 <listitem><para>
15046 <!-- B. -->
15047 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
15048 on the way to purchasing CDs.
15049 </para></listitem>
15050 <listitem><para>
15051 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
15052 <!-- C. -->
15053 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15054 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
15055 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
15056 </para></listitem>
15057 <listitem><para>
15058 <!-- D. -->
15059 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15060 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
15061 owner plainly endorses.
15062 </para></listitem>
15063 </orderedlist>
15064 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording</primary><secondary>VCRs</secondary></indexterm>
15065 <indexterm><primary>VCRs</primary></indexterm>
15066 <para>
15067 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
15068 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
15069 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
15070 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
15071 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
15072 significantly weakened.
15073 </para>
15074 <para>
15075 As I said in chapter <xref xrefstyle="select: labelnumber"
15076 linkend="piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
15077 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
15078 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
15079 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
15080 networks.
15081 </para>
15082 <para>
15083 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
15084 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
15085 should respond.
15086 </para>
15087 <para>
15088 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
15089 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
15090 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
15091 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
15092 is cumbersome and slow&mdash;we in the United States are lucky to have
15093 broadband service at 1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
15094 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
15095 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
15096 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
15097 Internet is mainly just an idea.
15098 </para>
15099 <para>
15100 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
15101 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
15102 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
15103 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
15104 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
15105 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
15106 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
15107 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
15108 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
15109 where everywhere you are&mdash;except maybe the desert or the
15110 Rockies&mdash;you can instantaneously be connected to the
15111 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
15112 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
15113 </para>
15114 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over</primary></indexterm>
15115 <para>
15116 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
15117 give you access to content on the fly&mdash;such as Internet radio,
15118 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
15119 then, is the critical point: When it is <emphasis>extremely</emphasis>
15120 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
15121 <emphasis>easier</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
15122 access to content than it will be to download and store content
15123 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
15124 content</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
15125 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
15126 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
15127 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
15128 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
15129 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
15130 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
15131 paying for this content even though <quote>free</quote> content is available in the
15132 form of MP3s across the Web.<footnote><para>
15133 <!-- f8. -->
15134 See, for example, <quote>Music Media Watch,</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3
15135 April 2002, available at
15136 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #76</ulink>.
15137 </para></footnote>
15138
15139 </para>
15140 <para>
15141 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
15142 present: It is emphatically temporary. The <quote>problem</quote> with file
15143 sharing&mdash;to the extent there is a real problem&mdash;is a problem
15144 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
15145 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
15146 makers today to be <quote>solving</quote> this problem in light of a technology
15147 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
15148 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
15149 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
15150 artists get paid, during
15151
15152 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
15153 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
15154 and twenty-first-century technologies.
15155 </para>
15156 <para>
15157 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different <quote>problems</quote>
15158 here to solve. Let's start with type D content&mdash;uncopyrighted
15159 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
15160 <quote>problem</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
15161 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
15162 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
15163 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
15164 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
15165 order to eliminate kidnapping.
15166 </para>
15167 <para>
15168 Type C content raises a different <quote>problem.</quote> This is content that was,
15169 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
15170 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
15171 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
15172 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
15173 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
15174 way that returns something to the artist.
15175 </para>
15176 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>out of print</secondary></indexterm>
15177 <indexterm><primary>books</primary><secondary>resales of</secondary></indexterm>
15178 <para>
15179 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
15180 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
15181 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
15182 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
15183 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
15184 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
15185 from the author's perspective, this <quote>sharing</quote> of his content without
15186 his being compensated is less than ideal.
15187 </para>
15188 <para>
15189 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
15190 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
15191 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
15192 providers would be free, under this rule, to <quote>share</quote> that content,
15193 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
15194 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
15195 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
15196 </para>
15197 <para>
15198
15199 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
15200 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
15201 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
15202 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
15203 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
15204 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
15205 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
15206 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
15207 trade.
15208 </para>
15209 <para>
15210 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
15211 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
15212 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
15213 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
15214 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
15215 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
15216 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
15217 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
15218 </para>
15219 <para>
15220 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
15221 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
15222 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
15223 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
15224 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
15225 delivering and accessing content.
15226 </para>
15227 <para>
15228 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
15229 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
15230 </para>
15231 <para>
15232 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
15233 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
15234 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
15235 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
15236 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
15237 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
15238 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
15239 harmed the interests of the content industry.
15240 </para>
15241 <para>
15242 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
15243 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
15244 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
15245 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
15246 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
15247 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
15248 way to compensate those who are harmed.
15249 </para>
15250 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15251 <para>
15252 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
15253 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.<footnote>
15254 <para>
15255 <!-- f9. -->
15256 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15257 William Fisher, <citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities</citetitle> (last
15258 revised: 10 October 2000), available at
15259 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #77</ulink>; William
15260 Fisher, <citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
15261 Entertainment</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
15262 2004), ch. 6, available at
15263 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #78</ulink>. Professor
15264 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
15265 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
15266 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, <quote>Impose a
15267 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,</quote> available at
15268 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Who's Holding Back
15269 Broadband?</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post</citetitle>, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
15270 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
15271 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee, 26 February 2002,
15272 available at
15273 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine, <citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
15274 Use Fee (IPUF)</citetitle>, 3 March 2002, available at
15275 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
15276 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,</quote> <citetitle>USA Today</citetitle>, 13 May
15277 2002, available at
15278 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry, <quote>Getting Copyright Right,</quote>
15279 IEEE Spectrum Online, 1 July 2002, available at
15280 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #83</ulink>; Declan
15281 McCullagh, <quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,</quote> CNET News.com, 27 August
15282 2002, available at
15283 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #84</ulink>.
15284 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
15285 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
15286 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
15287 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
15288 debate by about a decade. See
15289 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #85</ulink>.
15290 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William</primary></indexterm>
15291 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock</primary></indexterm>
15292 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)</primary></indexterm>
15293 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'/>
15294 </para></footnote>
15295 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
15296 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
15297 would (1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
15298 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
15299 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
15300 develop (2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
15301 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (3) artists would be
15302 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (4) an appropriate
15303 tax.
15304 </para>
15305 <para>
15306 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
15307 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
15308 <citetitle>Promises to Keep</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
15309 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
15310 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
15311 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
15312 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
15313 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
15314 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
15315 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
15316 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
15317 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
15318 controlling access.
15319 </para>
15320 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'/>
15321 <indexterm><primary>artists</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to</secondary></indexterm>
15322 <para>
15323 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
15324 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
15325 the system supports the widest range of <quote>semiotic democracy</quote>
15326 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
15327 other changes I described were accomplished&mdash;in particular, the
15328 limits on derivative
15329
15330 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
15331 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
15332 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
15333 allowed to do with the content itself.
15334 </para>
15335 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation</primary></indexterm>
15336 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore</primary></indexterm>
15337 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks</primary></indexterm>
15338 <indexterm><primary>CDs</primary><secondary>prices of</secondary></indexterm>
15339 <para>
15340 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
15341 <quote>harm</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
15342 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
15343 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
15344 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
15345 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat <quote>free</quote> by being
15346 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
15347 of songs at even the very high price of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents,
15348 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
15349 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
15350 Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a song. And no doubt
15351 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
15352 on-line.
15353 </para>
15354 <indexterm><primary>cable television</primary></indexterm>
15355 <indexterm><primary>television</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast</secondary></indexterm>
15356 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in</primary></indexterm>
15357 <indexterm><primary>piracy</primary><secondary>in Asia</secondary></indexterm>
15358 <indexterm><primary>film industry</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in</secondary></indexterm>
15359 <para>
15360 This competition has already occurred against the background of <quote>free</quote>
15361 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
15362 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
15363 that, there is nothing impossible at all about <quote>competing with free.</quote>
15364 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
15365 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
15366 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
15367 theaters are often luxurious&mdash;with <quote>first class</quote> seats, and meals
15368 served while you watch a movie&mdash;as they struggle and succeed in
15369 finding ways to compete with <quote>free.</quote>
15370 </para>
15371 <para>
15372 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
15373 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
15374 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
15375 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
15376 innovators&mdash;ones who would have a right to the content, and would
15377 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
15378 the law.
15379 </para>
15380 <para>
15381 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
15382 </para>
15383 <para>
15384
15385 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
15386 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
15387 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
15388 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
15389 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
15390 create.
15391 </para>
15392 <para>
15393 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
15394 by
15395 </para>
15396 <orderedlist numeration="arabic">
15397 <listitem><para>
15398 <!-- 1. -->
15399 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
15400 </para></listitem>
15401 <listitem><para>
15402 <!-- 2. -->
15403 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
15404 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
15405 statute;
15406 </para></listitem>
15407 <listitem><para>
15408 <!-- 3. -->
15409 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
15410 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
15411 </para></listitem>
15412 </orderedlist>
15413 <para>
15414 But what if <quote>piracy</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
15415 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
15416 consumers continue to <quote>take</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
15417 something then?
15418 </para>
15419 <para>
15420 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
15421 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
15422 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
15423 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
15424 technology that is 95 percent secure and produces a market of size <citetitle>x</citetitle>,
15425 or (b) to have a technology that is 50 percent secure but produces a
15426 market of five times <citetitle>x</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
15427 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
15428 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
15429 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
15430 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
15431 pirates.
15432 </para>
15433 <para>
15434 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
15435 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
15436 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
15437
15438 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
15439 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
15440 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
15441 </para>
15442 </section>
15443
15444 <section id="firelawyers">
15445 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers</title>
15446 <para>
15447 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
15448 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
15449 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
15450 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
15451 </para>
15452 <para>
15453 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
15454 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
15455 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
15456 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
15457 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
15458 strong view queers the law.
15459 </para>
15460 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville</primary></indexterm>
15461 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (1998)</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of</secondary></indexterm>
15462 <para>
15463 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
15464 <quote>radical</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
15465 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
15466 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
15467 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
15468 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
15469 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
15470 Nimmer, thought it obvious.<footnote><para>
15471 <!-- f10. -->
15472 Lawrence Lessig, <quote>Copyright's First Amendment</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
15473 Memorial Lecture), <citetitle>UCLA Law Review</citetitle> 48 (2001): 1057, 1069&ndash;70.
15474 </para></footnote>
15475
15476 </para>
15477 <para>
15478 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
15479 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
15480 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
15481 </para>
15482 <para>
15483 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
15484 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
15485 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
15486 the legal system are slight.<footnote><para>
15487 <!-- f11. -->
15488 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
15489 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
15490 leading him to question his own publicly stated
15491 position&mdash;twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
15492 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
15493 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
15494 J. Liebowitz, <citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
15495 Drive the Digital Marketplace</citetitle> (New York: Amacom, 2002), (reviewing his
15496 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
15497 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?</quote> working paper, June 2003,
15498 available at
15499 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #86</ulink>.
15500 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
15501 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
15502 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
15503 <citetitle>Rethinking</citetitle>, 174&ndash;76.
15504 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan</primary></indexterm>
15505 </para></footnote>
15506 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
15507 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
15508 them it works.
15509 </para>
15510 <para>
15511 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
15512 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
15513 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
15514 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
15515 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
15516 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
15517 practically never be done.
15518 </para>
15519 <para>
15520 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
15521 billed at the largest firms at more than $400 per hour. How much time
15522 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
15523 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
15524 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
15525 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
15526 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
15527 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
15528 </para>
15529 <para>
15530 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
15531 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
15532 their duty to change the way the law works&mdash;or better, to change the
15533 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
15534 top 1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
15535 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
15536 </para>
15537 <para>
15538 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
15539 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
15540 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
15541 its review.
15542 </para>
15543 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid</primary></indexterm>
15544 <para>
15545 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
15546 technology&mdash;the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
15547 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
15548 technology&mdash;a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
15549 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
15550 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
15551 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
15552 </para>
15553 <para>
15554 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture&mdash;but it should
15555 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
15556
15557 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311-->
15558 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
15559 simple pragmatic question: <quote>Will it do good?</quote> When challenged about
15560 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers, <quote>Why not?</quote>
15561 </para>
15562 <para>
15563 We should ask, <quote>Why?</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
15564 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
15565 keep your lawyers away.
15566 </para>
15567 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
15568 </section>
15569 </section>
15570 </chapter>
15571 <chapter label="" id="c-notes">
15572 <title>Notes</title>
15573 <para>
15574 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
15575 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
15576 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
15577 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
15578 this book. For each link below, you can go to
15579 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/notes"/>
15580 and locate the original source by clicking on the number after the #
15581 sign. If the original link remains alive, you will be redirected to
15582 that link. If the original link has disappeared, you will be
15583 redirected to an appropriate reference for the material.
15584 </para>
15585
15586 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
15587
15588 <index type="endnotes"/>
15589
15590 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
15591
15592 </chapter>
15593 <chapter label="" id="c-acknowledgments">
15594 <title>Acknowledgments</title>
15595 <para>
15596 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
15597 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
15598 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
15599 to him that this book is dedicated.
15600 </para>
15601 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark</primary></indexterm>
15602 <para>
15603 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
15604 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
15605 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
15606 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
15607 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
15608 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
15609 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
15610 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
15611 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
15612 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
15613 critical eye on much of this.
15614 </para>
15615 <para>
15616 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
15617 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
15618 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
15619 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
15620 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
15621 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
15622 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
15623 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
15624 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
15625 </para>
15626 <para>
15627 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
15628 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
15629 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
15630 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
15631 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
15632 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
15633 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
15634 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
15635 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
15636 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
15637 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
15638 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
15639 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
15640 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
15641 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, <quote>Wink,</quote> Roger Wood, <quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,</quote>
15642 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
15643 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
15644 a bunch of great replies.)
15645 </para>
15646 <para>
15647 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
15648 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
15649 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
15650 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
15651 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
15652 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
15653 throughout this book.
15654 </para>
15655 <para>
15656 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
15657 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
15658 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
15659 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
15660 </para>
15661 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
15662
15663 </chapter>
15664
15665 <chapter label="" id="c-about-this-edition">
15666 <title>About this edition</title>
15667 <para>
15668 This edition of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle> is the result of
15669 three years of volunteer work. The idea came from a discussion I had
15670 around ten years ago with a friend about the copyright debate in
15671 Norway, and how rarely the difficulties of long copyright made it into
15672 the public debate. A bit more than three years ago I finally had a
15673 look again at the idea and decided to publish a printed Norwegian
15674 Bokmål version of <citetitle>Free Culture</citetitle>, translated and
15675 formatted by volunteers. The new English edition is a by-product of
15676 the translation process.
15677 </para>
15678
15679 <para>
15680 Thanks to the Debian Edu / Skolelinux project, I already had
15681 experience translating Docbook documents, and it seemed like a good
15682 format for this book too. I found a Docbook formatted version of the
15683 book created by Hans Schou. Initial testing showed lots of Docbook
15684 validation errors in this version, but after some work I was able to
15685 transform it to PDF and EPUB. This was the start of the translation
15686 project. The Docbook file improved over time, and build rules were
15687 added to create both English and Bokmål versions. Finally, a call for
15688 volunteers went out to help me with the translation.
15689 </para>
15690
15691 <para>
15692 Several people joined, and Anders Hagen Jarmund, Kirill Miazine, Odd
15693 Kleiva, Kjetil Kilhavn og Kjetil T. Homme assisted with the initial
15694 translation. Ralph Amissah and his SiSu version provided index
15695 entries. Morten Sickel and Alexander Alemayhu helped with the
15696 figures, redrawing some of the bitmaps as vector images. Wivi
15697 Reinholdtsen, Ingrid Yrvin, Johannes Larsen and Gisle Hannemyr did
15698 very valuable proofreading. Håkon Wium Lie helped me track down a
15699 good replacement font without usage restrictions instead of the one in
15700 the original PDF. The PDF typesetting is done using dblatex, which we
15701 selected over the alternatives thanks to the invaluable and quick help
15702 from Benoît Guillon and Andreas Hoenen. Thomas Gramstad donated ISBN
15703 numbers needed for distribution to book stores. Marc Jeanmougin from
15704 the inkscape community helped me replicate the original front cover.
15705 The support of Lawrence Lessig helped me to complete the
15706 project&mdash;I am very thankful he had the original screen shots
15707 still available after 11 years.
15708 </para>
15709
15710 <para>
15711 At the end of the project, when the translation was done and it was
15712 time to publish, NUUG Foundation was asked and was willing to sponsor
15713 books to members of the Norwegian parliament and other decision
15714 makers.
15715 </para>
15716
15717 <para>
15718 In addition to these great contributors, I am very grateful to Mari
15719 and my family for their patience with me in this project.
15720 </para>
15721
15722 <para>
15723 &mdash; Petter Reinholdtsen, Oslo 2015-09-07
15724 </para>
15725
15726 </chapter>
15727 <index></index>
15728 <colophon>
15729 <title></title>
15730 <?latex {\centering
15731 ?>
15732 <para>
15733 Free culture: How big media uses technology and the law to lock down
15734 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
15735 </para>
15736 <para>
15737 Copyright &copy; 2004 Lawrence Lessig. Some rights reserved.
15738 </para>
15739
15740 <para>
15741 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/"/>
15742 </para>
15743
15744 <para>
15745 Published in English and Norwegian Bokmål 2015 by Petter Reinholdtsen
15746 with help from many volunteers. Typeset with dblatex using the font
15747 Crimson Text.
15748 </para>
15749
15750 <para>
15751 First published 2004 by The Penguin Press.
15752 </para>
15753
15754 <para>
15755 Excerpt from an editorial titled <quote>The Coming of Copyright
15756 Perpetuity,</quote> <citetitle>The New York Times</citetitle>, January
15757 16, 2003. Copyright &copy; 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted
15758 with permission.
15759 </para>
15760 <para>
15761 Cartoon in figure
15762 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by
15763 Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune Media Services, Inc. All rights
15764 reserved. Reprinted with permission.
15765 </para>
15766 <para>
15767 Diagram in figure
15768 <xref xrefstyle="template:%n" linkend="fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/>
15769 courtesy of the office of FCC Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
15770 </para>
15771
15772 <para>
15773 Cover created by Petter Reinholdtsen using inkscape.
15774 </para>
15775
15776 <para>
15777 The quotes on the cover came from
15778 <ulink url="http://free-culture.cc/jacket/"/>.
15779 </para>
15780
15781 <para>
15782 Portrait on the cover was created 2013 by ActuaLitté and licensed
15783 under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 2.0 license. It was
15784 downloaded from
15785 <ulink url="https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File%3ALawrence_Lessig_(11014343366)_(cropped).jpg"/>.
15786 </para>
15787
15788 <para>
15789 Classifications:
15790 </para>
15791
15792 <para>
15793 (Dewey)
15794 306.4,
15795 306.40973,
15796 306.46,
15797 341.7582,
15798 343.7309/9
15799 </para>
15800
15801 <para>
15802 (UDK) 347.78
15803 </para>
15804
15805 <para>
15806 (US Library of Congress) KF2979.L47 2004
15807 </para>
15808
15809 <para>
15810 (ACM CRCS) K.4.1
15811 </para>
15812
15813 <para>
15814 Thomas Gramstad Forlag donated the ISBN numbers.
15815 </para>
15816
15817 <para>
15818 Printing was sponsed by NUUG Foundation,
15819 <ulink url="http://www.nuugfoundation.no/"/>.
15820 </para>
15821
15822 <para>
15823 Includes index.
15824 </para>
15825
15826 <?latex } %\centering
15827 ?>
15828
15829 <para>
15830 The Docbook source is available from
15831 <ulink url="https://github.com/petterreinholdtsen/free-culture-lessig"/>.
15832 Please report any issues with the book there.
15833 </para>
15834
15835 <para>
15836 <informalfigure id="cc-logo">
15837 <graphic fileref="images/cc.svg" align="center" width="11%"></graphic>
15838 </informalfigure>
15839 </para>
15840
15841 <para>
15842 This book is licensed under a Creative Commons license. This license
15843 permits non-commercial use of this work, so long as attribution is
15844 given. For more information about the license visit
15845 <ulink url="http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/"/>.
15846 </para>
15847
15848 <para>
15849 This book is a proof reading draft. Please visit the github URL above
15850 to get the latest version.
15851 </para>
15852
15853 <para>
15854 <informaltable id="isbn">
15855 <tgroup cols="2" align="left">
15856 <thead>
15857 <row>
15858 <entry>Format / MIME-type</entry>
15859 <entry>ISBN</entry>
15860 </row>
15861 </thead>
15862 <tbody>
15863 <row>
15864 <entry>US Trade edition from lulu.com</entry>
15865 <entry>978-82-8067-010-6</entry>
15866 </row>
15867 <row>
15868 <entry>application/pdf</entry>
15869 <entry>978-82-8067-011-3</entry>
15870 </row>
15871 <row>
15872 <entry>application/epub+zip</entry>
15873 <entry>978-82-8067-012-0</entry>
15874 </row>
15875 <row>
15876 <entry>application/x-mobipocket-ebook</entry>
15877 <entry>978-82-8067-013-7</entry>
15878 </row>
15879 </tbody>
15880 </tgroup>
15881 </informaltable>
15882 </para>
15883
15884 </colophon>
15885 </book>