1 <?xml version='
1.0' encoding='UTF-
8'
?>
2 <?xml-stylesheet href=
"docbook-css-0.4/driver.css" type=
"text/css"?>
3 <!-- Converted to DocBook by Hans Schou 2004-03-29. Updated and improved
4 by Petter Reinholdtsen 2012 with input from Martin Borg. -->
9 <!DOCTYPE book PUBLIC
"-//OASIS//DTD DocBook XML V4.5//EN"
10 "http://www.oasis-open.org/docbook/xml/4.5/docbookx.dtd"
13 <!ENTITY translationblock
"">
15 <book id=
"index" lang=
"en">
17 <title>Free Culture
</title>
19 <abbrev>"freeculture"</abbrev>
21 <subtitle>HOW BIG MEDIA USES TECHNOLOGY AND THE LAW TO LOCK DOWN
22 CULTURE AND CONTROL CREATIVITY
</subtitle>
24 <pubdate>2004-
03-
25</pubdate>
26 <releaseinfo>Version
2004-
02-
10</releaseinfo>
30 <firstname>Lawrence
</firstname>
31 <surname>Lessig
</surname>
34 Keep these out to avoid showing up as author in the PDF.
37 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
38 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
41 <othercredit role='converter'>
42 <firstname>Petter</firstname>
43 <surname>Reinholdtsen</surname>
44 <contrib>Created this Docbook version from an earlier version</contrib>
49 <!-- <subjectset> and cover <mediaobject> Based on example from
50 http://jfearn.fedorapeople.org/en-US/Publican/2.7/html/Users_Guide/chap-Users_Guide-Creating_a_document.html
52 <subjectset scheme=
"libraryofcongress">
54 <subjectterm>Intellectual property
—United States.
</subjectterm>
57 <subjectterm>Mass media
—United States.
</subjectterm>
60 <subjectterm>Technological innovations
—United States.
</subjectterm>
63 <subjectterm>Art
—United States.
</subjectterm>
69 <publishername>Petter Reinholdtsen
</publishername>
70 <address><city>Oslo
</city></address>
75 <holder>Lawrence Lessig
</holder>
81 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cc.png" contentdepth=
"3em" width=
"100%" align=
"center"/>
84 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cc.svg" contentdepth=
"3em" width=
"100%" align=
"center"/>
87 <phrase>Creative Commons, Some rights reserved
</phrase>
93 This version of
<citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle> is licensed under
94 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
95 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
96 about the license, click the icon above, or visit
97 <ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/
1.0/
</ulink>
102 <title>ABOUT THE AUTHOR
</title>
105 (
<ulink url=
"http://www.lessig.org">http://www.lessig.org
</ulink>),
106 professor of law and a John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar
107 at Stanford Law School, is founder of the Stanford Center for Internet
108 and Society and is chairman of the Creative Commons
109 (
<ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org">http://creativecommons.org
</ulink>).
110 The author of The Future of Ideas (Random House,
2001) and Code: And
111 Other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books,
1999), Lessig is a member of
112 the boards of the Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier
113 Foundation, and Public Knowledge. He was the winner of the Free
114 Software Foundation's Award for the Advancement of Free Software,
115 twice listed in BusinessWeek's
<quote>e.biz
25,
</quote> and named one of Scientific
116 American's
<quote>50 visionaries.
</quote> A graduate of the University of
117 Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, and Yale Law School, Lessig
118 clerked for Judge Richard Posner of the U.S. Seventh Circuit Court of
123 <!-- testing different ways to tag the cover page -->
124 <mediaobject role=
"cover">
125 <imageobject remap=
"lrg" role=
"front-large">
126 <imagedata fileref=
"images/cover.png" format=
"PNG" width=
"444" />
129 <imageobject remap="s" role="front">
130 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
132 <imageobject remap="xs" role="front-small">
133 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
135 <imageobject remap="cs" role="thumbnail">
136 <imagedata fileref="images/cover_thumbnail.png" format="PNG" width="444" />
141 <biblioid class=
"isbn">978-
82-
92812-XX-Y
</biblioid>
144 http://catalog.loc.gov/cgi-bin/Pwebrecon.cgi?v3=1&DB=local&CMD=010a+2003063276&CNT=10+records+per+page
146 <biblioid class=
"libraryofcongress">2003063276</biblioid>
149 <!-- PAGE BREAK 3 -->
150 <dedication id=
"alsobylessig">
152 Also by Lawrence Lessig
159 The USA is lesterland: The nature of congressional corruption
163 Republic, lost: How money corrupts Congress - and a plan to stop it
167 Remix: Making art and commerce thrive in the hybrid economy
175 The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World
179 Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
183 <!-- PAGE BREAK 4 -->
184 <!-- PAGE BREAK 5 -->
185 <!-- PAGE BREAK 6 -->
186 <!-- PAGE BREAK 7 -->
187 <dedication><title></title>
188 <!-- FIXME figure out how to do this better in dblatex and docbook-xsl -->
189 <?latex {\Huge \centering
?>
191 To Eric Eldred
— whose work first drew me to this cause, and for whom
200 <title>List of figures
</title>
207 1 CHAPTER ONE: Creators
208 1 CHAPTER TWO: "Mere Copyists"
209 1 CHAPTER THREE: Catalogs
210 1 CHAPTER FOUR: "Pirates"
215 1 CHAPTER FIVE: "Piracy"
219 1 CHAPTER SIX: Founders
220 1 CHAPTER SEVEN: Recorders
221 1 CHAPTER EIGHT: Transformers
222 1 CHAPTER NINE: Collectors
223 1 CHAPTER TEN: "Property"
224 2 Why Hollywood Is Right
228 2 Law and Architecture: Reach
229 2 Architecture and Law: Force
230 2 Market: Concentration
233 1 CHAPTER ELEVEN: Chimera
234 1 CHAPTER TWELVE: Harms
235 2 Constraining Creators
236 2 Constraining Innovators
237 2 Corrupting Citizens
239 1 CHAPTER THIRTEEN: Eldred
240 1 CHAPTER FOURTEEN: Eldred II
244 2 Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
245 2 Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
247 2 1. More Formalities
248 3 Registration and Renewal
251 2 3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
252 2 4. Liberate the Music- -Again
253 2 5. Fire Lots of Lawyers 304
259 <!-- PAGE BREAK 11 -->
261 <preface id=
"preface">
262 <title>PREFACE
</title>
263 <indexterm id='idxpoguedavid' class='startofrange'
><primary>Pogue, David
</primary></indexterm>
265 <emphasis role=
"bold">At the end
</emphasis> of his review of my first
266 book,
<citetitle>Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace
</citetitle>, David
267 Pogue, a brilliant writer and author of countless technical and
268 computer-related texts, wrote this:
272 Unlike actual law, Internet software has no capacity to punish. It
273 doesn't affect people who aren't online (and only a tiny minority
274 of the world population is). And if you don't like the Internet's
275 system, you can always flip off the modem.
<footnote id=
"preface01"><para>
276 David Pogue,
<quote>Don't Just Chat, Do Something,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
30 January
2000.
281 Pogue was skeptical of the core argument of the book
—that
282 software, or
<quote>code,
</quote> functioned as a kind of law
—and his review
283 suggested the happy thought that if life in cyberspace got bad, we
284 could always
<quote>drizzle, drazzle, druzzle, drome
</quote>-like simply flip a
285 switch and be back home. Turn off the modem, unplug the computer, and
286 any troubles that exist in
<emphasis>that
</emphasis> space wouldn't
287 <quote>affect
</quote> us anymore.
290 Pogue might have been right in
1999—I'm skeptical, but maybe.
291 But even if he was right then, the point is not right now:
292 <citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle> is about the troubles the Internet
293 causes even after the modem is turned
295 off. It is an argument about how the battles that now rage regarding life
296 on-line have fundamentally affected
<quote>people who aren't online.
</quote> There
297 is no switch that will insulate us from the Internet's effect.
299 <indexterm startref='idxpoguedavid' class='endofrange'
/>
301 But unlike
<citetitle>Code
</citetitle>, the argument here is not much
302 about the Internet itself. It is instead about the consequence of the
303 Internet to a part of our tradition that is much more fundamental,
304 and, as hard as this is for a geek-wanna-be to admit, much more
308 That tradition is the way our culture gets made. As I explain in the
309 pages that follow, we come from a tradition of
<quote>free culture
</quote>—not
310 <quote>free
</quote> as in
<quote>free beer
</quote> (to borrow a phrase from the founder of the
311 free software movement
<footnote>
313 Richard M. Stallman,
<citetitle>Free Software, Free Societies
</citetitle> 57 (Joshua Gay, ed.
2002).
314 </para></footnote>), but
<quote>free
</quote> as in
<quote>free speech,
</quote> <quote>free markets,
</quote>
315 <quote>free trade,
</quote> <quote>free enterprise,
</quote> <quote>free will,
</quote> and
<quote>free elections.
</quote> A
316 free culture supports and protects creators and innovators. It does
317 this directly by granting intellectual property rights. But it does so
318 indirectly by limiting the reach of those rights, to guarantee that
319 follow-on creators and innovators remain
<emphasis>as free as
320 possible
</emphasis> from the control of the past. A free culture is
321 not a culture without property, just as a free market is not a market
322 in which everything is free. The opposite of a free culture is a
323 <quote>permission culture
</quote>—a culture in which creators get to create
324 only with the permission of the powerful, or of creators from the
328 If we understood this change, I believe we would resist it. Not
<quote>we
</quote>
329 on the Left or
<quote>you
</quote> on the Right, but we who have no stake in the
330 particular industries of culture that defined the twentieth century.
331 Whether you are on the Left or the Right, if you are in this sense
332 disinterested, then the story I tell here will trouble you. For the
333 changes I describe affect values that both sides of our political
334 culture deem fundamental.
336 <indexterm id='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='startofrange'
><primary>power, concentration of
</primary></indexterm>
337 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace
</primary></indexterm>
338 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
339 <indexterm><primary>Stevens, Ted
</primary></indexterm>
341 We saw a glimpse of this bipartisan outrage in the early summer of
342 2003. As the FCC considered changes in media ownership rules that
343 would relax limits on media concentration, an extraordinary coalition
344 generated more than
700,
000 letters to the FCC opposing the change.
345 As William Safire described marching
<quote>uncomfortably alongside CodePink
346 Women for Peace and the National Rifle Association, between liberal
347 Olympia Snowe and conservative Ted Stevens,
</quote> he formulated perhaps
348 most simply just what was at stake: the concentration of power. And as
353 Does that sound unconservative? Not to me. The concentration of
354 power
—political, corporate, media, cultural
—should be anathema to
355 conservatives. The diffusion of power through local control, thereby
356 encouraging individual participation, is the essence of federalism and
357 the greatest expression of democracy.
<footnote><para> William Safire,
358 <quote>The Great Media Gulp,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
22 May
2003.
359 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
364 This idea is an element of the argument of
<citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle>, though my
365 focus is not just on the concentration of power produced by
366 concentrations in ownership, but more importantly, if because less
367 visibly, on the concentration of power produced by a radical change in
368 the effective scope of the law. The law is changing; that change is
369 altering the way our culture gets made; that change should worry
370 you
—whether or not you care about the Internet, and whether you're on
371 Safire's left or on his right.
373 <indexterm startref='idxpowerconcentrationof' class='endofrange'
/>
375 <emphasis role=
"strong">The inspiration
</emphasis> for the title and for
376 much of the argument of this book comes from the work of Richard
377 Stallman and the Free Software Foundation. Indeed, as I reread
378 Stallman's own work, especially the essays in
<citetitle>Free Software, Free
379 Society
</citetitle>, I realize that all of the theoretical insights I develop here
380 are insights Stallman described decades ago. One could thus well argue
381 that this work is
<quote>merely
</quote> derivative.
384 I accept that criticism, if indeed it is a criticism. The work of a
385 lawyer is always derivative, and I mean to do nothing more in this
386 book than to remind a culture about a tradition that has always been
387 its own. Like Stallman, I defend that tradition on the basis of
388 values. Like Stallman, I believe those are the values of freedom. And
389 like Stallman, I believe those are values of our past that will need
390 to be defended in our future. A free culture has been our past, but it
391 will only be our future if we change the path we are on right now.
394 Like Stallman's arguments for free software, an argument for free
395 culture stumbles on a confusion that is hard to avoid, and even harder
396 to understand. A free culture is not a culture without property; it is not
397 a culture in which artists don't get paid. A culture without property, or
398 in which creators can't get paid, is anarchy, not freedom. Anarchy is not
402 Instead, the free culture that I defend in this book is a balance
403 between anarchy and control. A free culture, like a free market, is
404 filled with property. It is filled with rules of property and contract
405 that get enforced by the state. But just as a free market is perverted
406 if its property becomes feudal, so too can a free culture be queered
407 by extremism in the property rights that define it. That is what I
408 fear about our culture today. It is against that extremism that this
413 <!-- PAGE BREAK 15 -->
415 <!-- PAGE BREAK 16 -->
416 <chapter label=
"" id=
"c-introduction">
417 <title>INTRODUCTION
</title>
418 <indexterm id='idxwrightbrothers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
420 <emphasis role=
"strong">On December
17</emphasis>,
1903, on a windy North Carolina beach for just
421 shy of one hundred seconds, the Wright brothers demonstrated that a
422 heavier-than-air, self-propelled vehicle could fly. The moment was electric
423 and its importance widely understood. Almost immediately, there
424 was an explosion of interest in this newfound technology of manned
425 flight, and a gaggle of innovators began to build upon it.
427 <indexterm id='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>air traffic, land ownership vs.
</primary></indexterm>
428 <indexterm id='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='startofrange'
><primary>land ownership, air traffic and
</primary></indexterm>
429 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
431 At the time the Wright brothers invented the airplane, American
432 law held that a property owner presumptively owned not just the surface
433 of his land, but all the land below, down to the center of the earth,
434 and all the space above, to
<quote>an indefinite extent, upwards.
</quote><footnote><para>
435 St. George Tucker,
<citetitle>Blackstone's Commentaries
</citetitle> 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.:
436 Rothman Reprints,
1969),
18.
439 years, scholars had puzzled about how best to interpret the idea that
440 rights in land ran to the heavens. Did that mean that you owned the
441 stars? Could you prosecute geese for their willful and regular trespass?
443 <indexterm startref='idxwrightbrothers' class='endofrange'
/>
445 Then came airplanes, and for the first time, this principle of American
446 law
—deep within the foundations of our tradition, and acknowledged
447 by the most important legal thinkers of our past
—mattered. If
448 my land reaches to the heavens, what happens when United flies over
449 my field? Do I have the right to banish it from my property? Am I allowed
450 to enter into an exclusive license with Delta Airlines? Could we
451 set up an auction to decide how much these rights are worth?
453 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
454 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
456 In
1945, these questions became a federal case. When North Carolina
457 farmers Thomas Lee and Tinie Causby started losing chickens
458 because of low-flying military aircraft (the terrified chickens apparently
459 flew into the barn walls and died), the Causbys filed a lawsuit saying
460 that the government was trespassing on their land. The airplanes,
461 of course, never touched the surface of the Causbys' land. But if, as
462 Blackstone, Kent, and Coke had said, their land reached to
<quote>an indefinite
463 extent, upwards,
</quote> then the government was trespassing on their
464 property, and the Causbys wanted it to stop.
466 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
467 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
468 <indexterm id='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='startofrange'
><primary>Douglas, William O.
</primary></indexterm>
469 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='startofrange'
><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on airspace vs. land rights
</secondary></indexterm>
471 The Supreme Court agreed to hear the Causbys' case. Congress had
472 declared the airways public, but if one's property really extended to the
473 heavens, then Congress's declaration could well have been an unconstitutional
474 <quote>taking
</quote> of property without compensation. The Court acknowledged
475 that
<quote>it is ancient doctrine that common law ownership of
476 the land extended to the periphery of the universe.
</quote> But Justice Douglas
477 had no patience for ancient doctrine. In a single paragraph, hundreds of
478 years of property law were erased. As he wrote for the Court,
482 [The] doctrine has no place in the modern world. The air is a
483 public highway, as Congress has declared. Were that not true,
484 every transcontinental flight would subject the operator to countless
485 trespass suits. Common sense revolts at the idea. To recognize
486 such private claims to the airspace would clog these highways,
487 seriously interfere with their control and development in the public
488 interest, and transfer into private ownership that to which only
489 the public has a just claim.
<footnote>
491 United States v. Causby, U.S.
328 (
1946):
256,
261. The Court did find
492 that there could be a
<quote>taking
</quote> if the government's use of its land
493 effectively destroyed the value of the Causbys' land. This example was
494 suggested to me by Keith Aoki's wonderful piece,
<quote>(Intellectual)
495 Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward a Cultural Geography of
496 Authorship,
</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Law Review
</citetitle> 48 (
1996):
1293,
1333. See also Paul
497 Goldstein,
<citetitle>Real Property
</citetitle> (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press,
1984),
499 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
500 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
505 <quote>Common sense revolts at the idea.
</quote>
507 <indexterm startref='idxdouglaswilliamo' class='endofrange'
/>
509 This is how the law usually works. Not often this abruptly or
510 impatiently, but eventually, this is how it works. It was Douglas's style not to
511 dither. Other justices would have blathered on for pages to reach the
513 conclusion that Douglas holds in a single line:
<quote>Common sense revolts
514 at the idea.
</quote> But whether it takes pages or a few words, it is the special
515 genius of a common law system, as ours is, that the law adjusts to the
516 technologies of the time. And as it adjusts, it changes. Ideas that were
517 as solid as rock in one age crumble in another.
519 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
520 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
521 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
523 Or at least, this is how things happen when there's no one powerful
524 on the other side of the change. The Causbys were just farmers. And
525 though there were no doubt many like them who were upset by the
526 growing traffic in the air (though one hopes not many chickens flew
527 themselves into walls), the Causbys of the world would find it very
528 hard to unite and stop the idea, and the technology, that the Wright
529 brothers had birthed. The Wright brothers spat airplanes into the
530 technological meme pool; the idea then spread like a virus in a chicken
531 coop; farmers like the Causbys found themselves surrounded by
<quote>what
532 seemed reasonable
</quote> given the technology that the Wrights had produced.
533 They could stand on their farms, dead chickens in hand, and
534 shake their fists at these newfangled technologies all they wanted.
535 They could call their representatives or even file a lawsuit. But in the
536 end, the force of what seems
<quote>obvious
</quote> to everyone else
—the power of
537 <quote>common sense
</quote>—would prevail. Their
<quote>private interest
</quote> would not be
538 allowed to defeat an obvious public gain.
540 <indexterm startref='idxairtrafficlandownershipvs' class='endofrange'
/>
541 <indexterm startref='idxlandownershipairtrafficand' class='endofrange'
/>
542 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsairtrafficvs' class='endofrange'
/>
543 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtusonairspacevslandrights' class='endofrange'
/>
544 <indexterm id='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='startofrange'
><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
545 <indexterm><primary>Bell, Alexander Graham
</primary></indexterm>
546 <indexterm><primary>Edison, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
547 <indexterm><primary>Faraday, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
548 <indexterm id='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='startofrange'
><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of
</secondary></indexterm>
550 <emphasis role='strong'
>Edwin Howard Armstrong
</emphasis> is one of
551 America's forgotten inventor geniuses. He came to the great American
552 inventor scene just after the titans Thomas Edison and Alexander
553 Graham Bell. But his work in the area of radio technology was perhaps
554 the most important of any single inventor in the first fifty years of
555 radio. He was better educated than Michael Faraday, who as a
556 bookbinder's apprentice had discovered electric induction in
1831. But
557 he had the same intuition about how the world of radio worked, and on
558 at least three occasions, Armstrong invented profoundly important
559 technologies that advanced our understanding of radio.
560 <!-- PAGE BREAK 19 -->
563 On the day after Christmas,
1933, four patents were issued to Armstrong
564 for his most significant invention
—FM radio. Until then, consumer radio
565 had been amplitude-modulated (AM) radio. The theorists
566 of the day had said that frequency-modulated (FM) radio could never
567 work. They were right about FM radio in a narrow band of spectrum.
568 But Armstrong discovered that frequency-modulated radio in a wide
569 band of spectrum would deliver an astonishing fidelity of sound, with
570 much less transmitter power and static.
573 On November
5,
1935, he demonstrated the technology at a meeting of
574 the Institute of Radio Engineers at the Empire State Building in New
575 York City. He tuned his radio dial across a range of AM stations,
576 until the radio locked on a broadcast that he had arranged from
577 seventeen miles away. The radio fell totally silent, as if dead, and
578 then with a clarity no one else in that room had ever heard from an
579 electrical device, it produced the sound of an announcer's voice:
580 <quote>This is amateur station W2AG at Yonkers, New York, operating on
581 frequency modulation at two and a half meters.
</quote>
584 The audience was hearing something no one had thought possible:
588 A glass of water was poured before the microphone in Yonkers; it
589 sounded like a glass of water being poured.
… A paper was crumpled
590 and torn; it sounded like paper and not like a crackling forest
591 fire.
… Sousa marches were played from records and a piano solo
592 and guitar number were performed.
… The music was projected with a
593 live-ness rarely if ever heard before from a radio
<quote>music
594 box.
</quote><footnote><para>
595 Lawrence Lessing,
<citetitle>Man of High Fidelity: Edwin Howard Armstrong
</citetitle>
596 (Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company,
1956),
209.
600 <indexterm id='idxrca' class='startofrange'
><primary>RCA
</primary></indexterm>
601 <indexterm id='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='startofrange'
><primary>media
</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in
</secondary></indexterm>
603 As our own common sense tells us, Armstrong had discovered a vastly
604 superior radio technology. But at the time of his invention, Armstrong
605 was working for RCA. RCA was the dominant player in the then dominant
606 AM radio market. By
1935, there were a thousand radio stations across
607 the United States, but the stations in large cities were all owned by
608 a handful of networks.
611 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David
</primary></indexterm>
613 RCA's president, David Sarnoff, a friend of Armstrong's, was eager
614 that Armstrong discover a way to remove static from AM radio. So
615 Sarnoff was quite excited when Armstrong told him he had a device
616 that removed static from
<quote>radio.
</quote> But when Armstrong demonstrated
617 his invention, Sarnoff was not pleased.
621 I thought Armstrong would invent some kind of a filter to remove
622 static from our AM radio. I didn't think he'd start a
623 revolution
— start up a whole damn new industry to compete with
624 RCA.
<footnote><para> See
<quote>Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the
625 Electronic Era,
</quote> First Electronic Church of America, at
626 www.webstationone.com/fecha, available at
628 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
1</ulink>.
632 <indexterm id='idxfmradio' class='startofrange'
><primary>FM radio
</primary></indexterm>
633 <indexterm><primary>Sarnoff, David
</primary></indexterm>
635 Armstrong's invention threatened RCA's AM empire, so the company
636 launched a campaign to smother FM radio. While FM may have been a
637 superior technology, Sarnoff was a superior tactician. As one author
640 <indexterm id='idxlessinglawrence' class='startofrange'
><primary>Lessing, Lawrence
</primary></indexterm>
643 The forces for FM, largely engineering, could not overcome the weight
644 of strategy devised by the sales, patent, and legal offices to subdue
645 this threat to corporate position. For FM, if allowed to develop
646 unrestrained, posed
… a complete reordering of radio power
647 … and the eventual overthrow of the carefully restricted AM system
648 on which RCA had grown to power.
<footnote><para>Lessing,
226.
652 <indexterm id='idxfcconfmradio' class='startofrange'
><primary>FCC
</primary><secondary>on FM radio
</secondary></indexterm>
654 RCA at first kept the technology in house, insisting that further
655 tests were needed. When, after two years of testing, Armstrong grew
656 impatient, RCA began to use its power with the government to stall
657 FM radio's deployment generally. In
1936, RCA hired the former head
658 of the FCC and assigned him the task of assuring that the FCC assign
659 spectrum in a way that would castrate FM
—principally by moving FM
660 radio to a different band of spectrum. At first, these efforts failed. But
661 when Armstrong and the nation were distracted by World War II,
662 RCA's work began to be more successful. Soon after the war ended, the
663 FCC announced a set of policies that would have one clear effect: FM
664 radio would be crippled. As Lawrence Lessing described it,
666 <!-- PAGE BREAK 21 -->
669 The series of body blows that FM radio received right after the
670 war, in a series of rulings manipulated through the FCC by the
671 big radio interests, were almost incredible in their force and
672 deviousness.
<footnote><para>
677 <indexterm startref='idxlessinglawrence' class='endofrange'
/>
678 <indexterm><primary>AT
&T
</primary></indexterm>
680 To make room in the spectrum for RCA's latest gamble, television,
681 FM radio users were to be moved to a totally new spectrum band. The
682 power of FM radio stations was also cut, meaning FM could no longer
683 be used to beam programs from one part of the country to another.
684 (This change was strongly supported by AT
&T, because the loss of
685 FM relaying stations would mean radio stations would have to buy
686 wired links from AT
&T.) The spread of FM radio was thus choked, at
689 <indexterm startref='idxradiofmspectrumof' class='endofrange'
/>
690 <indexterm startref='idxfcconfmradio' class='endofrange'
/>
692 Armstrong resisted RCA's efforts. In response, RCA resisted
693 Armstrong's patents. After incorporating FM technology into the
694 emerging standard for television, RCA declared the patents
695 invalid
—baselessly, and almost fifteen years after they were
696 issued. It thus refused to pay him royalties. For six years, Armstrong
697 fought an expensive war of litigation to defend the patents. Finally,
698 just as the patents expired, RCA offered a settlement so low that it
699 would not even cover Armstrong's lawyers' fees. Defeated, broken, and
700 now broke, in
1954 Armstrong wrote a short note to his wife and then
701 stepped out of a thirteenth-story window to his death.
703 <indexterm startref='idxfmradio' class='endofrange'
/>
704 <indexterm startref='idxarmstrongedwinhoward' class='endofrange'
/>
705 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
706 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
708 This is how the law sometimes works. Not often this tragically, and
709 rarely with heroic drama, but sometimes, this is how it works. From
710 the beginning, government and government agencies have been subject to
711 capture. They are more likely captured when a powerful interest is
712 threatened by either a legal or technical change. That powerful
713 interest too often exerts its influence within the government to get
714 the government to protect it. The rhetoric of this protection is of
715 course always public spirited; the reality is something
716 different. Ideas that were as solid as rock in one age, but that, left
717 to themselves, would crumble in
719 another, are sustained through this subtle corruption of our political
720 process. RCA had what the Causbys did not: the power to stifle the
721 effect of technological change.
723 <indexterm startref='idxrca' class='endofrange'
/>
724 <indexterm startref='idxmediaownershipconcentrationin' class='endofrange'
/>
725 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
727 <emphasis role=
"strong">There's no
</emphasis> single inventor of the Internet. Nor is there any good date
728 upon which to mark its birth. Yet in a very short time, the Internet
729 has become part of ordinary American life. According to the Pew
730 Internet and American Life Project,
58 percent of Americans had access
731 to the Internet in
2002, up from
49 percent two years
732 before.
<footnote><para>
733 Amanda Lenhart,
<quote>The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at
734 Internet Access and the Digital Divide,
</quote> Pew Internet and American
735 Life Project,
15 April
2003:
6, available at
736 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
2</ulink>.
738 That number could well exceed two thirds of the nation by the end
742 As the Internet has been integrated into ordinary life, it has
743 changed things. Some of these changes are technical
—the Internet has
744 made communication faster, it has lowered the cost of gathering data,
745 and so on. These technical changes are not the focus of this book. They
746 are important. They are not well understood. But they are the sort of
747 thing that would simply go away if we all just switched the Internet off.
748 They don't affect people who don't use the Internet, or at least they
749 don't affect them directly. They are the proper subject of a book about
750 the Internet. But this is not a book about the Internet.
753 Instead, this book is about an effect of the Internet beyond the
754 Internet itself: an effect upon how culture is made. My claim is that
755 the Internet has induced an important and unrecognized change in that
756 process. That change will radically transform a tradition that is as
757 old as the Republic itself. Most, if they recognized this change,
758 would reject it. Yet most don't even see the change that the Internet
761 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'
/>
762 <indexterm><primary>Barlow, Joel
</primary></indexterm>
763 <indexterm id='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='startofrange'
><primary>culture
</primary><secondary>commercial vs. noncommercial
</secondary></indexterm>
764 <indexterm><primary>Webster, Noah
</primary></indexterm>
766 We can glimpse a sense of this change by distinguishing between
767 commercial and noncommercial culture, and by mapping the law's
768 regulation of each. By
<quote>commercial culture
</quote> I mean that part of our
769 culture that is produced and sold or produced to be sold. By
770 <quote>noncommercial culture
</quote> I mean all the rest. When old men sat around
772 <!-- PAGE BREAK 23 -->
773 street corners telling stories that kids and others consumed, that was
774 noncommercial culture. When Noah Webster published his
<quote>Reader,
</quote> or
775 Joel Barlow his poetry, that was commercial culture.
778 At the beginning of our history, and for just about the whole of our
779 tradition, noncommercial culture was essentially unregulated. Of
780 course, if your stories were lewd, or if your song disturbed the
781 peace, then the law might intervene. But the law was never directly
782 concerned with the creation or spread of this form of culture, and it
783 left this culture
<quote>free.
</quote> The ordinary ways in which ordinary
784 individuals shared and transformed their culture
—telling
785 stories, reenacting scenes from plays or TV, participating in fan
786 clubs, sharing music, making tapes
—were left alone by the law.
788 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>commercial creativity as primary purpose of
</secondary></indexterm>
790 The focus of the law was on commercial creativity. At first slightly,
791 then quite extensively, the law protected the incentives of creators by
792 granting them exclusive rights to their creative work, so that they could
793 sell those exclusive rights in a commercial
794 marketplace.
<footnote>
796 This is not the only purpose of copyright, though it is the overwhelmingly
797 primary purpose of the copyright established in the federal constitution.
798 State copyright law historically protected not just the commercial interest in
799 publication, but also a privacy interest. By granting authors the exclusive
800 right to first publication, state copyright law gave authors the power to
801 control the spread of facts about them. See Samuel D. Warren and Louis
802 D. Brandeis,
<quote>The Right to Privacy,
</quote> Harvard Law Review
4 (
1890):
193,
804 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
806 This is also, of course, an important part of creativity and culture,
807 and it has become an increasingly important part in America. But in no
808 sense was it dominant within our tradition. It was instead just one
809 part, a controlled part, balanced with the free.
811 <indexterm><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary> permission culture vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
812 <indexterm><primary>permission culture
</primary><secondary> free culture vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
814 This rough divide between the free and the controlled has now
815 been erased.
<footnote><para>
816 See Jessica Litman,
<citetitle>Digital Copyright
</citetitle> (New York: Prometheus Books,
818 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica
</primary></indexterm>
820 The Internet has set the stage for this erasure and, pushed by big
821 media, the law has now affected it. For the first time in our
822 tradition, the ordinary ways in which individuals create and share
823 culture fall within the reach of the regulation of the law, which has
824 expanded to draw within its control a vast amount of culture and
825 creativity that it never reached before. The technology that preserved
826 the balance of our history
—between uses of our culture that were
827 free and uses of our culture that were only upon permission
—has
828 been undone. The consequence is that we are less and less a free
829 culture, more and more a permission culture.
831 <!-- PAGE BREAK 24 -->
832 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
833 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
834 <indexterm><primary>protection of artists vs. business interests
</primary></indexterm>
836 This change gets justified as necessary to protect commercial
837 creativity. And indeed, protectionism is precisely its
838 motivation. But the protectionism that justifies the changes that I
839 will describe below is not the limited and balanced sort that has
840 defined the law in the past. This is not a protectionism to protect
841 artists. It is instead a protectionism to protect certain forms of
842 business. Corporations threatened by the potential of the Internet to
843 change the way both commercial and noncommercial culture are made and
844 shared have united to induce lawmakers to use the law to protect
845 them. It is the story of RCA and Armstrong; it is the dream of the
848 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitscommercialcreativityasprimarypurposeof' class='endofrange'
/>
850 For the Internet has unleashed an extraordinary possibility for many
851 to participate in the process of building and cultivating a culture
852 that reaches far beyond local boundaries. That power has changed the
853 marketplace for making and cultivating culture generally, and that
854 change in turn threatens established content industries. The Internet
855 is thus to the industries that built and distributed content in the
856 twentieth century what FM radio was to AM radio, or what the truck was
857 to the railroad industry of the nineteenth century: the beginning of
858 the end, or at least a substantial transformation. Digital
859 technologies, tied to the Internet, could produce a vastly more
860 competitive and vibrant market for building and cultivating culture;
861 that market could include a much wider and more diverse range of
862 creators; those creators could produce and distribute a much more
863 vibrant range of creativity; and depending upon a few important
864 factors, those creators could earn more on average from this system
865 than creators do today
—all so long as the RCAs of our day don't
866 use the law to protect themselves against this competition.
869 Yet, as I argue in the pages that follow, that is precisely what is
870 happening in our culture today. These modern-day equivalents of the
871 early twentieth-century radio or nineteenth-century railroads are
872 using their power to get the law to protect them against this new,
873 more efficient, more vibrant technology for building culture. They are
874 succeeding in their plan to remake the Internet before the Internet
877 <indexterm startref='idxculturecommercialvsnoncommercial' class='endofrange'
/>
878 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack
</primary><secondary> on creative property rights
</secondary></indexterm>
880 It doesn't seem this way to many. The battles over copyright and the
881 <!-- PAGE BREAK 25 -->
882 Internet seem remote to most. To the few who follow them, they seem
883 mainly about a much simpler brace of questions
—whether
<quote>piracy
</quote> will
884 be permitted, and whether
<quote>property
</quote> will be protected. The
<quote>war
</quote> that
885 has been waged against the technologies of the Internet
—what
886 Motion Picture Association of America (MPAA) president Jack Valenti
887 calls his
<quote>own terrorist war
</quote><footnote><para>
888 Amy Harmon,
<quote>Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates
889 Use New Tools to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club,
</quote> <citetitle>New York
890 Times
</citetitle>,
17 January
2002.
891 </para></footnote>—has been framed as a battle about the
892 rule of law and respect for property. To know which side to take in this
893 war, most think that we need only decide whether we're for property or
897 If those really were the choices, then I would be with Jack Valenti
898 and the content industry. I, too, am a believer in property, and
899 especially in the importance of what Mr. Valenti nicely calls
900 <quote>creative property.
</quote> I believe that
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong, and that the
901 law, properly tuned, should punish
<quote>piracy,
</quote> whether on or off the
905 But those simple beliefs mask a much more fundamental question
906 and a much more dramatic change. My fear is that unless we come to see
907 this change, the war to rid the world of Internet
<quote>pirates
</quote> will also rid our
908 culture of values that have been integral to our tradition from the start.
910 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>First Amendment to
</secondary></indexterm>
911 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>as protection of creators
</secondary></indexterm>
912 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment
</primary></indexterm>
913 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
915 These values built a tradition that, for at least the first
180 years of
916 our Republic, guaranteed creators the right to build freely upon their
917 past, and protected creators and innovators from either state or private
918 control. The First Amendment protected creators against state control.
919 And as Professor Neil Netanel powerfully argues,
<footnote>
921 Neil W. Netanel,
<quote>Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
922 Journal
</citetitle> 106 (
1996):
283.
923 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
925 copyright law, properly balanced, protected creators against private
926 control. Our tradition was thus neither Soviet nor the tradition of
927 patrons. It instead carved out a wide berth within which creators
928 could cultivate and extend our culture.
931 Yet the law's response to the Internet, when tied to changes in the
932 technology of the Internet itself, has massively increased the
933 effective regulation of creativity in America. To build upon or
934 critique the culture around us one must ask, Oliver Twist
–like,
935 for permission first. Permission is, of course, often
936 granted
—but it is not often granted to the critical or the
937 independent. We have built a kind of cultural nobility; those within
938 the noble class live easily; those outside it don't. But it is
939 nobility of any form that is alien to our tradition.
941 <!-- PAGE BREAK 26. FIXME: Ask author if "Is it" should be "It is" ? -->
943 The story that follows is about this war. It is not about the
944 <quote>centrality of technology
</quote> to ordinary life. I don't believe in gods,
945 digital or otherwise. Nor is it an effort to demonize any individual
946 or group, for neither do I believe in a devil, corporate or
947 otherwise. It is not a morality tale. Nor is it a call to jihad
951 It is instead an effort to understand a hopelessly destructive war
952 inspired by the technologies of the Internet but reaching far beyond
953 its code. And by understanding this battle, it is an effort to map
954 peace. There is no good reason for the current struggle around
955 Internet technologies to continue. There will be great harm to our
956 tradition and culture if it is allowed to continue unchecked. We must
957 come to understand the source of this war. We must resolve it soon.
959 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
960 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
961 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary></indexterm>
963 <emphasis role=
"strong">Like the Causbys'
</emphasis> battle, this war is, in part, about
<quote>property.
</quote> The
964 property of this war is not as tangible as the Causbys', and no
965 innocent chicken has yet to lose its life. Yet the ideas surrounding
966 this
<quote>property
</quote> are as obvious to most as the Causbys' claim about the
967 sacredness of their farm was to them. We are the Causbys. Most of us
968 take for granted the extraordinarily powerful claims that the owners
969 of
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> now assert. Most of us, like the Causbys,
970 treat these claims as obvious. And hence we, like the Causbys, object
971 when a new technology interferes with this property. It is as plain to
972 us as it was to them that the new technologies of the Internet are
973 <quote>trespassing
</quote> upon legitimate claims of
<quote>property.
</quote> It is as plain to
974 us as it was to them that the law should intervene to stop this
977 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
978 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
979 <indexterm><primary>Wright brothers
</primary></indexterm>
981 And thus, when geeks and technologists defend their Armstrong or
982 Wright brothers technology, most of us are simply unsympathetic.
983 Common sense does not revolt. Unlike in the case of the unlucky
984 Causbys, common sense is on the side of the property owners in this
987 the lucky Wright brothers, the Internet has not inspired a revolution
990 <indexterm><primary>power, concentration of
</primary></indexterm>
992 My hope is to push this common sense along. I have become increasingly
993 amazed by the power of this idea of intellectual property and, more
994 importantly, its power to disable critical thought by policy makers
995 and citizens. There has never been a time in our history when more of
996 our
<quote>culture
</quote> was as
<quote>owned
</quote> as it is now. And yet there has never
997 been a time when the concentration of power to control the
998 <emphasis>uses
</emphasis> of culture has been as unquestioningly
999 accepted as it is now.
1002 The puzzle is, Why? Is it because we have come to understand a truth
1003 about the value and importance of absolute property over ideas and
1004 culture? Is it because we have discovered that our tradition of
1005 rejecting such an absolute claim was wrong?
1008 Or is it because the idea of absolute property over ideas and culture
1009 benefits the RCAs of our time and fits our own unreflective intuitions?
1012 Is the radical shift away from our tradition of free culture an instance
1013 of America correcting a mistake from its past, as we did after a bloody
1014 war with slavery, and as we are slowly doing with inequality? Or is the
1015 radical shift away from our tradition of free culture yet another example
1016 of a political system captured by a few powerful special interests?
1019 Does common sense lead to the extremes on this question because common
1020 sense actually believes in these extremes? Or does common sense stand
1021 silent in the face of these extremes because, as with Armstrong versus
1022 RCA, the more powerful side has ensured that it has the more powerful
1025 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
1026 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
1028 I don't mean to be mysterious. My own views are resolved. I believe it
1029 was right for common sense to revolt against the extremism of the
1030 Causbys. I believe it would be right for common sense to revolt
1031 against the extreme claims made today on behalf of
<quote>intellectual
1032 property.
</quote> What the law demands today is increasingly as silly as a
1033 sheriff arresting an airplane for trespass. But the consequences of
1034 this silliness will be much more profound.
1035 <!-- PAGE BREAK 28 -->
1037 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrights' class='endofrange'
/>
1039 <emphasis role=
"strong">The struggle
</emphasis> that rages just now centers on two ideas:
<quote>piracy
</quote> and
1040 <quote>property.
</quote> My aim in this book's next two parts is to explore these two
1044 My method is not the usual method of an academic. I don't want to
1045 plunge you into a complex argument, buttressed with references to
1046 obscure French theorists
—however natural that is for the weird
1047 sort we academics have become. Instead I begin in each part with a
1048 collection of stories that set a context within which these apparently
1049 simple ideas can be more fully understood.
1052 The two sections set up the core claim of this book: that while the
1053 Internet has indeed produced something fantastic and new, our
1054 government, pushed by big media to respond to this
<quote>something new,
</quote> is
1055 destroying something very old. Rather than understanding the changes
1056 the Internet might permit, and rather than taking time to let
<quote>common
1057 sense
</quote> resolve how best to respond, we are allowing those most
1058 threatened by the changes to use their power to change the
1059 law
—and more importantly, to use their power to change something
1060 fundamental about who we have always been.
1063 We allow this, I believe, not because it is right, and not because
1064 most of us really believe in these changes. We allow it because the
1065 interests most threatened are among the most powerful players in our
1066 depressingly compromised process of making law. This book is the story
1067 of one more consequence of this form of corruption
—a consequence
1068 to which most of us remain oblivious.
1071 <!-- PAGE BREAK 29 -->
1072 <part id=
"c-piracy">
1073 <title><quote>PIRACY
</quote></title>
1075 <!-- PAGE BREAK 30 -->
1076 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>English
</secondary></indexterm>
1077 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord
</primary></indexterm>
1078 <indexterm><primary>music publishing
</primary></indexterm>
1079 <indexterm><primary>sheet music
</primary></indexterm>
1081 <emphasis role=
"strong">Since the inception
</emphasis> of the law regulating creative property, there has
1082 been a war against
<quote>piracy.
</quote> The precise contours of this concept,
1083 <quote>piracy,
</quote> are hard to sketch, but the animating injustice is easy to
1084 capture. As Lord Mansfield wrote in a case that extended the reach of
1085 English copyright law to include sheet music,
1089 A person may use the copy by playing it, but he has no right to
1090 rob the author of the profit, by multiplying copies and disposing
1091 of them for his own use.
<footnote><para>
1093 <citetitle>Bach
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Longman
</citetitle>,
98 Eng. Rep.
1274 (
1777) (Mansfield).
1096 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord' class='endofrange'
/>
1098 <indexterm><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary> efficient content distribution on
</secondary></indexterm>
1099 <indexterm id='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='startofrange'
><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing
</primary><secondary>efficiency of
</secondary></indexterm>
1101 Today we are in the middle of another
<quote>war
</quote> against
<quote>piracy.
</quote> The
1102 Internet has provoked this war. The Internet makes possible the
1103 efficient spread of content. Peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing is among
1104 the most efficient of the efficient technologies the Internet
1105 enables. Using distributed intelligence, p2p systems facilitate the
1106 easy spread of content in a way unimagined a generation ago.
1107 <!-- PAGE BREAK 31 -->
1110 This efficiency does not respect the traditional lines of copyright.
1111 The network doesn't discriminate between the sharing of copyrighted
1112 and uncopyrighted content. Thus has there been a vast amount of
1113 sharing of copyrighted content. That sharing in turn has excited the
1114 war, as copyright owners fear the sharing will
<quote>rob the author of the
1117 <indexterm startref='idxpeertopeerppfilesharingefficiencyof' class='endofrange'
/>
1119 The warriors have turned to the courts, to the legislatures, and
1120 increasingly to technology to defend their
<quote>property
</quote> against this
1121 <quote>piracy.
</quote> A generation of Americans, the warriors warn, is being
1122 raised to believe that
<quote>property
</quote> should be
<quote>free.
</quote> Forget tattoos,
1123 never mind body piercing
—our kids are becoming
1124 <emphasis>thieves
</emphasis>!
1127 There's no doubt that
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong, and that pirates should be
1128 punished. But before we summon the executioners, we should put this
1129 notion of
<quote>piracy
</quote> in some context. For as the concept is increasingly
1130 used, at its core is an extraordinary idea that is almost certainly wrong.
1133 The idea goes something like this:
1137 Creative work has value; whenever I use, or take, or build upon
1138 the creative work of others, I am taking from them something of
1139 value. Whenever I take something of value from someone else, I
1140 should have their permission. The taking of something of value
1141 from someone else without permission is wrong. It is a form of
1145 <indexterm><primary>ASCAP
</primary></indexterm>
1146 <indexterm><primary>Dreyfuss, Rochelle
</primary></indexterm>
1147 <indexterm><primary>Girl Scouts
</primary></indexterm>
1148 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='startofrange'
><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory of
</secondary></indexterm>
1149 <indexterm id='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='startofrange'
><primary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory
</primary></indexterm>
1151 This view runs deep within the current debates. It is what NYU law
1152 professor Rochelle Dreyfuss criticizes as the
<quote>if value, then right
</quote>
1153 theory of creative property
<footnote><para>
1155 See Rochelle Dreyfuss,
<quote>Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language
1156 in the Pepsi Generation,
</quote> <citetitle>Notre Dame Law Review
</citetitle> 65 (
1990):
397.
1158 —if there is value, then someone must have a
1159 right to that value. It is the perspective that led a composers' rights
1160 organization, ASCAP, to sue the Girl Scouts for failing to pay for the
1161 songs that girls sang around Girl Scout campfires.
<footnote><para>
1163 Lisa Bannon,
<quote>The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay
1164 Up,
</quote> <citetitle>Wall Street Journal
</citetitle>,
21 August
1996, available at
1165 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
3</ulink>; Jonathan
1166 Zittrain,
<quote>Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free
1167 Speech, No One Wins,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
24 November
2002.
1168 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
1170 There was
<quote>value
</quote> (the songs) so there must have been a
1171 <quote>right
</quote>—even against the Girl Scouts.
1173 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyifvaluethenrighttheoryof' class='endofrange'
/>
1175 This idea is certainly a possible understanding of how creative
1176 property should work. It might well be a possible design for a system
1177 <!-- PAGE BREAK 32 -->
1178 of law protecting creative property. But the
<quote>if value, then right
</quote>
1179 theory of creative property has never been America's theory of
1180 creative property. It has never taken hold within our law.
1182 <indexterm startref='idxifvaluethenrighttheory' class='endofrange'
/>
1183 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
1184 <indexterm id='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>legal restrictions on
</secondary></indexterm>
1186 Instead, in our tradition, intellectual property is an instrument. It
1187 sets the groundwork for a richly creative society but remains
1188 subservient to the value of creativity. The current debate has this
1189 turned around. We have become so concerned with protecting the
1190 instrument that we are losing sight of the value.
1193 The source of this confusion is a distinction that the law no longer
1194 takes care to draw
—the distinction between republishing someone's
1195 work on the one hand and building upon or transforming that work on
1196 the other. Copyright law at its birth had only publishing as its concern;
1197 copyright law today regulates both.
1199 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork' class='endofrange'
/>
1201 Before the technologies of the Internet, this conflation didn't matter
1202 all that much. The technologies of publishing were expensive; that
1203 meant the vast majority of publishing was commercial. Commercial
1204 entities could bear the burden of the law
—even the burden of the
1205 Byzantine complexity that copyright law has become. It was just one
1206 more expense of doing business.
1208 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>creativity impeded by
</secondary></indexterm>
1209 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
1210 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)
</primary></indexterm>
1212 But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of
1213 the law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of
1214 commercial creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that
1215 expansion would not matter much if copyright law regulated only
1216 <quote>copying,
</quote> when the law regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does,
1217 the extension matters a lot. The burden of this law now vastly
1218 outweighs any original benefit
—certainly as it affects
1219 noncommercial creativity, and increasingly as it affects commercial
1220 creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see more clearly in the chapters
1221 below, the law's role is less and less to support creativity, and more
1222 and more to protect certain industries against competition. Just at
1223 the time digital technology could unleash an extraordinary range of
1224 commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law burdens this
1225 creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the threat
1226 of obscenely severe penalties. We may
1227 <!-- PAGE BREAK 33 -->
1228 be seeing, as Richard Florida writes, the
<quote>Rise of the Creative
1229 Class.
</quote><footnote>
1232 In
<citetitle>The Rise of the Creative Class
</citetitle> (New York:
1233 Basic Books,
2002), Richard Florida documents a shift in the nature of
1234 labor toward a labor of creativity. His work, however, doesn't
1235 directly address the legal conditions under which that creativity is
1236 enabled or stifled. I certainly agree with him about the importance
1237 and significance of this change, but I also believe the conditions
1238 under which it will be enabled are much more tenuous.
1240 <indexterm><primary>Florida, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
1241 <indexterm><primary>Rise of the Creative Class, The (Florida)
</primary></indexterm>
1243 Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of regulation of
1244 this creative class.
1246 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitylegalrestrictionson' class='endofrange'
/>
1248 These burdens make no sense in our tradition. We should begin by
1249 understanding that tradition a bit more and by placing in their proper
1250 context the current battles about behavior labeled
<quote>piracy.
</quote>
1254 <!-- PAGE BREAK 34 -->
1255 <chapter label=
"1" id=
"creators">
1256 <title>Creators
</title>
1257 <indexterm id='idxanimatedcartoons' class='startofrange'
><primary>animated cartoons
</primary></indexterm>
1258 <indexterm id='idxcartoonfilms' class='startofrange'
><primary>cartoon films
</primary></indexterm>
1259 <indexterm id='idxfilmsanimated' class='startofrange'
><primary>films
</primary><secondary>animated
</secondary></indexterm>
1260 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatwillie' class='startofrange'
><primary>Steamboat Willie
</primary></indexterm>
1261 <indexterm id='idxmickeymouse' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mickey Mouse
</primary></indexterm>
1263 <emphasis role=
"strong">In
1928</emphasis>, a cartoon character was born. An early Mickey Mouse
1264 made his debut in May of that year, in a silent flop called
<citetitle>Plane Crazy
</citetitle>.
1265 In November, in New York City's Colony Theater, in the first widely
1266 distributed cartoon synchronized with sound,
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle> brought
1267 to life the character that would become Mickey Mouse.
1269 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1271 Synchronized sound had been introduced to film a year earlier in the
1272 movie
<citetitle>The Jazz Singer
</citetitle>. That success led Walt Disney to copy the
1273 technique and mix sound with cartoons. No one knew whether it would
1274 work or, if it did work, whether it would win an audience. But when
1275 Disney ran a test in the summer of
1928, the results were unambiguous.
1276 As Disney describes that first experiment,
1280 A couple of my boys could read music, and one of them could play
1281 a mouth organ. We put them in a room where they could not see
1282 the screen and arranged to pipe their sound into the room where
1283 our wives and friends were going to see the picture.
1284 <!-- PAGE BREAK 35 -->
1287 The boys worked from a music and sound-effects score. After several
1288 false starts, sound and action got off with the gun. The mouth
1289 organist played the tune, the rest of us in the sound department
1290 bammed tin pans and blew slide whistles on the beat. The
1291 synchronization was pretty close.
1294 The effect on our little audience was nothing less than electric.
1295 They responded almost instinctively to this union of sound and
1296 motion. I thought they were kidding me. So they put me in the audience
1297 and ran the action again. It was terrible, but it was wonderful! And
1298 it was something new!
<footnote><para>
1300 Leonard Maltin,
<citetitle>Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated
1301 Cartoons
</citetitle> (New York: Penguin Books,
1987),
34–35.
1305 <indexterm><primary>Iwerks, Ub
</primary></indexterm>
1307 Disney's then partner, and one of animation's most extraordinary
1308 talents, Ub Iwerks, put it more strongly:
<quote>I have never been so thrilled
1309 in my life. Nothing since has ever equaled it.
</quote>
1312 Disney had created something very new, based upon something relatively
1313 new. Synchronized sound brought life to a form of creativity that had
1314 rarely
—except in Disney's hands
—been anything more than
1315 filler for other films. Throughout animation's early history, it was
1316 Disney's invention that set the standard that others struggled to
1317 match. And quite often, Disney's great genius, his spark of
1318 creativity, was built upon the work of others.
1320 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt' class='endofrange'
/>
1321 <indexterm id='idxkeatonbuster' class='startofrange'
><primary>Keaton, Buster
</primary></indexterm>
1322 <indexterm id='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='startofrange'
><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
1324 This much is familiar. What you might not know is that
1928 also marks
1325 another important transition. In that year, a comic (as opposed to
1326 cartoon) genius created his last independently produced silent film.
1327 That genius was Buster Keaton. The film was
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>.
1330 Keaton was born into a vaudeville family in
1895. In the era of silent
1331 film, he had mastered using broad physical comedy as a way to spark
1332 uncontrollable laughter from his audience.
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1333 Jr
</citetitle>. was a classic of this form, famous among film buffs for its
1334 incredible stunts. The film was classic Keaton
—wildly popular
1335 and among the best of its genre.
1337 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1338 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1340 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat
1342 <!-- PAGE BREAK 36 -->
1343 The coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a
1344 direct cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,
<footnote><para>
1346 I am grateful to David Gerstein and his careful history, described at
1347 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
4</ulink>.
1348 According to Dave Smith of the Disney Archives, Disney paid royalties to
1349 use the music for five songs in
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle>:
<quote>Steamboat Bill,
</quote> <quote>The
1350 Simpleton
</quote> (Delille),
<quote>Mischief Makers
</quote> (Carbonara),
<quote>Joyful Hurry No.
1</quote>
1351 (Baron), and
<quote>Gawky Rube
</quote> (Lakay). A sixth song,
<quote>The Turkey in the
1352 Straw,
</quote> was already in the public domain. Letter from David Smith to
1353 Harry Surden,
10 July
2003, on file with author.
1355 and both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from
1356 the invention of synchronized sound in
<citetitle>The Jazz Singer
</citetitle> that we
1357 get
<citetitle>Steamboat Willie
</citetitle>. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of
1358 Steamboat Bill, Jr., itself inspired by the song
<quote>Steamboat Bill,
</quote>
1359 that we get Steamboat Willie, and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey
1362 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatwillie' class='endofrange'
/>
1363 <indexterm startref='idxmickeymouse' class='endofrange'
/>
1364 <indexterm startref='idxkeatonbuster' class='endofrange'
/>
1365 <indexterm startref='idxsteamboatbilljr' class='endofrange'
/>
1366 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works
</secondary></indexterm>
1367 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
1369 This
<quote>borrowing
</quote> was nothing unique, either for Disney or for the
1370 industry. Disney was always parroting the feature-length mainstream
1371 films of his day.
<footnote><para>
1373 He was also a fan of the public domain. See Chris Sprigman,
<quote>The Mouse
1374 that Ate the Public Domain,
</quote> Findlaw,
5 March
2002, at
1375 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
5</ulink>.
1377 So did many others. Early cartoons are filled with
1378 knockoffs
—slight variations on winning themes; retellings of
1379 ancient stories. The key to success was the brilliance of the
1380 differences. With Disney, it was sound that gave his animation its
1381 spark. Later, it was the quality of his work relative to the
1382 production-line cartoons with which he competed. Yet these additions
1383 were built upon a base that was borrowed. Disney added to the work of
1384 others before him, creating something new out of something just barely
1387 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales' class='startofrange'
><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
1389 Sometimes this borrowing was slight. Sometimes it was significant.
1390 Think about the fairy tales of the Brothers Grimm. If you're as
1391 oblivious as I was, you're likely to think that these tales are happy,
1392 sweet stories, appropriate for any child at bedtime. In fact, the
1393 Grimm fairy tales are, well, for us, grim. It is a rare and perhaps
1394 overly ambitious parent who would dare to read these bloody,
1395 moralistic stories to his or her child, at bedtime or anytime.
1398 Disney took these stories and retold them in a way that carried them
1399 into a new age. He animated the stories, with both characters and
1400 light. Without removing the elements of fear and danger altogether, he
1401 made funny what was dark and injected a genuine emotion of compassion
1402 where before there was fear. And not just with the work of the
1403 Brothers Grimm. Indeed, the catalog of Disney work drawing upon the
1404 work of others is astonishing when set together:
<citetitle>Snow White
</citetitle>
1405 (
1937),
<citetitle>Fantasia
</citetitle> (
1940),
<citetitle>Pinocchio
</citetitle> (
1940),
<citetitle>Dumbo
</citetitle>
1406 (
1941),
<citetitle>Bambi
</citetitle> (
1942),
<citetitle>Song of the South
</citetitle> (
1946),
1407 <citetitle>Cinderella
</citetitle> (
1950),
<citetitle>Alice in Wonderland
</citetitle> (
1951),
<citetitle>Robin
1408 Hood
</citetitle> (
1952),
<citetitle>Peter Pan
</citetitle> (
1953),
<citetitle>Lady and the Tramp
</citetitle>
1409 <!-- PAGE BREAK 37 -->
1410 (
1955),
<citetitle>Mulan
</citetitle> (
1998),
<citetitle>Sleeping Beauty
</citetitle> (
1959),
<citetitle>101
1411 Dalmatians
</citetitle> (
1961),
<citetitle>The Sword in the Stone
</citetitle> (
1963), and
1412 <citetitle>The Jungle Book
</citetitle> (
1967)
—not to mention a recent example
1413 that we should perhaps quickly forget,
<citetitle>Treasure Planet
</citetitle>
1414 (
2003). In all of these cases, Disney (or Disney, Inc.) ripped
1415 creativity from the culture around him, mixed that creativity with his
1416 own extraordinary talent, and then burned that mix into the soul of
1417 his culture. Rip, mix, and burn.
1419 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales' class='endofrange'
/>
1421 This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should
1422 remember and celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no
1423 creativity except this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize
1424 its importance. We could call this
<quote>Disney creativity,
</quote> though that
1425 would be a bit misleading. It is, more precisely,
<quote>Walt Disney
1426 creativity
</quote>—a form of expression and genius that builds upon the
1427 culture around us and makes it something different.
1429 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs' class='endofrange'
/>
1430 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs' class='endofrange'
/>
1431 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks' class='endofrange'
/>
1432 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
1433 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>defined
</secondary></indexterm>
1434 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>traditional term for conversion to
</secondary></indexterm>
1435 <para> In
1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was
1436 relatively fresh. The public domain in
1928 was not very old and was
1437 therefore quite vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around
1438 thirty years
—for that minority of creative work that was in fact
1439 copyrighted.
<footnote><para>
1441 Until
1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an
1442 initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the
<quote>average
</quote> term by
1444 the weighted average of total registrations for any particular year,
1445 and the proportion renewing. Thus, if
100 copyrights are registered in year
1446 1, and only
15 are renewed, and the renewal term is
28 years, then the
1448 term is
32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, see the
1449 Web site associated with this book, available at
1450 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
6</ulink>.
1452 That means that for thirty years, on average, the authors or
1453 copyright holders of a creative work had an
<quote>exclusive right
</quote> to control
1454 certain uses of the work. To use this copyrighted work in limited ways
1455 required the permission of the copyright owner.
1458 At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain.
1459 No permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No
1460 permission and, hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a
<quote>lawyer-free
1461 zone.
</quote> Thus, most of the content from the nineteenth century was free
1462 for Disney to use and build upon in
1928. It was free for
1463 anyone
— whether connected or not, whether rich or not, whether
1464 approved or not
—to use and build upon.
1466 <indexterm startref='idxanimatedcartoons' class='endofrange'
/>
1467 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsanimated' class='endofrange'
/>
1469 This is the ways things always were
—until quite recently. For most
1470 of our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From
1471 until
1978, the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two
1472 years, meaning that most culture just a generation and a half old was
1474 <!-- PAGE BREAK 38 -->
1475 free for anyone to build upon without the permission of anyone else.
1476 Today's equivalent would be for creative work from the
1960s and
1970s
1477 to now be free for the next Walt Disney to build upon without
1478 permission. Yet today, the public domain is presumptive only for
1479 content from before the Great Depression.
1481 <indexterm startref='idxcartoonfilms' class='endofrange'
/>
1482 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc' class='endofrange'
/>
1483 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof' class='endofrange'
/>
1484 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaindefined' class='endofrange'
/>
1485 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomaintraditionaltermforconversionto' class='endofrange'
/>
1486 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1488 <emphasis role=
"strong">Of course
</emphasis>, Walt Disney had no monopoly on
<quote>Walt Disney creativity.
</quote>
1489 Nor does America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and
1490 except within totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite
1493 <indexterm id='idxcomicsjapanese' class='startofrange'
><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1494 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1495 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics' class='startofrange'
><primary>Japanese comics
</primary></indexterm>
1496 <indexterm id='idxmanga' class='startofrange'
><primary>manga
</primary></indexterm>
1497 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
1499 Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many
1500 Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture:
<citetitle>manga
</citetitle>, or
1501 comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some
40 percent of
1502 publications are comics, and
30 percent of publication revenue derives
1503 from comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every
1504 magazine stand, carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's
1505 extraordinary system of public transportation.
1508 Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an
1509 unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand
1510 much about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to
1511 the stories that these
<quote>graphic novels
</quote> tell. For the Japanese, manga
1512 cover every aspect of social life. For us, comics are
<quote>men in tights.
</quote>
1513 And anyway, it's not as if the New York subways are filled with
1514 readers of Joyce or even Hemingway. People of different cultures
1515 distract themselves in different ways, the Japanese in this
1516 interestingly different way.
1519 But my purpose here is not to understand manga. It is to describe a
1520 variant on manga that from a lawyer's perspective is quite odd, but
1521 from a Disney perspective is quite familiar.
1523 <indexterm id='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='startofrange'
><primary>creativity
</primary><secondary>by transforming previous works
</secondary></indexterm>
1524 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics' class='startofrange'
><primary>doujinshi comics
</primary></indexterm>
1526 This is the phenomenon of
<citetitle>doujinshi
</citetitle>. Doujinshi are also comics, but
1527 they are a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of
1528 doujinshi. It is not doujinshi if it is
<emphasis>just
</emphasis> a
1529 copy; the artist must make a contribution to the art he copies, by
1530 transforming it either subtly or
1531 <!-- PAGE BREAK 39 -->
1532 significantly. A doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and
1533 develop it differently
—with a different story line. Or the comic can
1534 keep the character in character but change its look slightly. There is no
1535 formula for what makes the doujinshi sufficiently
<quote>different.
</quote> But they
1536 must be different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed,
1537 there are committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows
1538 and reject any copycat comic that is merely a copy.
1540 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1542 These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are
1543 huge. More than
33,
000 <quote>circles
</quote> of creators from across Japan produce
1544 these bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than
450,
000 Japanese come
1545 together twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country,
1546 to exchange and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the
1547 mainstream commercial manga market. In some ways, it obviously
1548 competes with that market, but there is no sustained effort by those
1549 who control the commercial manga market to shut the doujinshi market
1550 down. It flourishes, despite the competition and despite the law.
1552 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1553 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
1555 The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained
1556 in the law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under
1557 Japanese copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors
1558 American copyright law, the doujinshi market is an illegal
1559 one. Doujinshi are plainly
<quote>derivative works.
</quote> There is no general
1560 practice by doujinshi artists of securing the permission of the manga
1561 creators. Instead, the practice is simply to take and modify the
1562 creations of others, as Walt Disney did with
<citetitle>Steamboat Bill,
1563 Jr
</citetitle>. Under both Japanese and American law, that
<quote>taking
</quote> without
1564 the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an
1565 infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative
1566 work without the original copyright owner's permission.
1568 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt2' class='endofrange'
/>
1569 <indexterm id='idxwinickjudd' class='startofrange'
><primary>Winick, Judd
</primary></indexterm>
1571 Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in
1572 the view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga
1573 flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me,
<quote>The
1574 early days of comics in America are very much like what's going on
1575 in Japan now.
… American comics were born out of copying each
1576 <!-- PAGE BREAK 40 -->
1577 other.
… That's how [the artists] learn to draw
— by going into comic
1578 books and not tracing them, but looking at them and copying them
</quote>
1579 and building from them.
<footnote><para>
1581 For an excellent history, see Scott McCloud,
<citetitle>Reinventing Comics
</citetitle> (New
1582 York: Perennial,
2000).
1585 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese' class='endofrange'
/>
1586 <indexterm><primary>Superman comics
</primary></indexterm>
1588 American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part
1589 because of the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are
1590 allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me,
<quote>there are these rules
1591 and you have to stick to them.
</quote> There are things Superman
<quote>cannot
</quote>
1592 do.
<quote>As a creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters
1593 which are fifty years old.
</quote>
1595 <indexterm startref='idxwinickjudd' class='endofrange'
/>
1596 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1597 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1598 <indexterm id='idxmehrasalil' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mehra, Salil
</primary></indexterm>
1600 The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is
1601 precisely the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that
1602 explains the mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra,
1603 for example, hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these
1604 technical violations because they spur the manga market to be more
1605 wealthy and productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were
1606 banned, so the law does not ban doujinshi.
<footnote><para>
1608 See Salil K. Mehra,
<quote>Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain
1609 Why All the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?
</quote> <citetitle>Rutgers Law
1610 Review
</citetitle> 55 (
2002):
155,
182.
<quote>[T]here might be a collective economic
1611 rationality that would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing
1612 legal actions for infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga
1613 artists may be better off collectively if they set aside their
1614 individual self-interest and decide not to press their legal
1615 rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma solved.
</quote>
1618 <indexterm startref='idxcomicsjapanese' class='endofrange'
/>
1619 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics' class='endofrange'
/>
1620 <indexterm startref='idxmanga' class='endofrange'
/>
1622 The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges,
1623 is that the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not
1624 clear. It may well be that the market as a whole is better off if
1625 doujinshi are permitted rather than banned, but that doesn't explain
1626 why individual copyright owners don't sue nonetheless. If the law has
1627 no general exception for doujinshi, and indeed in some cases
1628 individual manga artists have sued doujinshi artists, why is there not
1629 a more general pattern of blocking this
<quote>free taking
</quote> by the doujinshi
1632 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese2' class='endofrange'
/>
1633 <indexterm startref='idxmehrasalil' class='endofrange'
/>
1635 I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question
1636 as often as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by
1637 a friend from a major Japanese law firm.
<quote>We don't have enough
1638 lawyers,
</quote> he told me one afternoon. There
<quote>just aren't enough resources
1639 to prosecute cases like this.
</quote>
1642 This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a
1643 function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those
1644 words have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is
1645 begged: Would Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga
1646 <!-- PAGE BREAK 41 -->
1647 be richer if doujinshi artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the
1648 Japanese gain something important if they could end this practice of
1649 uncompensated sharing? Does piracy here hurt the victims of the
1650 piracy, or does it help them? Would lawyers fighting this piracy help
1651 their clients or hurt them?
1653 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics' class='endofrange'
/>
1655 <emphasis role='strong'
>Let's pause
</emphasis> for a moment.
1658 If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they
1659 first start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should
1660 be puzzled about something you hadn't thought through before.
1663 We live in a world that celebrates
<quote>property.
</quote> I am one of those
1664 celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also
1665 believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call
1666 <quote>intellectual property.
</quote><footnote><para>
1668 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
1669 The term
<citetitle>intellectual property
</citetitle> is of relatively recent origin. See
1670 Siva Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
11 (New York: New York
1671 University Press,
2001). See also Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>
1672 (New York: Random House,
2001),
293 n.
26. The term accurately
1673 describes a set of
<quote>property
</quote> rights
— copyright, patents,
1674 trademark, and trade-secret
— but the nature of those rights is
1677 A large, diverse society cannot survive without property; a large,
1678 diverse, and modern society cannot flourish without intellectual
1681 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1682 <indexterm id='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
1683 <indexterm><primary>Keaton, Buster
</primary></indexterm>
1685 But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is
1686 plenty of value out there that
<quote>property
</quote> doesn't capture. I don't
1687 mean
<quote>money can't buy you love,
</quote> but rather, value that is plainly
1688 part of a process of production, including commercial as well as
1689 noncommercial production. If Disney animators had stolen a set of
1690 pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd have no hesitation in
1691 condemning that taking as wrong
— even though trivial, even if
1692 unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the law of the
1693 day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers
1694 Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because
1695 Disney's use would have been considered
<quote>fair.
</quote> There was nothing
1696 wrong with the taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in
1699 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='startofrange'
><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>derivative works based on
</secondary></indexterm>
1701 Thus, even though the things that Disney took
—or more generally,
1702 the things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity
—are
1703 valuable, our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some
1705 <!-- PAGE BREAK 42 -->
1706 things remain free for the taking within a free culture, and that
1709 <indexterm startref='idxgrimmfairytales2' class='endofrange'
/>
1710 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>Japanese
</secondary></indexterm>
1711 <indexterm><primary>comics, Japanese
</primary></indexterm>
1712 <indexterm id='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='startofrange'
><primary>doujinshi comics
</primary></indexterm>
1713 <indexterm id='idxjapanesecomics2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Japanese comics
</primary></indexterm>
1714 <indexterm id='idxmanga2' class='startofrange'
><primary>manga
</primary></indexterm>
1716 The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into
1717 a publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest
1718 work
—or even one copy
—without paying, we'd have no hesitation in
1719 saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would
1720 have stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever
1721 form, whether large or small.
1723 <indexterm startref='idxcreativitybytransformingpreviousworks2' class='endofrange'
/>
1725 Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to
1726 say that the copycat comic artists are
<quote>stealing.
</quote> This form of Walt
1727 Disney creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in
1728 particular find it hard to say why.
1730 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs2' class='endofrange'
/>
1731 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs2' class='endofrange'
/>
1732 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawjapanese3' class='endofrange'
/>
1733 <indexterm startref='idxdoujinshicomics2' class='endofrange'
/>
1734 <indexterm startref='idxjapanesecomics2' class='endofrange'
/>
1735 <indexterm startref='idxmanga2' class='endofrange'
/>
1736 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
1738 It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you
1739 begin to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists
1740 without asking or paying for the privilege. (
<quote>Excuse me, Professor
1741 Einstein, but may I have permission to use your theory of relativity
1742 to show that you were wrong about quantum physics?
</quote>) Acting companies
1743 perform adaptations of the works of Shakespeare without securing
1744 permission from anyone. (Does
<emphasis>anyone
</emphasis> believe
1745 Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a
1746 central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of
1747 Shakespeare must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles
1748 with a certain kind of movie: five asteroid films in the late
1990s;
1749 two volcano disaster films in
1997.
1752 Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building
1753 upon the creativity that went before and that surrounds them now.
1754 That building is always and everywhere at least partially done without
1755 permission and without compensating the original creator. No society,
1756 free or controlled, has ever demanded that every use be paid for or that
1757 permission for Walt Disney creativity must always be sought. Instead,
1758 every society has left a certain bit of its culture free for the taking
—free
1759 societies more fully than unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree.
1760 <!-- PAGE BREAK 43 -->
1762 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt3' class='endofrange'
/>
1764 The hard question is therefore not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis> a
1765 culture is free. All cultures are free to some degree. The hard
1766 question instead is
<quote><emphasis>How
</emphasis> free is this culture?
</quote>
1767 How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take and
1768 build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of
1769 the royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock
1770 Exchange? Or is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally,
1771 whether affiliated with the Met or not? To musicians generally,
1772 whether white or not? To filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with
1776 Free cultures are cultures that leave a great deal open for others to
1777 build upon; unfree, or permission, cultures leave much less. Ours was a
1778 free culture. It is becoming much less so.
1780 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturederivativeworksbasedon' class='endofrange'
/>
1782 <!-- PAGE BREAK 44 -->
1784 <chapter label=
"2" id=
"mere-copyists">
1785 <title><quote>Mere Copyists
</quote></title>
1786 <indexterm><primary>Daguerre, Louis
</primary></indexterm>
1787 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
1788 <indexterm id='idxphotography' class='startofrange'
><primary>photography
</primary></indexterm>
1790 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1839</emphasis>, Louis Daguerre invented
1791 the first practical technology for producing what we would call
1792 <quote>photographs.
</quote> Appropriately enough, they were called
1793 <quote>daguerreotypes.
</quote> The process was complicated and
1794 expensive, and the field was thus limited to professionals and a few
1795 zealous and wealthy amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre
1796 Association that helped regulate the industry, as do all such
1797 associations, by keeping competition down so as to keep prices up.)
1799 <indexterm><primary>Talbot, William
</primary></indexterm>
1801 Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong.
1802 This pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make
1803 <quote>automatic pictures.
</quote> William Talbot soon discovered a process for
1804 making
<quote>negatives.
</quote> But because the negatives were glass, and had to
1805 be kept wet, the process still remained expensive and cumbersome. In
1806 the
1870s, dry plates were developed, making it easier to separate the
1807 taking of a picture from its developing. These were still plates of
1808 glass, and thus it was still not a process within reach of most
1811 <indexterm id='idxeastmangeorge' class='startofrange'
><primary>Eastman, George
</primary></indexterm>
1813 The technological change that made mass photography possible
1814 didn't happen until
1888, and was the creation of a single man. George
1815 <!-- PAGE BREAK 45 -->
1816 Eastman, himself an amateur photographer, was frustrated by the
1817 technology of photographs made with plates. In a flash of insight (so
1818 to speak), Eastman saw that if the film could be made to be flexible,
1819 it could be held on a single spindle. That roll could then be sent to
1820 a developer, driving the costs of photography down substantially. By
1821 lowering the costs, Eastman expected he could dramatically broaden the
1822 population of photographers.
1824 <indexterm id='idxkodakcameras' class='startofrange'
><primary>Kodak cameras
</primary></indexterm>
1825 <indexterm id='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='startofrange'
><primary>Kodak Primer, The (Eastman)
</primary></indexterm>
1827 Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed
1828 rolls of it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was
1829 marketed on the basis of its simplicity.
<quote>You press the button and we
1830 do the rest.
</quote><footnote><para>
1832 Reese V. Jenkins,
<citetitle>Images and Enterprise
</citetitle> (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1975),
112.
1833 </para></footnote> As he described in
<citetitle>The Kodak Primer
</citetitle>:
1837 The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that
1838 any person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work
1839 that only an expert can do.
… We furnish anybody, man, woman or
1840 child, who has sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and
1841 press a button, with an instrument which altogether removes from the
1842 practice of photography the necessity for exceptional facilities or,
1843 in fact, any special knowledge of the art. It can be employed without
1844 preliminary study, without a darkroom and without
1845 chemicals.
<footnote>
1848 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian
</primary></indexterm>
1849 Brian Coe,
<citetitle>The Birth of Photography
</citetitle> (New York: Taplinger Publishing,
1854 <indexterm startref='idxkodakprimertheeastman' class='endofrange'
/>
1856 For $
25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded
1857 with film, and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an
1858 Eastman factory, where the film was developed. Over time, of course,
1859 the cost of the camera and the ease with which it could be used both
1860 improved. Roll film thus became the basis for the explosive growth of
1861 popular photography. Eastman's camera first went on sale in
1888; one
1862 year later, Kodak was printing more than six thousand negatives a day.
1863 From
1888 through
1909, while industrial production was rising by
4.7
1864 percent, photographic equipment and material sales increased by
11
1865 percent.
<footnote><para>
1868 </para></footnote> Eastman Kodak's sales during the same period experienced
1869 an average annual increase of over
17 percent.
<footnote><para>
1871 Based on a chart in Jenkins, p.
178.
1874 <indexterm><primary>Coe, Brian
</primary></indexterm>
1877 <!-- PAGE BREAK 46 -->
1878 The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not
1879 economic. It was social. Professional photography gave individuals a
1880 glimpse of places they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography
1881 gave them the ability to record their own lives in a way they had
1882 never been able to do before. As author Brian Coe notes,
<quote>For the
1883 first time the snapshot album provided the man on the street with a
1884 permanent record of his family and its activities.
… For the first
1885 time in history there exists an authentic visual record of the
1886 appearance and activities of the common man made without [literary]
1887 interpretation or bias.
</quote><footnote><para>
1892 <indexterm><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
1893 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
1895 In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of
1896 expression. The pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of
1897 expression, of course. But it took years of training before they could
1898 be deployed by amateurs in any useful or effective way. With the
1899 Kodak, expression was possible much sooner and more simply. The
1900 barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at its
<quote>quality
</quote>;
1901 professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a child study
1902 how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the experience of
1903 creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave ordinary
1904 people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could
1907 <indexterm startref='idxkodakcameras' class='endofrange'
/>
1908 <indexterm id='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='startofrange'
><primary>permissions
</primary><secondary>photography exempted from
</secondary></indexterm>
1910 What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously,
1911 Eastman's genius was an important part. But also important was the
1912 legal environment within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in
1913 the history of photography, there was a series of judicial decisions
1914 that could well have changed the course of photography substantially.
1915 Courts were asked whether the photographer, amateur or professional,
1916 required permission before he could capture and print whatever image
1917 he wanted. Their answer was no.
<footnote><para>
1919 For illustrative cases, see, for example,
<citetitle>Pavesich
</citetitle>
1920 v.
<citetitle>N.E. Life Ins. Co
</citetitle>.,
50 S.E.
68 (Ga.
1905);
1921 <citetitle>Foster-Milburn Co
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Chinn
</citetitle>,
123090 S.W.
364,
366
1922 (Ky.
1909);
<citetitle>Corliss
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Walker
</citetitle>,
64 F.
280 (Mass.
1926 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology' class='endofrange'
/>
1927 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt4' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
1928 <indexterm id='idximagesownershipof' class='startofrange'
><primary>images, ownership of
</primary></indexterm>
1930 The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly
1931 familiar. The photographer was
<quote>taking
</quote> something from the person or
1932 building whose photograph he shot
—pirating something of
1933 value. Some even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as
1934 Disney was not free to take the pencils that his animators used to
1936 <!-- PAGE BREAK 47 -->
1937 Mickey, so, too, should these photographers not be free to take images
1938 that they thought valuable.
1940 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
1941 <indexterm><primary>Steamboat Bill, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
1942 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology2' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
1944 On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well.
1945 Sure, there may be something of value being used. But citizens should
1946 have the right to capture at least those images that stand in public view.
1947 (Louis Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought
1948 the rule should be different for images from private spaces.
<footnote>
1951 Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis,
<quote>The Right to Privacy,
</quote>
1952 <citetitle>Harvard Law Review
</citetitle> 4 (
1890):
193.
1953 <indexterm><primary>Brandeis, Louis D.
</primary></indexterm>
1954 <indexterm><primary>Warren, Samuel D.
</primary></indexterm>
1955 </para></footnote>) It may be that this means that the photographer
1956 gets something for nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from
1957 <citetitle>Steamboat Bill, Jr
</citetitle>. or the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be
1958 free to capture an image without compensating the source.
1960 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt4' class='endofrange'
/>
1962 Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these
1963 early decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no
1964 permission would be required before an image could be captured and
1965 shared with others. Instead, permission was presumed. Freedom was the
1966 default. (The law would eventually craft an exception for famous
1967 people: commercial photographers who snap pictures of famous people
1968 for commercial purposes have more restrictions than the rest of
1969 us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured without
1970 clearing the rights to do the capturing.
<footnote><para>
1972 See Melville B. Nimmer,
<quote>The Right of Publicity,
</quote> <citetitle>Law and Contemporary
1973 Problems
</citetitle> 19 (
1954):
203; William L. Prosser,
<quote>Privacy,
</quote> <citetitle>California Law
1974 Review
</citetitle> 48 (
1960)
398–407;
<citetitle>White
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Samsung Electronics America,
1975 Inc
</citetitle>.,
971 F.
2d
1395 (
9th Cir.
1992), cert. denied,
508 U.S.
951
1979 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras
</primary></indexterm>
1980 <indexterm><primary>Napster
</primary></indexterm>
1982 We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had
1983 the law gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the
1984 photographer, then the photographer would have had to demonstrate
1985 permission. Perhaps Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate
1986 permission, too, before it developed the film upon which images were
1987 captured. After all, if permission were not granted, then Eastman
1988 Kodak would be benefiting from the
<quote>theft
</quote> committed by the
1989 photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright
1990 infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting
1991 from the
<quote>image-right
</quote> infringement of its photographers. We could
1992 imagine the law then requiring that some form of permission be
1993 demonstrated before a company developed pictures. We could imagine a
1994 system developing to demonstrate that permission.
1996 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology2' class='endofrange'
/>
1997 <indexterm id='idxcameratechnology3' class='startofrange'
><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
1998 <indexterm><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
1999 <indexterm><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
2002 <!-- PAGE BREAK 48 -->
2003 But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be
2004 very hard to see how photography could have flourished as it did if
2005 the requirement for permission had been built into the rules that
2006 govern it. Photography would have existed. It would have grown in
2007 importance over time. Professionals would have continued to use the
2008 technology as they did
—since professionals could have more
2009 easily borne the burdens of the permission system. But the spread of
2010 photography to ordinary people would not have occurred. Nothing like
2011 that growth would have been realized. And certainly, nothing like that
2012 growth in a democratic technology of expression would have been
2015 <indexterm startref='idxphotography' class='endofrange'
/>
2016 <indexterm startref='idxeastmangeorge' class='endofrange'
/>
2017 <indexterm startref='idxpermissionsphotographyexemptedfrom' class='endofrange'
/>
2018 <indexterm startref='idximagesownershipof' class='endofrange'
/>
2019 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras
</primary></indexterm>
2020 <indexterm id='idxjustthink' class='startofrange'
><primary>Just Think!
</primary></indexterm>
2022 <emphasis role='strong'
>If you drive
</emphasis> through San
2023 Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses
2024 painted over with colorful and striking images, and the logo
2025 <quote>Just Think!
</quote> in place of the name of a school. But
2026 there's little that's
<quote>just
</quote> cerebral in the projects
2027 that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies
2028 that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even
2029 the film of your VCR. Rather the
<quote>film
</quote> of digital
2030 cameras. Just Think! is a project that enables kids to make films, as
2031 a way to understand and critique the filmed culture that they find all
2032 around them. Each year, these busses travel to more than thirty
2033 schools and enable three hundred to five hundred children to learn
2034 something about media by doing something with media. By doing, they
2035 think. By tinkering, they learn.
2037 <indexterm id='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'
><primary>education
</primary><secondary>in media literacy
</secondary></indexterm>
2038 <indexterm id='idxmedialiteracy' class='startofrange'
><primary>media literacy
</primary></indexterm>
2039 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='startofrange'
><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>media literacy and
</secondary></indexterm>
2041 These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is
2042 increasingly so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has
2043 fallen dramatically. As one analyst puts it,
<quote>Five years ago, a good
2044 real-time digital video editing system cost $
25,
000. Today you can get
2045 professional quality for $
595.
</quote><footnote><para>
2047 H. Edward Goldberg,
<quote>Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and
2048 Software You Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations,
</quote>
2049 cadalyst, February
2002, available at
2050 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
7</ulink>.
2052 These buses are filled with technology that would have cost hundreds
2053 of thousands just ten years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not
2054 just buses like this, but classrooms across the country where kids are
2055 learning more and more of something teachers call
<quote>media literacy.
</quote>
2057 <indexterm><primary>Yanofsky, Dave
</primary></indexterm>
2059 <!-- PAGE BREAK 49 -->
2060 <quote>Media literacy,
</quote> as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just
2061 Think!, puts it,
<quote>is the ability
… to understand, analyze, and
2062 deconstruct media images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the
2063 way media works, the way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and
2064 the way people access it.
</quote>
2066 <indexterm startref='idxjustthink' class='endofrange'
/>
2068 This may seem like an odd way to think about
<quote>literacy.
</quote> For most
2069 people, literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway
2070 and noticing split infinitives are the things that
<quote>literate
</quote> people know
2073 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
2074 <indexterm><primary>commercials
</primary></indexterm>
2075 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>advertising on
</secondary></indexterm>
2077 Maybe. But in a world where children see on average
390 hours of
2078 television commercials per year, or between
20,
000 and
45,
000
2079 commercials generally,
<footnote><para>
2081 Judith Van Evra,
<citetitle>Television and Child Development
</citetitle> (Hillsdale, N.J.:
2082 Lawrence Erlbaum Associates,
1990);
<quote>Findings on Family and TV
2083 Study,
</quote> <citetitle>Denver Post
</citetitle>,
25 May
1997, B6.
2085 it is increasingly important to understand the
<quote>grammar
</quote> of media. For
2086 just as there is a grammar for the written word, so, too, is there one
2087 for media. And just as kids learn how to write by writing lots of
2088 terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by constructing lots of
2089 (at least at first) terrible media.
2092 A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy
2093 as crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who
2094 has written understands how difficult writing is
—how difficult
2095 it is to sequence the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft
2096 language to be understandable
—few of us have any real sense of
2097 how difficult media is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense
2098 of how media works, how it holds an audience or leads it through a
2099 story, how it triggers emotion or builds suspense.
2101 <indexterm startref='idxcameratechnology3' class='endofrange'
/>
2103 It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well.
2104 But even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about
2105 the film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not
2106 from reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then
2107 reflecting upon what one has written. One learns to write with images
2108 by making them and then reflecting upon what one has created.
2110 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='startofrange'
><primary>Daley, Elizabeth
</primary></indexterm>
2111 <indexterm><primary>Crichton, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
2113 This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film,
2114 as Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern
2115 California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the
2117 <!-- PAGE BREAK 50 -->
2118 USC School of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was
2119 about
<quote>the placement of objects, color,
… rhythm, pacing, and
2120 texture.
</quote><footnote>
2123 Interview with Elizabeth Daley and Stephanie Barish,
13 December
2125 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2126 <indexterm><primary>Daley, Elizabeth
</primary></indexterm>
2128 But as computers open up an interactive space where a story is
2129 <quote>played
</quote> as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple
2130 control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author
2131 Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction.
2132 But when he tried to design a computer game based on one of his
2133 works, it was a new craft he had to learn. How to lead people through
2134 a game without their feeling they have been led was not obvious, even
2135 to a wildly successful author.
<footnote><para>
2137 See Scott Steinberg,
<quote>Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs,
</quote> E!online,
4
2138 November
2000, available at
2139 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
8</ulink>;
<quote>Timeline,
</quote> 22 November
2000,
2141 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
9</ulink>.
2144 <indexterm><primary>computer games
</primary></indexterm>
2146 This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley
2147 describes,
<quote>people are very surprised about how they are led through a
2148 film. [I]t is perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you
2149 have no idea. If a filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were
2150 led.
</quote> If you know you were led through a film, the film has failed.
2153 Yet the push for an expanded literacy
—one that goes beyond text
2154 to include audio and visual elements
—is not about making better
2155 film directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of
2156 filmmaking at all. Instead, as Daley explained,
2160 From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide
2161 is not access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the
2162 language that that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people
2163 can write with this language, and all the rest of us are reduced to
2168 <quote>Read-only.
</quote> Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere.
2169 Couch potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the
2173 The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial
2174 point: It could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better
2175 understanding the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding
2176 the tools that enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any
2178 <!-- PAGE BREAK 51 -->
2179 and this literacy in particular, is to
<quote>empower people to choose the
2180 appropriate language for what they need to create or
2181 express.
</quote><footnote>
2184 Interview with Daley and Barish.
2185 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2186 </para></footnote> It is to enable students
<quote>to communicate in the
2187 language of the twenty-first century.
</quote><footnote><para>
2192 <indexterm id='idxbarishstephanie' class='startofrange'
><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2194 As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to
2195 others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in
2196 written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the
2197 Institute for Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe
2198 one particularly poignant example of a project they ran in a high
2199 school. The high school was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles
2200 school. In all the traditional measures of success, this school was a
2201 failure. But Daley and Barish ran a program that gave kids an
2202 opportunity to use film to express meaning about something the
2203 students know something about
—gun violence.
2205 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth' class='endofrange'
/>
2207 The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively
2208 new problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was
2209 getting the kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them
2210 away. The
<quote>kids were showing up at
6 A.M. and leaving at
5 at night,
</quote>
2211 said Barish. They were working harder than in any other class to do
2212 what education should be about
—learning how to express themselves.
2215 Using whatever
<quote>free web stuff they could find,
</quote> and relatively simple
2216 tools to enable the kids to mix
<quote>image, sound, and text,
</quote> Barish said
2217 this class produced a series of projects that showed something about
2218 gun violence that few would otherwise understand. This was an issue
2219 close to the lives of these students. The project
<quote>gave them a tool
2220 and empowered them to be able to both understand it and talk about
2221 it,
</quote> Barish explained. That tool succeeded in creating
2222 expression
—far more successfully and powerfully than could have
2223 been created using only text.
<quote>If you had said to these students, `you
2224 have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands up and
2225 gone and done something else,
</quote> Barish described, in part, no doubt,
2226 because expressing themselves in text is not something these students
2227 can do well. Yet neither is text a form in which
2228 <emphasis>these
</emphasis> ideas can be expressed well. The power of
2229 this message depended upon its connection to this form of expression.
2231 <indexterm startref='idxbarishstephanie' class='endofrange'
/>
2232 <indexterm id='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Daley, Elizabeth
</primary></indexterm>
2235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 52 -->
2236 <quote>But isn't education about teaching kids to write?
</quote> I asked. In part,
2237 of course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education,
2238 Daley explained, is about giving students a way of
<quote>constructing
2239 meaning.
</quote> To say that that means just writing is like saying teaching
2240 writing is only about teaching kids how to spell. Text is one
2241 part
—and increasingly, not the most powerful part
—of
2242 constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the most moving part of
2247 What you want is to give these students ways of constructing
2248 meaning. If all you give them is text, they're not going to do it.
2249 Because they can't. You know, you've got Johnny who can look at a
2250 video, he can play a video game, he can do graffiti all over your
2251 walls, he can take your car apart, and he can do all sorts of other
2252 things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny comes to school and
2253 you say,
<quote>Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do matters.
</quote>
2254 Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can]
2255 dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss
2256 you. [But i]nstead, if you say,
<quote>Well, with all these things that you
2257 can do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think
2258 reflects that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw
2259 for me something that reflects that.
</quote> Not by giving a kid a video
2260 camera and
… saying,
<quote>Let's go have fun with the video camera and
2261 make a little movie.
</quote> But instead, really help you take these elements
2262 that you understand, that are your language, and construct meaning
2263 about the topic.
…
2265 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2267 That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of
2268 course, is eventually, as it has happened in all these classes, they
2269 bump up against the fact,
<quote>I need to explain this and I really need
2270 to write something.
</quote> And as one of the teachers told Stephanie,
2271 they would rewrite a paragraph
5,
6,
7,
8 times, till they got it right.
2274 Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They
2275 needed to say something, as opposed to just jumping through
2276 your hoops. They actually needed to use a language that they
2277 <!-- PAGE BREAK 53 -->
2278 didn't speak very well. But they had come to understand that they
2279 had a lot of power with this language.
2281 <!-- FIXME removed a " from the end of the previous paragraph that did
2282 not match with any start quote. -->
2284 <indexterm startref='idxeducationinmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'
/>
2285 <indexterm startref='idxmedialiteracy' class='endofrange'
/>
2286 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofmedialiteracyand' class='endofrange'
/>
2287 <indexterm startref='idxdaleyelizabeth2' class='endofrange'
/>
2288 <indexterm id='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='startofrange'
><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
2289 <indexterm><primary>World Trade Center
</primary></indexterm>
2290 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage' class='startofrange'
><primary>news coverage
</primary></indexterm>
2292 <emphasis role='strong'
>When two planes
</emphasis> crashed into the
2293 World Trade Center, another into the Pentagon, and a fourth into a
2294 Pennsylvania field, all media around the world shifted to this
2295 news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, and for
2296 weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold the
2297 story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a
2298 retelling, because we had seen the events that were described. The
2299 genius of this awful act of terrorism was that the delayed second
2300 attack was perfectly timed to assure that the whole world would be
2304 These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music
2305 scored for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across
2306 the screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was
<quote>balance,
</quote>
2307 and seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have
2308 increasingly come to expect it,
<quote>news as entertainment,
</quote> even if the
2309 entertainment is tragedy.
2311 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
2312 <indexterm><primary>CBS
</primary></indexterm>
2314 But in addition to this produced news about the
<quote>tragedy of September
2315 11,
</quote> those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different
2316 production as well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same
2317 events. Yet these Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some
2318 people constructed photo pages that captured images from around the
2319 world and presented them as slide shows with text. Some offered open
2320 letters. There were sound recordings. There was anger and frustration.
2321 There were attempts to provide context. There was, in short, an
2322 extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in the sense Mike Godwin uses
2323 the term in his book
<citetitle>Cyber Rights
</citetitle>, around a news event that had
2324 captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, but there
2325 was also the Internet.
2327 <indexterm startref='idxseptemberterroristattacksof' class='endofrange'
/>
2329 I don't mean simply to praise the Internet
—though I do think the
2330 people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean
2331 instead to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a
2332 Kodak, the Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a
2334 <!-- PAGE BREAK 54 -->
2335 by a student on the
<quote>Just Think!
</quote> bus, the visual images could be mixed
2339 But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet
2340 allows these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of
2341 people, practically instantaneously. This is something new in our
2342 tradition
—not just that culture can be captured mechanically,
2343 and obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but
2344 that this mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely
2345 spread practically instantaneously.
2347 <indexterm><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
2348 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs' class='startofrange'
><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2349 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>blogs on
</secondary></indexterm>
2350 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs' class='startofrange'
><primary>Web-logs (blogs)
</primary></indexterm>
2352 September
11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the
2353 same time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was
2354 just beginning to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or
2355 blog. The blog is a kind of public diary, and within some cultures,
2356 such as in Japan, it functions very much like a diary. In those
2357 cultures, it records private facts in a public way
—it's a kind
2358 of electronic
<citetitle>Jerry Springer
</citetitle>, available anywhere in the world.
2360 <indexterm><primary>political discourse
</primary></indexterm>
2361 <indexterm id='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>public discourse conducted on
</secondary></indexterm>
2363 But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different
2364 character. There are some who use the space simply to talk about
2365 their private life. But there are many who use the space to engage in
2366 public discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing
2367 others who are mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about
2368 the decisions they make, offering solutions to problems we all see:
2369 blogs create the sense of a virtual public meeting, but one in which
2370 we don't all hope to be there at the same time and in which
2371 conversations are not necessarily linked. The best of the blog entries
2372 are relatively short; they point directly to words used by others,
2373 criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the most
2374 important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have.
2376 <indexterm id='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='startofrange'
><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>in technologies of expression
</secondary></indexterm>
2377 <indexterm id='idxelections' class='startofrange'
><primary>elections
</primary></indexterm>
2378 <indexterm id='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='startofrange'
><primary>expression, technologies of
</primary><secondary>democratic
</secondary></indexterm>
2380 That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as
2381 it does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most
2382 difficult for those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy
2383 has atrophied. Of course we have elections, and most of the time the
2384 courts allow those elections to count. A relatively small number of
2386 <!-- PAGE BREAK 55 -->
2387 in those elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally
2388 professionalized and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy.
2390 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs' class='endofrange'
/>
2391 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson' class='endofrange'
/>
2392 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs' class='endofrange'
/>
2393 <indexterm><primary>Tocqueville, Alexis de
</primary></indexterm>
2394 <indexterm id='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='startofrange'
><primary>democracy
</primary><secondary>public discourse in
</secondary></indexterm>
2395 <indexterm><primary>jury system
</primary></indexterm>
2397 But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy
2398 means rule by the people, but rule means something more than mere
2399 elections. In our tradition, it also means control through reasoned
2400 discourse. This was the idea that captured the imagination of Alexis
2401 de Tocqueville, the nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the
2402 most important account of early
<quote>Democracy in America.
</quote> It wasn't
2403 popular elections that fascinated him
—it was the jury, an
2404 institution that gave ordinary people the right to choose life or
2405 death for other citizens. And most fascinating for him was that the
2406 jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would impose. They
2407 deliberated. Members argued about the
<quote>right
</quote> result; they tried to
2408 persuade each other of the
<quote>right
</quote> result, and in criminal cases at
2409 least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to
2410 come to an end.
<footnote><para>
2412 See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville,
<citetitle>Democracy in America
</citetitle>,
2413 bk.
1, trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books,
2000), ch.
16.
2416 <indexterm startref='idxelections' class='endofrange'
/>
2418 Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its
2419 place, there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some
2420 are pushing to create just such an institution.
<footnote><para>
2422 Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin,
<quote>Deliberation Day,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of
2423 Political Philosophy
</citetitle> 10 (
2) (
2002):
129.
2425 And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation
2426 remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or
2427 place for
<quote>democratic deliberation
</quote> to occur.
2429 <indexterm id='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='startofrange'
><primary>political discourse
</primary></indexterm>
2431 More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to
2432 occur. We, the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a
2433 strong norm against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about
2434 politics with people you agree with. But it is rude to argue about
2435 politics with people you disagree with. Political discourse becomes
2436 isolated, and isolated discourse becomes more extreme.
<footnote><para>
2438 Cass Sunstein,
<citetitle>Republic.com
</citetitle> (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
2001),
2439 65–80,
175,
182,
183,
192.
2440 </para></footnote> We say what our friends want to hear, and hear very
2441 little beyond what our friends say.
2443 <indexterm id='idxblogsweblogs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2444 <indexterm><primary>e-mail
</primary></indexterm>
2445 <indexterm id='idxinternetblogson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>blogs on
</secondary></indexterm>
2446 <indexterm id='idxweblogsblogs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Web-logs (blogs)
</primary></indexterm>
2447 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracyintechnologiesofexpression' class='endofrange'
/>
2448 <indexterm startref='idxexpressiontechnologiesofdemocratic' class='endofrange'
/>
2449 <indexterm startref='idxdemocracypublicdiscoursein' class='endofrange'
/>
2451 Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this
2452 problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they
2453 want to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time.
2454 Technologies that enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail,
2455 increase the opportunity for communication. Blogs allow for public
2457 <!-- PAGE BREAK 56 -->
2458 discourse without the public ever needing to gather in a single public
2462 But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of
2463 norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics.
2464 Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and
2465 the left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian,
2466 but there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not
2467 political cover political issues when the occasion merits.
2469 <indexterm><primary>Dean, Howard
</primary></indexterm>
2471 The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The
2472 name Howard Dean may well have faded from the
2004 presidential race
2473 but for blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading
2474 is having an effect.
2476 <indexterm><primary>Lott, Trent
</primary></indexterm>
2477 <indexterm><primary>Thurmond, Strom
</primary></indexterm>
2478 <indexterm id='idxmediablogpressureon' class='startofrange'
><primary>media
</primary><secondary>blog pressure on
</secondary></indexterm>
2479 <indexterm id='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>news events on
</secondary></indexterm>
2481 One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the
2482 mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott
2483 <quote>misspoke
</quote> at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising
2484 Thurmond's segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this
2485 story would disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight
2486 hours. It did. But he didn't calculate its life cycle in blog
2487 space. The bloggers kept researching the story. Over time, more and
2488 more instances of the same
<quote>misspeaking
</quote> emerged. Finally, the story
2489 broke back into the mainstream press. In the end, Lott was forced to
2490 resign as senate majority leader.
<footnote><para>
2492 Noah Shachtman,
<quote>With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot,
</quote> New
2493 York Times,
16 January
2003, G5.
2496 <indexterm id='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>media
</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of
</secondary></indexterm>
2498 This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures
2499 don't exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and
2500 newspapers are commercial entities. They must work to keep attention.
2501 If they lose readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move
2504 <indexterm startref='idxmediablogpressureon' class='endofrange'
/>
2505 <indexterm><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>peer-generated rankings on
</secondary></indexterm>
2507 But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they
2508 can focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a
2509 particularly interesting story, more and more people link to that
2510 story. And as the number of links to a particular story increases, it
2511 rises in the ranks of stories. People read what is popular; what is
2512 popular has been selected by a very democratic process of
2513 peer-generated rankings.
2515 <indexterm startref='idxmediacommercialimperativesof' class='endofrange'
/>
2516 <indexterm id='idxjournalism' class='startofrange'
><primary>journalism
</primary></indexterm>
2517 <indexterm id='idxwinerdave' class='startofrange'
><primary>Winer, Dave
</primary></indexterm>
2519 There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle
2520 <!-- PAGE BREAK 57 -->
2521 from the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this
2522 movement and a software author for many decades, told me, another
2523 difference is the absence of a financial
<quote>conflict of interest.
</quote> <quote>I think you
2524 have to take the conflict of interest
</quote> out of journalism, Winer told me.
2525 <quote>An amateur journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the
2526 conflict of interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of
2527 get it out of the way.
</quote>
2529 <indexterm><primary>CNN
</primary></indexterm>
2530 <indexterm><primary>media
</primary><secondary>commercial imperatives of
</secondary></indexterm>
2531 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
2532 <indexterm><primary>media
</primary><secondary>ownership concentration in
</secondary></indexterm>
2534 These conflicts become more important as media becomes more
2535 concentrated (more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more
2536 from the public than an unconcentrated media can
—as CNN admitted
2537 it did after the Iraq war because it was afraid of the consequences to
2538 its own employees.
<footnote><para>
2540 Telephone interview with David Winer,
16 April
2003.
2542 It also needs to sustain a more coherent account. (In the middle of
2543 the Iraq war, I read a post on the Internet from someone who was at
2544 that time listening to a satellite uplink with a reporter in Iraq. The
2545 New York headquarters was telling the reporter over and over that her
2546 account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer a more
2547 optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they
2548 told her that
<emphasis>they
</emphasis> were writing
<quote>the story.
</quote>)
2550 <indexterm startref='idxinternetnewseventson2' class='endofrange'
/>
2552 Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the
2553 debate
—<quote>amateur
</quote> not in the sense of inexperienced,
2554 but in the sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning not paid by anyone to
2555 give their reports. It allows for a much broader range of input into a
2556 story, as reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when hundreds
2557 from across the southwest United States turned to the Internet to
2558 retell what they had seen.
<footnote><para>
2560 John Schwartz,
<quote>Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of
2561 Information Online,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
2 February
2003, A28; Staci
2562 D. Kramer,
<quote>Shuttle Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall,
</quote>
2563 Online Journalism Review,
2 February
2003, available at
2564 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
10</ulink>.
2566 And it drives readers to read across the range of accounts and
2567 <quote>triangulate,
</quote> as Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are
2568 <quote>communicating directly with our constituency, and the middle man is
2569 out of it
</quote>—with all the benefits, and costs, that might entail.
2572 Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected
2573 with blogs.
<quote>It's going to become an essential skill,
</quote> Winer predicts,
2574 for public figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's
2575 not clear that
<quote>journalism
</quote> is happy about this
—some journalists
2576 have been told to curtail their blogging.
<footnote>
2579 <indexterm><primary>CNN
</primary></indexterm>
2580 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
2581 <indexterm><primary>Olafson, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
2582 <indexterm><primary>blogs (Web-logs)
</primary></indexterm>
2583 See Michael Falcone,
<quote>Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?
</quote> <citetitle>New
2584 York Times
</citetitle>,
29 September
2003, C4. (
<quote>Not all news organizations have
2585 been as accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN
2586 correspondent in Iraq who started a blog about his reporting of the
2587 war on March
9, stopped posting
12 days later at his bosses'
2588 request. Last year Steve Olafson, a
<citetitle>Houston Chronicle
</citetitle> reporter, was
2589 fired for keeping a personal Web log, published under a pseudonym,
2590 that dealt with some of the issues and people he was covering.
</quote>)
2592 But it is clear that we are still in transition.
<quote>A
2594 <!-- PAGE BREAK 58 -->
2595 lot of what we are doing now is warm-up exercises,
</quote> Winer told me.
2596 There is a lot that must mature before this space has its mature effect.
2597 And as the inclusion of content in this space is the least infringing use
2598 of the Internet (meaning infringing on copyright), Winer said,
<quote>we will
2599 be the last thing that gets shut down.
</quote>
2601 <indexterm startref='idxjournalism' class='endofrange'
/>
2603 This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because
<quote>you
2604 don't have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper.
</quote>
2605 That is true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As
2606 more and more citizens express what they think, and defend it in
2607 writing, that will change the way people understand public issues. It
2608 is easy to be wrong and misguided in your head. It is harder when the
2609 product of your mind can be criticized by others. Of course, it is a
2610 rare human who admits that he has been persuaded that he is wrong. But
2611 it is even rarer for a human to ignore when he has been proven wrong.
2612 The writing of ideas, arguments, and criticism improves democracy.
2613 Today there are probably a couple of million blogs where such writing
2614 happens. When there are ten million, there will be something
2615 extraordinary to report.
2617 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage' class='endofrange'
/>
2618 <indexterm startref='idxinternetpublicdiscourseconductedon' class='endofrange'
/>
2619 <indexterm startref='idxpoliticaldiscourse' class='endofrange'
/>
2620 <indexterm startref='idxblogsweblogs2' class='endofrange'
/>
2621 <indexterm startref='idxinternetblogson2' class='endofrange'
/>
2622 <indexterm startref='idxweblogsblogs2' class='endofrange'
/>
2623 <indexterm startref='idxwinerdave' class='endofrange'
/>
2624 <indexterm id='idxbrownjohnseely' class='startofrange'
><primary>Brown, John Seely
</primary></indexterm>
2625 <indexterm id='idxadvertising1' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
2627 <emphasis role='strong'
>John Seely Brown
</emphasis> is the chief
2628 scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, as his Web site
2629 describes it, is
<quote>human learning and
… the creation of
2630 knowledge ecologies for creating
… innovation.
</quote>
2633 Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit
2634 differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he
2635 would be excited about any technology that might improve
2636 democracy. But his real excitement comes from how these technologies
2640 As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When
<quote>a lot of us grew up,
</quote>
2641 he explains, that tinkering was done
<quote>on motorcycle engines, lawnmower
2642 engines, automobiles, radios, and so on.
</quote> But digital technologies
2643 enable a different kind of tinkering
—with abstract ideas though
2644 in concrete form. The kids at Just Think! not only think about how a
2645 commercial portrays a politician; using digital technology, they can
2646 <!-- PAGE BREAK 59 -->
2647 take the commercial apart and manipulate it, tinker with it to see how
2648 it does what it does. Digital technologies launch a kind of bricolage,
2649 or
<quote>free collage,
</quote> as Brown calls it. Many get to add to or transform
2650 the tinkering of many others.
2653 The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free
2654 software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose
2655 source code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a
2656 FS/OSS program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of
2657 FS/OSS technology works can tinker with the code.
2660 This opportunity creates a
<quote>completely new kind of learning platform,
</quote>
2661 as Brown describes.
<quote>As soon as you start doing that, you
…
2662 unleash a free collage on the community, so that other people can
2663 start looking at your code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing
2664 if they can improve it.
</quote> Each effort is a kind of
2665 apprenticeship.
<quote>Open source becomes a major apprenticeship platform.
</quote>
2668 In this process,
<quote>the concrete things you tinker with are abstract.
2669 They are code.
</quote> Kids are
<quote>shifting to the ability to tinker in the
2670 abstract, and this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that
2671 you're doing in your garage. You are tinkering with a community
2672 platform.
… You are tinkering with other people's stuff. The more
2673 you tinker the more you improve.
</quote> The more you improve, the more you
2677 This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same
2678 collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts
2679 it,
<quote>the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of
2680 intelligence.
</quote> Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word
2681 processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than
2682 text.
<quote>The Web
… says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if
2683 you are visual, if you are interested in film
… [then] there is a
2684 lot you can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor
2685 these multiple forms of intelligence.
</quote>
2687 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising1' class='endofrange'
/>
2688 <indexterm><primary>Barish, Stephanie
</primary></indexterm>
2690 Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and
2691 Just Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well
2693 <!-- PAGE BREAK 60 -->
2694 as creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different
2695 kind of recognition.
2698 Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed.
2699 Indeed, as we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is
2700 increasingly highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father
2701 had the right to tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that
2702 your child will have the right to tinker with the images she finds all
2703 around. The law and, increasingly, technology interfere with a
2704 freedom that technology, and curiosity, would otherwise ensure.
2707 These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars.
2708 Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter
2709 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>)
2710 has developed a powerful argument in favor of the
<quote>right to
2711 tinker
</quote> as it applies to computer science and to knowledge in
2712 general.
<footnote><para>
2714 See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel,
<quote>Technological Access
2715 Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship,
</quote> <citetitle>Communications
2716 of the Association for Computer Machinery
</citetitle> 43 (
2000):
9.
2718 But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more fundamental. It is
2719 about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because of the law.
2722 <quote>This is where education in the twenty-first century is going,
</quote> Brown
2723 explains. We need to
<quote>understand how kids who grow up digital think
2724 and want to learn.
</quote>
2727 <quote>Yet,
</quote> as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will
2728 evince,
<quote>we are building a legal system that completely suppresses the
2729 natural tendencies of today's digital kids.
… We're building an
2730 architecture that unleashes
60 percent of the brain [and] a legal
2731 system that closes down that part of the brain.
</quote>
2733 <indexterm startref='idxbrownjohnseely' class='endofrange'
/>
2735 We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes
2736 moving images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an
2737 opportunity to spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building
2738 the law to close down that technology.
2741 <quote>No way to run a culture,
</quote> as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in
2742 chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"collectors"/>,
2743 quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence.
2745 <!-- PAGE BREAK 61 -->
2747 <chapter label=
"3" id=
"catalogs">
2748 <title>Catalogs
</title>
2749 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse
</primary></indexterm>
2750 <indexterm><primary>RPI
</primary><see>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)
</see></indexterm>
2751 <indexterm id='idxrensselaer' class='startofrange'
><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)
</primary></indexterm>
2752 <indexterm id='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute (RPI)
</primary><secondary>computer network search engine of
</secondary></indexterm>
2753 <indexterm id='idxsearchengines' class='startofrange'
><primary>search engines
</primary></indexterm>
2754 <indexterm id='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='startofrange'
><primary>university computer networks, p2p sharing on
</primary></indexterm>
2755 <indexterm id='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>search engines used on
</secondary></indexterm>
2757 <emphasis role='strong'
>In the fall
</emphasis> of
2002, Jesse Jordan
2758 of Oceanside, New York, enrolled as a freshman at Rensselaer
2759 Polytechnic Institute, in Troy, New York. His major at RPI was
2760 information technology. Though he is not a programmer, in October
2761 Jesse decided to begin to tinker with search engine technology that
2762 was available on the RPI network.
2765 RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions.
2766 It offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering
2767 to information sciences. More than
65 percent of its five thousand
2768 undergraduates finished in the top
10 percent of their high school
2769 class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to
2770 imagine and then build, a generation for the network age.
2773 RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to
2774 one another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything
2775 available on the RPI network is available on the Internet. But the
2776 network is designed to enable students to get access to the Internet,
2777 as well as more intimate access to other members of the RPI community.
2779 <indexterm id='idxgoogle' class='startofrange'
><primary>Google
</primary></indexterm>
2781 Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google
2782 <!-- PAGE BREAK 62 -->
2783 brought the Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically
2784 improving the quality of search on the network. Specialty search
2785 engines can do this even better. The idea of
<quote>intranet
</quote> search
2786 engines, search engines that search within the network of a particular
2787 institution, is to provide users of that institution with better
2788 access to material from that institution. Businesses do this all the
2789 time, enabling employees to have access to material that people
2790 outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well.
2792 <indexterm id='idxjordanjesse' class='startofrange'
><primary>Jordan, Jesse
</primary></indexterm>
2793 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>network file system of
</secondary></indexterm>
2795 These engines are enabled by the network technology itself.
2796 Microsoft, for example, has a network file system that makes it very
2797 easy for search engines tuned to that network to query the system for
2798 information about the publicly (within that network) available
2799 content. Jesse's search engine was built to take advantage of this
2800 technology. It used Microsoft's network file system to build an index
2801 of all the files available within the RPI network.
2803 <indexterm startref='idxgoogle' class='endofrange'
/>
2805 Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network.
2806 Indeed, his engine was a simple modification of engines that others
2807 had built. His single most important improvement over those engines
2808 was to fix a bug within the Microsoft file-sharing system that could
2809 cause a user's computer to crash. With the engines that existed
2810 before, if you tried to access a file through a Windows browser that
2811 was on a computer that was off-line, your computer could crash. Jesse
2812 modified the system a bit to fix that problem, by adding a button that
2813 a user could click to see if the machine holding the file was still
2816 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftnetworkfilesystemof' class='endofrange'
/>
2818 Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six
2819 months, he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By
2820 March, the system was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one
2821 million files in his directory, including every type of content that might
2822 be on users' computers.
2824 <indexterm startref='idxinternetsearchenginesusedon' class='endofrange'
/>
2826 Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which
2827 students could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or
2828 research; copies of information pamphlets; movie clips that students
2829 might have created; university brochures
—basically anything that
2830 <!-- PAGE BREAK 63 -->
2831 users of the RPI network made available in a public folder of their
2834 <indexterm><primary>Google
</primary></indexterm>
2835 <indexterm><primary>education
</primary><secondary>tinkering as means of
</secondary></indexterm>
2837 But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the
2838 files that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that
2839 means, of course, that three quarters were not, and
—so that this
2840 point is absolutely clear
—Jesse did nothing to induce people to
2841 put music files in their public folders. He did nothing to target the
2842 search engine to these files. He was a kid tinkering with a
2843 Google-like technology at a university where he was studying
2844 information science, and hence, tinkering was the aim. Unlike Google,
2845 or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from this tinkering;
2846 he was not connected to any business that would make any money from
2847 this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an
2848 environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was
2851 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>in recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
2852 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>against student file sharing
</secondary></indexterm>
2853 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of
</secondary></indexterm>
2854 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by
</secondary></indexterm>
2855 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaerpolytechnicinstituterpicomputernetworksearchengineof' class='endofrange'
/>
2857 On April
3,
2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at
2858 RPI. The dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association
2859 of America, the RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three
2860 other students whom he didn't even know, two of them at other
2861 universities. A few hours later, Jesse was served with papers from
2862 the suit. As he read these papers and watched the news reports about
2863 them, he was increasingly astonished.
2866 <quote>It was absurd,
</quote> he told me.
<quote>I don't think I did anything
2867 wrong.
… I don't think there's anything wrong with the search
2868 engine that I ran or
… what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't
2869 modified it in any way that promoted or enhanced the work of
2870 pirates. I just modified the search engine in a way that would make it
2871 easier to use
</quote>—again, a
<emphasis>search engine
</emphasis>,
2872 which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing
2873 system, which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the
2874 RPI community to get access to content, which Jesse had not himself
2875 created or posted, and the vast majority of which had nothing to do
2878 <indexterm startref='idxsearchengines' class='endofrange'
/>
2879 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of
</secondary></indexterm>
2880 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>statutory damages of
</secondary></indexterm>
2881 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>individual defendants intimidated by
</secondary></indexterm>
2882 <indexterm><primary>statutory damages
</primary></indexterm>
2883 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>intimidation tactics of
</secondary></indexterm>
2885 But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a
2886 network and had therefore
<quote>willfully
</quote> violated copyright laws. They
2887 <!-- PAGE BREAK 64 -->
2888 demanded that he pay them the damages for his wrong. For cases of
2889 <quote>willful infringement,
</quote> the Copyright Act specifies something lawyers
2890 call
<quote>statutory damages.
</quote> These damages permit a copyright owner to
2891 claim $
150,
000 per infringement. As the RIAA alleged more than one
2892 hundred specific copyright infringements, they therefore demanded that
2893 Jesse pay them at least $
15,
000,
000.
2895 <indexterm><primary>Michigan Technical University
</primary></indexterm>
2896 <indexterm><primary>Princeton University
</primary></indexterm>
2898 Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other
2899 student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at
2900 Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case
2901 was different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same:
2902 huge demands for
<quote>damages
</quote> that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to.
2903 If you added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in
2904 the United States to award the plaintiffs close to $
100
2905 <emphasis>billion
</emphasis>—six times the
2906 <emphasis>total
</emphasis> profit of the film industry in
2907 2001.
<footnote><para>
2910 Tim Goral,
<quote>Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-
2-P Networks:
2911 Suit Alleges $
97.8 Billion in Damages,
</quote> <citetitle>Professional Media Group LCC
</citetitle> 6
2912 (
2003):
5, available at
2003 WL
55179443.
2915 <indexterm startref='idxrensselaer' class='endofrange'
/>
2917 Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened.
2918 An uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They
2919 demanded to know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved
2920 $
12,
000 from summer jobs and other employment. They demanded
2921 $
12,
000 to dismiss the case.
2923 <indexterm><primary>Oppenheimer, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
2925 The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He
2926 refused. They wanted him to agree to an injunction that would
2927 essentially make it impossible for him to work in many fields of
2928 technology for the rest of his life. He refused. They made him
2929 understand that this process of being sued was not going to be
2930 pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief lawyer on the
2931 case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse,
<quote>You don't want to pay another
2932 visit to a dentist like me.
</quote>) And throughout, the RIAA insisted it
2933 would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved.
2935 <indexterm><primary>legal system, attorney costs in
</primary></indexterm>
2937 Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight.
2938 But Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the
2939 American legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even
2940 win. But the cost of fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be
2941 at least $
250,
000. If he won, he would not recover that money. If he
2942 <!-- PAGE BREAK 65 -->
2943 won, he would have a piece of paper saying he had won, and a piece of
2944 paper saying he and his family were bankrupt.
2947 So Jesse faced a mafia-like choice: $
250,
000 and a chance at winning,
2948 or $
12,
000 and a settlement.
2950 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
2951 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
2952 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>lobbying power of
</secondary></indexterm>
2954 The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality.
2955 Let's put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality.
2956 Where is the morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in
2957 scapegoatism? The RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The
2958 president of the RIAA is reported to make more than $
1 million a year.
2959 Artists, on the other hand, are not well paid. The average recording
2960 artist makes $
45,
900.
<footnote><para>
2962 Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (
2001)
2963 (
27–2042—Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for
2964 the Arts,
<citetitle>More Than One in a Blue Moon
</citetitle> (
2000).
2966 There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect
2967 and direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a
2968 student for running a search engine?
<footnote><para>
2970 Douglas Lichtman makes a related point in
<quote>KaZaA and Punishment,
</quote>
2971 <citetitle>Wall Street Journal
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, A24.
2974 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsindividualdefendantsintimidatedby' class='endofrange'
/>
2975 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaintimidationtacticsof' class='endofrange'
/>
2977 On June
23, Jesse wired his savings to the lawyer working for the
2978 RIAA. The case against him was then dismissed. And with this, this
2979 kid who had tinkered a computer into a $
15 million lawsuit became an
2984 I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be
2985 an activist.
… [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I
2986 ever foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely
2987 absurd what the RIAA has done.
2991 Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As
2992 his father told me, Jesse
<quote>considers himself very conservative, and so do
2993 I.
… He's not a tree hugger.
… I think it's bizarre that they would
2994 pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the
2995 wrong message. And he wants to correct the record.
</quote>
2997 <indexterm startref='idxuniversitycomputernetworksppsharingon' class='endofrange'
/>
2998 <indexterm startref='idxjordanjesse' class='endofrange'
/>
2999 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'
/>
3000 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsagainststudentfilesharing' class='endofrange'
/>
3001 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrycopyrightinfringementlawsuitsof' class='endofrange'
/>
3002 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaacopyrightinfringementlawsuitsfiledby' class='endofrange'
/>
3003 <!-- PAGE BREAK 66 -->
3005 <chapter label=
"4" id=
"pirates">
3006 <title><quote>Pirates
</quote></title>
3007 <indexterm id='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>in development of content industry
</secondary></indexterm>
3008 <indexterm><primary><quote>if value, then right
</quote> theory
</primary></indexterm>
3010 <emphasis role='strong'
>If
<quote>piracy
</quote> means
</emphasis>
3011 using the creative property of others without their
3012 permission
—if
<quote>if value, then right
</quote> is
3013 true
—then the history of the content industry is a history of
3014 piracy. Every important sector of
<quote>big media
</quote>
3015 today
—film, records, radio, and cable TV
—was born of a
3016 kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last
3017 generation's pirates join this generation's country club
—until
3023 The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.
<footnote><para>
3025 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
3026 I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary
3027 history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
87–93,
3028 which details Edison's
<quote>adventures
</quote> with copyright and patent.
3030 Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast to California in
3031 the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that patents
3032 granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls were
3033 exercised through a monopoly
<quote>trust,
</quote> the Motion Pictures Patents
3034 Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative
3035 property
—patents. Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights
3036 this creative property
3037 <!-- PAGE BREAK 67 -->
3038 gave him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded.
3041 As one commentator tells one part of the story,
3045 A January
1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with
3046 the license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to
3047 themselves as independents protested the trust and carried on
3048 business without submitting to the Edison monopoly. In the
3049 summer of
1909 the independent movement was in full-swing,
3050 with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and
3051 imported film stock to create their own underground market.
3053 <indexterm><primary>Fox, William
</primary></indexterm>
3054 <indexterm><primary>General Film Company
</primary></indexterm>
3055 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
3057 With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of
3058 nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement
3059 by forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company
3060 to block the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics
3061 that have become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed
3062 equipment, discontinued product supply to theaters which showed
3063 unlicensed films, and effectively monopolized distribution with the
3064 acquisition of all U.S. film exchanges, except for the one owned by
3065 the independent William Fox who defied the Trust even after his
3066 license was revoked.
<footnote><para>
3068 J. A. Aberdeen,
<citetitle>Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion
3069 Picture Producers
</citetitle> (Cobblestone Entertainment,
2000) and expanded texts
3070 posted at
<quote>The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents
3071 Company vs. the Independent Outlaws,
</quote> available at
3072 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
11</ulink>. For a
3073 discussion of the economic motive behind both these limits and the
3074 limits imposed by Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker,
<quote>From
3075 Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and
3076 the Propertization of Copyright
</quote> (September
2002), University of
3077 Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in Law and Economics,
3078 Working Paper No.
159.
3079 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
3084 The Napsters of those days, the
<quote>independents,
</quote> were companies like
3085 Fox. And no less than today, these independents were vigorously
3086 resisted.
<quote>Shooting was disrupted by machinery stolen, and
3087 `accidents' resulting in loss of negatives, equipment, buildings and
3088 sometimes life and limb frequently occurred.
</quote><footnote><para>
3090 Marc Wanamaker,
<quote>The First Studios,
</quote> <citetitle>The Silents Majority
</citetitle>, archived at
3091 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
12</ulink>.
3093 That led the independents to flee the East
3094 Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that
3095 filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the
3096 law. And the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently,
3100 Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement
3101 of federal law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the
3102 patent holder a truly
<quote>limited
</quote> monopoly (just seventeen years at that
3104 <!-- PAGE BREAK 68 -->
3105 time), by the time enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had
3106 expired. A new industry had been born, in part from the piracy of
3107 Edison's creative property.
3110 <section id=
"recordedmusic">
3111 <title>Recorded Music
</title>
3112 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on music recordings
</secondary></indexterm>
3114 The record industry was born of another kind of piracy, though to see
3115 how requires a bit of detail about the way the law regulates music.
3117 <indexterm id='idxfourneauxhenri' class='startofrange'
><primary>Fourneaux, Henri
</primary></indexterm>
3118 <indexterm><primary>Russel, Phil
</primary></indexterm>
3120 At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines
3121 for reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player
3122 piano), the law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of
3123 their music and the exclusive right to control public performances of
3124 their music. In other words, in
1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's
3125 1899 hit
<quote>Happy Mose,
</quote> the law said I would have to pay for the right
3126 to get a copy of the musical score, and I would also have to pay for the
3127 right to perform it publicly.
3129 <indexterm><primary>Beatles
</primary></indexterm>
3131 But what if I wanted to record
<quote>Happy Mose,
</quote> using Edison's phonograph
3132 or Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear
3133 enough that I would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I
3134 performed in making this recording. And it was clear enough that I
3135 would have to pay for any public performance of the work I was
3136 recording. But it wasn't totally clear that I would have to pay for a
3137 <quote>public performance
</quote> if I recorded the song in my own house (even
3138 today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing their songs in
3139 the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in your
3140 brain are not
—yet
— regulated by copyright law). So if I
3141 simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own
3142 home, it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more
3143 importantly, it wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I
3144 then made copies of those recordings. Because of this gap in the law,
3145 then, I could effectively pirate someone else's song without paying
3146 its composer anything.
3148 <indexterm startref='idxfourneauxhenri' class='endofrange'
/>
3150 The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about
3151 <!-- PAGE BREAK 69 -->
3152 this capacity to pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge
3154 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred
</primary></indexterm>
3158 Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an
3159 opera. A publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and
3160 copyrights it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who
3161 cut music rolls and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the
3162 composer and publisher without any regard for [their]
3163 rights.
<footnote><para>
3165 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on
3166 S.
6330 and H.R.
19853 Before the (Joint) Committees on Patents,
59th
3167 Cong.
59,
1st sess. (
1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge,
3168 of South Dakota, chairman), reprinted in
<citetitle>Legislative History of the
3169 Copyright Act
</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South
3170 Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1976).
3171 <indexterm><primary>Kittredge, Alfred
</primary></indexterm>
3175 <indexterm><primary>Sousa, John Philip
</primary></indexterm>
3177 The innovators who developed the technology to record other
3178 people's works were
<quote>sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and
3179 genius of American composers,
</quote><footnote><para>
3181 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
223
3182 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3184 and the
<quote>music publishing industry
</quote>
3185 was thereby
<quote>at the complete mercy of this one pirate.
</quote><footnote><para>
3187 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
226
3188 (statement of Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association).
3191 Sousa put it, in as direct a way as possible,
<quote>When they make money
3192 out of my pieces, I want a share of it.
</quote><footnote><para>
3194 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
23
3195 (statement of John Philip Sousa, composer).
3198 <indexterm><primary>American Graphophone Company
</primary></indexterm>
3199 <indexterm><primary>player pianos
</primary></indexterm>
3200 <indexterm><primary>sheet music
</primary></indexterm>
3201 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
3202 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
3203 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in
</secondary></indexterm>
3204 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>statutory license system in
</secondary></indexterm>
3206 These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too,
3207 do the arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the
3208 player piano argued that
<quote>it is perfectly demonstrable that the
3209 introduction of automatic music players has not deprived any composer
3210 of anything he had before their introduction.
</quote> Rather, the machines
3211 increased the sales of sheet music.
<footnote><para>
3214 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
283–84
3215 (statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music
3216 Perforating Company of New York).
3217 </para></footnote> In any case, the innovators argued, the job of
3218 Congress was
<quote>to consider first the interest of [the public], whom
3219 they represent, and whose servants they are.
</quote> <quote>All talk about
3220 `theft,'
</quote> the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company
3221 wrote,
<quote>is the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas
3222 musical, literary or artistic, except as defined by
3223 statute.
</quote><footnote><para>
3225 To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright,
376 (prepared
3226 memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American
3227 Graphophone Company Association).
3230 <indexterm><primary>cover songs
</primary></indexterm>
3232 The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer
3233 <emphasis>and
</emphasis> the recording artist. Congress amended the
3234 law to make sure that composers would be paid for the
<quote>mechanical
3235 reproductions
</quote> of their music. But rather than simply granting the
3236 composer complete control over the right to make mechanical
3237 reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the
3238 music, at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be
3239 recorded once. This is the part of
3241 <!-- PAGE BREAK 70 -->
3242 copyright law that makes cover songs possible. Once a composer
3243 authorizes a recording of his song, others are free to record the same
3244 song, so long as they pay the original composer a fee set by the law.
3246 <indexterm id='idxcompulsorylicense' class='startofrange'
><primary>compulsory license
</primary></indexterm>
3247 <indexterm id='idxstatutorylicenses' class='startofrange'
><primary>statutory licenses
</primary></indexterm>
3249 American law ordinarily calls this a
<quote>compulsory license,
</quote> but I will
3250 refer to it as a
<quote>statutory license.
</quote> A statutory license is a license
3251 whose key terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the
3252 Copyright Act in
1909, record companies were free to distribute copies
3253 of recordings so long as they paid the composer (or copyright holder)
3254 the fee set by the statute.
3256 <indexterm id='idxgrishamjohn' class='startofrange'
><primary>Grisham, John
</primary></indexterm>
3258 This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham
3259 writes a novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if
3260 Grisham gives the publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to
3261 charge whatever he wants for that permission. The price to publish
3262 Grisham is thus set by Grisham, and copyright law ordinarily says you
3263 have no permission to use Grisham's work except with permission of
3266 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings' class='endofrange'
/>
3267 <indexterm><primary>Beatles
</primary></indexterm>
3269 But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And
3270 thus, in effect, the law
<emphasis>subsidizes
</emphasis> the recording
3271 industry through a kind of piracy
—by giving recording artists a
3272 weaker right than it otherwise gives creative authors. The Beatles
3273 have less control over their creative work than Grisham does. And the
3274 beneficiaries of this less control are the recording industry and the
3275 public. The recording industry gets something of value for less than
3276 it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much wider range
3277 of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about its
3278 reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of
3279 rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on
3280 creativity.
<footnote><para>
3283 Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S.
2499, S.
2900, H.R.
243, and
3284 H.R.
11794 Before the (Joint) Committee on Patents,
60th Cong.,
1st
3285 sess.,
217 (
1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted
3286 in
<citetitle>Legislative History of the
1909 Copyright Act
</citetitle>, E. Fulton Brylawski and
3287 Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints,
1976).
3290 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws' class='endofrange'
/>
3291 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry' class='endofrange'
/>
3292 <indexterm startref='idxgrishamjohn' class='endofrange'
/>
3294 While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently,
3295 historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for
3296 records. As a
1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary
3301 the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory
3302 <!-- PAGE BREAK 71 -->
3303 license system must be retained. They asserted that the record
3304 industry is a half-billion-dollar business of great economic
3305 importance in the United States and throughout the world; records
3306 today are the principal means of disseminating music, and this creates
3307 special problems, since performers need unhampered access to musical
3308 material on nondiscriminatory terms. Historically, the record
3309 producers pointed out, there were no recording rights before
1909 and
3310 the
1909 statute adopted the compulsory license as a deliberate
3311 anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these rights. They argue that
3312 the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, with the public
3313 being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater
3314 choice.
<footnote><para>
3316 Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R.
2512, House Committee
3317 on the Judiciary,
90th Cong.,
1st sess., House Document no.
83, (
8
3318 March
1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to
3319 this report.
</para></footnote>
3322 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin' class='endofrange'
/>
3323 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustrystatutorylicensesystemin' class='endofrange'
/>
3324 <indexterm startref='idxcompulsorylicense' class='endofrange'
/>
3325 <indexterm startref='idxstatutorylicenses' class='endofrange'
/>
3327 By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their
3328 creative work, the record producers, and the public, benefit.
3331 <section id=
"radio">
3332 <title>Radio
</title>
3333 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and
</secondary></indexterm>
3334 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
3336 Radio was also born of piracy.
3339 When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a
3340 <quote>public performance
</quote> of the composer's work.
<footnote><para>
3342 See
17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, sections
106 and
110. At the beginning,
3343 record companies printed
<quote>Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast
</quote> and other
3344 messages purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a
3345 radio station. Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a
3346 warning attached to a record might restrict the rights of the radio
3347 station. See
<citetitle>RCA Manufacturing Co
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Whiteman
</citetitle>,
114 F.
2d
86 (
2nd
3348 Cir.
1940). See also Randal C. Picker,
<quote>From Edison to the Broadcast
3349 Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of
3350 Copyright,
</quote> <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
281.
3351 <indexterm><primary>Hand, Learned
</primary></indexterm>
3352 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
3354 As I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder)
3355 an exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio
3356 station thus owes the composer money for that performance.
3359 But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a
3360 copy of the
<emphasis>composer's
</emphasis> work. The radio station is
3361 also performing a copy of the
<emphasis>recording artist's
</emphasis>
3362 work. It's one thing to have
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> sung on the radio by the
3363 local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by the
3364 Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the
3365 value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the
3366 law were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the
3367 recording artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the
3369 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
3371 <!-- PAGE BREAK 72 -->
3374 But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio
3375 station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station
3376 need only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of
3377 something for nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work
3378 for free, even if it must pay the composer something for the privilege
3379 of playing the song.
3381 <indexterm id='idxmadonna' class='startofrange'
><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
3383 This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music.
3384 Imagine it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize
3385 public performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your
3386 song in public, she has to get your permission.
3389 Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She
3390 then decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top
3391 hit. Under our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you
3392 get some money. But Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on
3393 the sale of her CDs. The public performance of her recording is not a
3394 <quote>protected
</quote> right. The radio station thus gets to
3395 <emphasis>pirate
</emphasis> the value of Madonna's work without paying
3398 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto' class='endofrange'
/>
3399 <indexterm startref='idxmadonna' class='endofrange'
/>
3401 No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists
3402 benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the
3403 performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law
3404 ordinarily gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making
3405 the choice for him or her, the law gives the radio station the right
3406 to take something for nothing.
3408 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand' class='endofrange'
/>
3410 <section id=
"cabletv">
3411 <title>Cable TV
</title>
3412 <indexterm id='idxcabletelevision' class='startofrange'
><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
3414 Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy.
3417 When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable
3418 television in
1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content
3419 that they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies
3420 started selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay
3421 <!-- PAGE BREAK 73 -->
3422 for what they sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing
3423 broadcasters' content, but more egregiously than anything Napster ever
3424 did
— Napster never charged for the content it enabled others to
3427 <indexterm><primary>Anello, Douglas
</primary></indexterm>
3428 <indexterm><primary>Burdick, Quentin
</primary></indexterm>
3429 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.
</primary></indexterm>
3431 Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft.
3432 Rosel Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of
3433 <quote>unfair and potentially destructive competition.
</quote><footnote><para>
3435 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV: Hearing on S.
1006 Before the
3436 Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate
3437 Committee on the Judiciary,
89th Cong.,
2nd sess.,
78 (
1966)
3438 (statement of Rosel H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications
3440 <indexterm><primary>Hyde, Rosel H.
</primary></indexterm>
3442 There may have been a
<quote>public interest
</quote> in spreading the reach of cable
3443 TV, but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association
3444 of Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony,
<quote>Does public
3445 interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?
</quote><footnote><para>
3447 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello,
3448 general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters).
3450 As another broadcaster put it,
3454 The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the
3455 only business I know of where the product that is being sold is not
3456 paid for.
<footnote><para>
3458 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes,
3459 general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.).
3464 Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough:
3468 All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now
3469 take our property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop
3470 piracy and I don't think there is any lesser word to describe it. I
3471 think there are harsher words which would fit it.
<footnote><para>
3473 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
169 (joint statement of Arthur B.
3474 Krim, president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of
3475 United Artists Television, Inc.).
3479 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton
</primary></indexterm>
3481 These were
<quote>free-ride[rs],
</quote> Screen Actor's Guild president Charlton
3482 Heston said, who were
<quote>depriving actors of
3483 compensation.
</quote><footnote><para>
3485 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
209 (statement of Charlton Heston,
3486 president of the Screen Actors Guild).
3487 <indexterm><primary>Heston, Charlton
</primary></indexterm>
3492 But again, there was another side to the debate. As Assistant Attorney
3493 General Edwin Zimmerman put it,
3497 Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any
3498 copyright protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright
3499 holders who are already compensated, who already have a monopoly,
3500 should be permitted to extend that monopoly.
… The
3502 <!-- PAGE BREAK 74 -->
3503 question here is how much compensation they should have and
3504 how far back they should carry their right to compensation.
<footnote><para>
3506 Copyright Law Revision
—CATV,
216 (statement of Edwin M.
3507 Zimmerman, acting assistant attorney general).
3508 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin
</primary></indexterm>
3510 <indexterm><primary>Zimmerman, Edwin
</primary></indexterm>
3514 Copyright owners took the cable companies to court. Twice the Supreme
3515 Court held that the cable companies owed the copyright owners nothing.
3518 It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question
3519 of whether cable companies had to pay for the content they
<quote>pirated.
</quote>
3520 In the end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it
3521 resolved the question about record players and player pianos. Yes,
3522 cable companies would have to pay for the content that they broadcast;
3523 but the price they would have to pay was not set by the copyright
3524 owner. The price was set by law, so that the broadcasters couldn't
3525 exercise veto power over the emerging technologies of cable. Cable
3526 companies thus built their empire in part upon a
<quote>piracy
</quote> of the value
3527 created by broadcasters' content.
3529 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyindevelopmentofcontentindustry' class='endofrange'
/>
3530 <indexterm startref='idxcabletelevision' class='endofrange'
/>
3532 <emphasis role='strong'
>These separate stories
</emphasis> sing a
3533 common theme. If
<quote>piracy
</quote> means using value from someone
3534 else's creative property without permission from that creator
—as
3535 it is increasingly described today
<footnote><para>
3537 See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association,
<citetitle>The Engine
3538 of Free Expression: Copyright on the Internet
—The Myth of Free
3539 Information
</citetitle>, available at
3540 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
13</ulink>.
<quote>The
3541 threat of piracy
—the use of someone else's creative work without
3542 permission or compensation
—has grown with the Internet.
</quote>
3544 — then
<emphasis>every
</emphasis> industry affected by copyright
3545 today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of
3546 piracy. Film, records, radio, cable TV.
… The list is long and
3547 could well be expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the
3548 last. Every generation
—until now.
3550 <!-- PAGE BREAK 75 -->
3553 <chapter label=
"5" id=
"piracy">
3554 <title><quote>Piracy
</quote></title>
3556 <emphasis role='strong'
>There is piracy
</emphasis> of copyrighted
3557 material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in many forms. The most
3558 significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized taking of other
3559 people's content within a commercial context. Despite the many
3560 justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is
3561 wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it.
3564 But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of
<quote>taking
</quote>
3565 that is more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems
3566 wrong to many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this
3567 taking
<quote>piracy,
</quote> however, we should understand its nature a bit more.
3568 For the harm of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than
3569 outright copying, and the law should account for that ambiguity, as it
3570 has so often done in the past.
3571 <!-- PAGE BREAK 76 -->
3573 <section id=
"piracy-i">
3574 <title>Piracy I
</title>
3575 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3576 <indexterm id='idxcdsforeign' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>foreign piracy of
</secondary></indexterm>
3578 All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there
3579 are businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted
3580 content, copy it, and sell it
—all without the permission of a copyright
3581 owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $
4.6 billion
3582 every year to physical piracy
<footnote><para>
3584 See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry),
<citetitle>The
3585 Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report
2003</citetitle>, July
2003, available
3586 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
14</ulink>. See
3587 also Ben Hunt,
<quote>Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk,
</quote> <citetitle>Financial
3588 Times
</citetitle>,
14 February
2003,
11.
3590 (that works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA
3591 estimates that it loses $
3 billion annually worldwide to piracy.
3594 This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this
3595 book, nor in the argument that most people make when talking about
3596 the subject of this book, should draw into doubt this simple point:
3597 This piracy is wrong.
3600 Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made
3601 for it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one
3602 hundred years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign
3603 copyrights. We were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might
3604 therefore seem hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other
3605 developing nations treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years
3606 of our existence, treated as right.
3609 That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban
3610 the taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American
3611 works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works
3612 without the permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule.
3613 The copy shops in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian
3614 law does protect foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops
3615 violate that law. So the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not
3616 just a moral wrong, but a legal wrong, and not just an internationally
3617 legal wrong, but a locally legal wrong as well.
3620 True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these
3621 countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose
3622 <!-- PAGE BREAK 77-->
3623 not to protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a
3624 pirate nation, but we will not allow any other nation to have a
3628 If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are
3629 its laws regardless of their source. The international law under which
3630 these nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden
3631 of intellectual property law.
<footnote><para>
3633 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism:
3634 <citetitle>Who Owns the Knowledge Economy?
</citetitle> (New York: The
3635 New Press,
2003),
10–13,
209. The Trade-Related Aspects of
3636 Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement obligates member
3637 nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms for
3638 intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing
3639 countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for
3640 staple industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the
3641 disparity between burdens imposed upon developing countries and
3642 benefits conferred to industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit
3643 governments to use patents for public, noncommercial uses without
3644 first obtaining the patent holder's permission. Developing nations may
3645 be able to use this to gain the benefits of foreign patents at lower
3646 prices. This is a promising strategy for developing nations within the
3648 <indexterm><primary>agricultural patents
</primary></indexterm>
3649 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
3650 </para></footnote> In my view, more developing nations should take
3651 advantage of that opportunity, but when they don't, then their laws
3652 should be respected. And under the laws of these nations, this piracy
3655 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3657 Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in
3658 any case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access
3659 to American CDs at
50 cents a copy are not people who would have
3660 bought those American CDs at $
15 a copy. So no one really has any
3661 less money than they otherwise would have had.
<footnote><para>
3663 For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan
3664 Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy
</citetitle> (New York: Amacom,
2002),
3665 144–90.
<quote>In some instances
… the impact of piracy on the
3666 copyright holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will
3667 be negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual
3668 engaging in pirating would not have purchased an original even if
3669 pirating were not an option.
</quote> Ibid.,
149.
3670 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
3674 This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many
3675 thousands of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay
3676 for the content they have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree
3677 the harm caused by such taking. Extremists in this debate love to say,
3678 <quote>You wouldn't go into Barnes
& Noble and take a book off of the shelf
3679 without paying; why should it be any different with on-line music?
</quote>
3680 The difference is, of course, that when you take a book from Barnes
&
3681 Noble, it has one less book to sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3
3682 from a computer network, there is not one less CD that can be sold.
3683 The physics of piracy of the intangible are different from the physics of
3684 piracy of the tangible.
3686 <indexterm startref='idxcdsforeign' class='endofrange'
/>
3688 This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a
3689 property right of a very special sort, it
<emphasis>is
</emphasis> a
3690 property right. Like all property rights, the copyright gives the
3691 owner the right to decide the terms under which content is shared. If
3692 the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she doesn't have to. There
3693 are exceptions: important statutory licenses that apply to copyrighted
3694 content regardless of the wish of the copyright owner. Those licenses
3695 give people the right to
<quote>take
</quote> copyrighted content whether or not the
3696 copyright owner wants to sell. But
3698 <!-- PAGE BREAK 78 -->
3699 where the law does not give people the right to take content, it is
3700 wrong to take that content even if the wrong does no harm. If we have
3701 a property system, and that system is properly balanced to the
3702 technology of a time, then it is wrong to take property without the
3703 permission of a property owner. That is exactly what
<quote>property
</quote> means.
3705 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
3706 <indexterm><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>in Asia
</secondary></indexterm>
3707 <indexterm><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)
</primary></indexterm>
3708 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3709 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3710 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>competitive strategies of
</secondary></indexterm>
3711 <indexterm><primary>Windows
</primary></indexterm>
3712 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>international software piracy of
</secondary></indexterm>
3713 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>Windows operating system of
</secondary></indexterm>
3715 Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the
3716 piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese
<quote>steal
</quote>
3717 Windows, that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft
3718 loses the value of the software that was taken. But it gains users who
3719 are used to life in the Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation
3720 grows more wealthy, more and more people will buy software rather than
3721 steal it. And hence over time, because that buying will benefit
3722 Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If instead of pirating
3723 Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux operating
3724 system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying
3725 Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose.
3727 <indexterm><primary>law
</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in
</secondary></indexterm>
3729 This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good
3730 one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law
3731 students, for example, are given free access to the two largest legal
3732 databases. The companies marketing both hope the students will become
3733 so used to their service that they will want to use it and not the
3734 other when they become lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees).
3736 <indexterm><primary>Netscape
</primary></indexterm>
3737 <indexterm><primary>Internet Explorer
</primary></indexterm>
3738 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3739 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
3741 Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the
3742 alcoholic a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that
3743 will make it more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we
3744 ordinarily allow businesses to decide for themselves when it is best
3745 to give their product away. If Microsoft fears the competition of
3746 GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can give its product away, as it did, for
3747 example, with Internet Explorer to fight Netscape. A property right
3748 means giving the property owner the right to say who gets access to
3749 what
—at least ordinarily. And if the law properly balances the
3750 rights of the copyright owner with the rights of access, then
3751 violating the law is still wrong.
3754 <!-- PAGE BREAK 79 -->
3755 Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy,
3756 and I certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts
3757 at justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy
3758 is rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it
3759 steals; it doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives
3760 someone access to something that the law says he should not have.
3761 Nothing has changed to draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy
3765 But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part
3766 suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all
<quote>piracy
</quote> is. Or
3767 at least, not all
<quote>piracy
</quote> is wrong if that term is understood in the
3768 way it is increasingly used today. Many kinds of
<quote>piracy
</quote> are useful
3769 and productive, to produce either new content or new ways of doing
3770 business. Neither our tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all
3771 <quote>piracy
</quote> in that sense of the term.
3774 This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest
3775 piracy concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we
3776 need to understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before
3777 we condemn it to the gallows with the charge of piracy.
3780 For (
1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly
3781 controlling industry; and (
2) like the original recording industry, it
3782 simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (
3) unlike cable
3783 TV, no one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services.
3786 These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They
3787 should push us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this
3791 <section id=
"piracy-ii">
3792 <title>Piracy II
</title>
3794 The key to the
<quote>piracy
</quote> that the law aims to quash is a use that
<quote>rob[s]
3795 the author of [his] profit.
</quote><footnote><para>
3797 <citetitle>Bach
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Longman
</citetitle>,
98 Eng. Rep.
1274 (
1777).
3799 This means we must determine whether
3800 and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how strongly the
3801 <!-- PAGE BREAK 80 -->
3802 law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to assure the
3803 author of his profit.
3806 <indexterm><primary>Fanning, Shawn
</primary></indexterm>
3807 <indexterm><primary>innovation
</primary></indexterm>
3808 <indexterm id='idxnapster' class='startofrange'
><primary>Napster
</primary></indexterm>
3809 Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of
3810 the Napster technology had not made any major technological
3811 innovations. Like every great advance in innovation on the Internet
3812 (and, arguably, off the Internet as well
<footnote><para>
3814 <indexterm><primary>innovation
</primary></indexterm>
3815 See Clayton M. Christensen,
<citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary
3816 National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business
</citetitle> (New York:
3817 HarperBusiness,
2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies
3818 that give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to
3819 come up with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own
3820 products. This job usually falls to outside innovators, who
3821 reassemble existing technology in inventive ways. For a discussion of
3822 Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>Future
</citetitle>,
89–92,
139.
3824 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.
</primary></indexterm>
3825 </para></footnote>), Shawn Fanning and crew had simply
3826 put together components that had been developed independently.
3829 <indexterm><primary>Kazaa
</primary></indexterm>
3830 <indexterm><primary>Napster
</primary><secondary>number of registrations on
</secondary></indexterm>
3831 <indexterm><primary>Napster
</primary><secondary>replacement of
</secondary></indexterm>
3832 The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July
1999,
3833 Napster amassed over
10 million users within nine months. After
3834 eighteen months, there were close to
80 million registered users of the
3835 system.
<footnote><para>
3837 See Carolyn Lochhead,
<quote>Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare,
</quote> <citetitle>San
3838 Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
24 September
2002, A1;
<quote>Rock 'n' Roll Suicide,
</quote>
3839 <citetitle>New Scientist
</citetitle>,
6 July
2002,
42; Benny Evangelista,
<quote>Napster Names CEO,
3840 Secures New Financing,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
23 May
2003, C1;
3841 <quote>Napster's Wake-Up Call,
</quote> <citetitle>Economist
</citetitle>,
24 June
2000,
23; John Naughton,
3842 <quote>Hollywood at War with the Internet
</quote> (London)
<citetitle>Times
</citetitle>,
26 July
2002,
18.
3844 Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other services emerged
3845 to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p service. It
3846 boasts over
100 million members.) These services' systems are different
3847 architecturally, though not very different in function: Each enables
3848 users to make content available to any number of other users. With a
3849 p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend
—
3850 or your
20,
000 best friends.
3852 <indexterm startref='idxnapster' class='endofrange'
/>
3854 According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans
3855 have tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in
3856 September
2002 estimated that
60 million Americans had downloaded
3857 music
—28 percent of Americans older than
12.
<footnote><para>
3860 See Ipsos-Insight,
<citetitle>TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution
</citetitle>
3861 (September
2002), reporting that
28 percent of Americans aged twelve
3862 and older have downloaded music off of the Internet and
30 percent have
3863 listened to digital music files stored on their computers.
3865 A survey by the NPD group quoted in
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>
3866 estimated that
43 million citizens used file-sharing networks to
3867 exchange content in May
2003.
<footnote><para>
3869 Amy Harmon,
<quote>Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight,
</quote> <citetitle>New
3870 York Times
</citetitle>,
6 June
2003, A1.
3872 The vast majority of these are not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a
3873 massive quantity of content is being
<quote>taken
</quote> on these networks. The
3874 ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing networks have inspired
3875 millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't before.
3878 Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does
3879 not. And even among the part that is technically copyright
3880 infringement, calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more
3881 complicated than one might think. So consider
—a bit more
3882 carefully than the polarized voices around this debate usually
3883 do
—the kinds of sharing that file sharing enables, and the kinds
3887 <!-- PAGE BREAK 81 -->
3888 File sharers share different kinds of content. We can divide these
3889 different kinds into four types.
3891 <orderedlist numeration=
"upperalpha">
3893 <indexterm><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
3896 There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing
3897 content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying
3898 the CD, these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether
3899 everyone who takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't
3900 make it available for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly
3901 there are some who would. The latter are the target of category A:
3902 users who download instead of purchasing.
3906 There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before
3907 purchasing it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist
3908 he's not heard of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This
3909 is a kind of targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the
3910 friend recommending the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation,
3911 then one could expect that the recommendations will actually be quite
3912 good. The net effect of this sharing could increase the quantity of
3917 There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted
3918 content that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased
3919 because the transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of
3920 sharing networks is among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were
3921 part of your childhood but have long vanished from the marketplace
3922 magically appear again on the network. (One friend told me that when
3923 she discovered Napster, she spent a solid weekend
<quote>recalling
</quote> old
3924 songs. She was astonished at the range and mix of content that was
3925 available.) For content not sold, this is still technically a
3926 violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is not
3927 selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero
—the same
3928 harm that occurs when I sell my collection of
1960s
45-rpm records to
3932 <!-- PAGE BREAK 82 -->
3934 Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access
3935 to content that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner
3940 How do these different types of sharing balance out?
3943 Let's start with some simple but important points. From the
3944 perspective of the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the
3945 perspective of economics, only type A sharing is clearly
3946 harmful.
<footnote><para>
3948 See Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy
</citetitle>,
148–49.
3949 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
3951 Type B sharing is illegal but plainly beneficial. Type C sharing is
3952 illegal, yet good for society (since more exposure to music is good)
3953 and harmless to the artist (since the work is not otherwise
3954 available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard question to
3955 answer
—and certainly much more difficult than the current
3956 rhetoric around the issue suggests.
3959 Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how
3960 harmful type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood,
3961 composers complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained
3962 about radio, and broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music
3963 industry complains that type A sharing is a kind of
<quote>theft
</quote> that is
3964 <quote>devastating
</quote> the industry.
3966 <indexterm id='idxcassette' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
3968 While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how
3969 harmful is harder to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's
3970 practice to blame technology for any drop in sales. The history of
3971 cassette recording is a good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst
3972 & Young put it,
<quote>Rather than exploiting this new, popular
3973 technology, the labels fought it.
</quote><footnote><para>
3975 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary></indexterm>
3976 See Cap Gemini Ernst
& Young,
<citetitle>Technology Evolution and the
3977 Music Industry's Business Model Crisis
</citetitle> (
2003),
3. This report
3978 describes the music industry's effort to stigmatize the budding
3979 practice of cassette taping in the
1970s, including an advertising
3980 campaign featuring a cassette-shape skull and the caption
<quote>Home taping
3981 is killing music.
</quote> At the time digital audio tape became a threat,
3982 the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a survey of consumer
3983 behavior. In
1988,
40 percent of consumers older than ten had taped
3984 music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology
3985 Assessment,
<citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law
</citetitle>,
3986 OTA-CIT-
422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office,
3987 October
1989),
145–56.
</para></footnote>
3988 The labels claimed that every album taped was an album unsold, and
3989 when record sales fell by
11.4 percent in
1981, the industry claimed
3990 that its point was proved. Technology was the problem, and banning or
3991 regulating technology was the answer.
3993 <indexterm><primary>MTV
</primary></indexterm>
3995 Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity
3996 to enact regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record
3997 turnaround.
<quote>In the end,
</quote> Cap Gemini concludes,
<quote>the `crisis'
… was
3998 not the fault of the tapers
—who did not [stop after MTV came into
3999 <!-- PAGE BREAK 83 -->
4000 being]
—but had to a large extent resulted from stagnation in musical
4001 innovation at the major labels.
</quote><footnote><para>
4003 U.S. Congress,
<citetitle>Copyright and Home Copying
</citetitle>,
4.
4006 <indexterm startref='idxcassette' class='endofrange'
/>
4008 But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is
4009 wrong today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to
4010 the industry in particular, and society in general
—or at least
4011 the society that inherits the tradition that gave us the film
4012 industry, the record industry, the radio industry, cable TV, and the
4013 VCR
—the question is not simply whether type A sharing is
4014 harmful. The question is also
<emphasis>how
</emphasis> harmful type A
4015 sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are.
4018 We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the
4019 standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause.
4020 The
<quote>net harm
</quote> to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type
4021 A sharing exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records
4022 through sampling than they lost through substitution, then sharing
4023 networks would actually benefit music companies on balance. They would
4024 therefore have little
<emphasis>static
</emphasis> reason to resist
4028 <indexterm id='idxcdssales' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>sales levels of
</secondary></indexterm>
4030 Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because
4031 of file sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales
4032 actually suggest it might be close.
4035 In
2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by
8.9 percent,
4036 from
882 million to
803 million units; revenues fell
6.7
4037 percent.
<footnote><para>
4039 See Recording Industry Association of America,
<citetitle>2002 Yearend Statistics
</citetitle>,
4041 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
15</ulink>. A later
4042 report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry
4043 Association of America,
<citetitle>Some Facts About Music Piracy
</citetitle>,
25 June
2003,
4044 available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
4045 #
16</ulink>:
<quote>In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music
4046 have fallen by
26 percent from
1.16 billion units in to
860 million
4047 units in
2002 in the United States (based on units shipped). In terms
4048 of sales, revenues are down
14 percent, from $
14.6 billion in to $
12.6
4049 billion last year (based on U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music
4050 industry worldwide has gone from a $
39 billion industry in
2000 down
4051 to a $
32 billion industry in
2002 (based on U.S. dollar value of
4054 This confirms a trend over the past few years. The RIAA blames
4055 Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other causes that
4056 could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a more
4057 than
20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since
1999. That no
4058 doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could
4059 account for at least some of the loss.
<quote>From
1999 to
2001, the average
4060 price of a CD rose
7.2 percent, from $
13.04 to $
14.19.
</quote><footnote>
4063 Jane Black,
<quote>Big Music's Broken Record,
</quote> BusinessWeek online,
13
4064 February
2003, available at
4065 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
17</ulink>.
4066 <indexterm><primary>Black, Jane
</primary></indexterm>
4069 Competition from other forms of media could also account for some of
4070 the decline. As Jane Black of
<citetitle>BusinessWeek
</citetitle> notes,
<quote>The
4071 soundtrack to the film
<citetitle>High Fidelity
</citetitle> has a list price of
4072 $
18.98. You could get the whole movie [on DVD] for
4073 $
19.99.
</quote><footnote><para>
4080 <!-- PAGE BREAK 84 -->
4081 But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales
4082 is because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period
4083 that the RIAA estimates that
803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA
4084 estimates that
2.1 billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus,
4085 although
2.6 times the total number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4086 free, sales revenue fell by just
6.7 percent.
4089 There are too many different things happening at the same time to
4090 explain these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable:
4091 The recording industry constantly asks,
<quote>What's the difference between
4092 downloading a song and stealing a CD?
</quote>—but their own numbers
4093 reveal the difference. If I steal a CD, then there is one less CD to
4094 sell. Every taking is a lost sale. But on the basis of the numbers the
4095 RIAA provides, it is absolutely clear that the same is not true of
4096 downloads. If every download were a lost sale
—if every use of
4097 Kazaa
<quote>rob[bed] the author of [his] profit
</quote>—then the industry
4098 would have suffered a
100 percent drop in sales last year, not a
7
4099 percent drop. If
2.6 times the number of CDs sold were downloaded for
4100 free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just
6.7 percent, then there is
4101 a huge difference between
<quote>downloading a song and stealing a CD.
</quote>
4103 <indexterm startref='idxcdssales' class='endofrange'
/>
4105 These are the harms
—alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's
4106 assume, real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on
4107 the recording industry. What value does it produce in addition to
4111 One benefit is type C sharing
—making available content that
4112 is technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially
4113 available. This is not a small category of content. There are
4114 millions of tracks that are no longer commercially
4115 available.
<footnote><para>
4117 By one estimate,
75 percent of the music released by the major labels
4118 is no longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright
4119 Law
—Coming Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the
4120 Senate Committee on the Judiciary,
107th Cong.,
1st sess. (
3 April
4121 2001) (prepared statement of the Future of Music Coalition), available
4122 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
18</ulink>.
4124 And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available
4125 because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made
4126 available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the
4127 publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic
4128 sense
<emphasis>to the company
</emphasis> to make it available.
4130 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
4132 In real space
—long before the Internet
—the market had a simple
4133 <!-- PAGE BREAK 85 -->
4134 response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are
4135 thousands of used book and used record stores in America
4136 today.
<footnote><para>
4138 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
4139 While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores
4140 in existence, in
2002, there were
7,
198 used book dealers in the
4141 United States, an increase of
20 percent since
1993. See Book Hunter
4142 Press,
<citetitle>The Quiet Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book
4143 Market
</citetitle> (
2002), available at
4144 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
19</ulink>. Used
4145 records accounted for $
260 million in sales in
2002. See National
4146 Association of Recording Merchandisers,
<quote>2002 Annual Survey
4147 Results,
</quote> available at
4148 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
20</ulink>.
4150 These stores buy content from owners, then sell the content they
4151 buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell this
4152 content,
<emphasis>even if the content is still under
4153 copyright
</emphasis>, the copyright owner doesn't get a dime. Used
4154 book and record stores are commercial entities; their owners make
4155 money from the content they sell; but as with cable companies before
4156 statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the copyright owner for
4157 the content they sell.
4159 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
4160 <indexterm><primary>Bernstein, Leonard
</primary></indexterm>
4161 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>books on
</secondary></indexterm>
4163 Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used
4164 record stores. It is different, of course, because the person making
4165 the content available isn't making money from making the content
4166 available. It is also different, of course, because in real space,
4167 when I sell a record, I don't have it anymore, while in cyberspace,
4168 when someone shares my
1949 recording of Bernstein's
<quote>Two Love Songs,
</quote>
4169 I still have it. That difference would matter economically if the
4170 owner of the copyright were selling the record in competition to my
4171 sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that is not
4172 currently commercially available. The Internet is making it available,
4173 through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market.
4176 It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the
4177 copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may
4178 well be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book
4179 stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be
4180 stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be
4183 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of
</secondary></indexterm>
4184 <indexterm><primary>Doctorow, Cory
</primary></indexterm>
4185 <indexterm><primary>Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom (Doctorow)
</primary></indexterm>
4187 Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable
4188 type D sharing to occur
—the sharing of content that copyright owners
4189 want to have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This
4190 sharing clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author
4191 Cory Doctorow, for example, released his first novel,
<citetitle>Down and Out in
4192 the Magic Kingdom
</citetitle>, both free on-line and in bookstores on the same
4194 <!-- PAGE BREAK 86 -->
4195 day. His (and his publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution
4196 would be a great advertisement for the
<quote>real
</quote> book. People would read
4197 part on-line, and then decide whether they liked the book or not. If
4198 they liked it, they would be more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is
4199 type D content. If sharing networks enable his work to be spread, then
4200 both he and society are better off. (Actually, much better off: It is a
4203 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline1' class='endofrange'
/>
4205 Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society
4206 with no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem
4207 of type A sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we
4208 lose something important in order to protect type A content.
4211 The point throughout is this: While the recording industry
4212 understandably says,
<quote>This is how much we've lost,
</quote> we must also ask,
4213 <quote>How much has society gained from p2p sharing? What are the
4214 efficiencies? What is the content that otherwise would be
4215 unavailable?
</quote>
4217 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson' class='endofrange'
/>
4219 For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this
4220 chapter, much of the
<quote>piracy
</quote> that file sharing enables is plainly
4221 legal and good. And like the piracy I described in chapter
4222 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"pirates"/>, much of
4223 this piracy is motivated by a new way of spreading content caused by
4224 changes in the technology of distribution. Thus, consistent with the
4225 tradition that gave us Hollywood, radio, the recording industry, and
4226 cable TV, the question we should be asking about file sharing is how
4227 best to preserve its benefits while minimizing (to the extent
4228 possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The question is one of
4229 balance. The law should seek that balance, and that balance will be
4230 found only with time.
4233 <quote>But isn't the war just a war against illegal sharing? Isn't the target
4234 just what you call type A sharing?
</quote>
4237 You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The effect
4238 of the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far
4239 beyond that one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the
4240 Napster case itself. When Napster told the district court that it had
4241 developed a technology to block the transfer of
99.4 percent of
4244 <!-- PAGE BREAK 87 -->
4245 infringing material, the district court told counsel for Napster
99.4
4246 percent was not good enough. Napster had to push the infringements
4247 <quote>down to zero.
</quote><footnote><para>
4249 See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at
34-
4250 35 (N.D. Cal.,
11 July
2001), nos. MDL-
00-
1369 MHP, C
99-
5183
4253 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
21</ulink>. For an
4254 account of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn,
4255 <citetitle>All the Rave: The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster
</citetitle> (New
4256 York: Crown Business,
2003),
269–82.
4260 If
99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing
4261 technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to
4262 assure that a p2p system is used
100 percent of the time in compliance
4263 with the law, any more than there is a way to assure that
100 percent of
4264 VCRs or
100 percent of Xerox machines or
100 percent of handguns
4265 are used in compliance with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p.
4266 The court's ruling means that we as a society must lose the benefits of
4267 p2p, even for the totally legal and beneficial uses they serve, simply to
4268 assure that there are zero copyright infringements caused by p2p.
4271 Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the
4272 content industry that we know today. The history of American law has
4273 been a process of balance. As new technologies changed the way content
4274 was distributed, the law adjusted, after some time, to the new
4275 technology. In this adjustment, the law sought to ensure the
4276 legitimate rights of creators while protecting innovation. Sometimes
4277 this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes less.
4279 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
4280 <indexterm><primary>composers, copyright protections of
</primary></indexterm>
4281 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
4282 <indexterm id='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
4283 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on music recordings
</secondary></indexterm>
4284 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in
</secondary></indexterm>
4285 <indexterm><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>music recordings played on
</secondary></indexterm>
4286 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
4287 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>copyright protections in
</secondary></indexterm>
4288 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and
</secondary></indexterm>
4289 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses
</primary></indexterm>
4290 <indexterm><primary>composer's rights vs. producers' rights in
</primary></indexterm>
4292 So, as we've seen, when
<quote>mechanical reproduction
</quote> threatened the
4293 interests of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers
4294 against the interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to
4295 composers, but also to the recording artists: Composers were to be
4296 paid, but at a price set by Congress. But when radio started
4297 broadcasting the recordings made by these recording artists, and they
4298 complained to Congress that their
<quote>creative property
</quote> was not being
4299 respected (since the radio station did not have to pay them for the
4300 creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their claim. An indirect
4303 <indexterm id='idxcabletv2' class='startofrange'
><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
4305 Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts
4306 rejected the claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content
4307 they rebroadcast, Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to
4308 compensation, but at a level set by the law. It likewise gave cable
4309 companies the right to the content, so long as they paid the statutory
4312 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusonrecordingindustry2' class='endofrange'
/>
4315 <!-- PAGE BREAK 88 -->
4316 This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player
4317 pianos, served two important goals
—indeed, the two central goals
4318 of any copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new
4319 innovators would have the freedom to develop new ways to deliver
4320 content. Second, the law assured that copyright holders would be paid
4321 for the content that was distributed. One fear was that if Congress
4322 simply required cable TV to pay copyright holders whatever they
4323 demanded for their content, then copyright holders associated with
4324 broadcasters would use their power to stifle this new technology,
4325 cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use broadcasters'
4326 content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized cable. Thus
4327 Congress chose a path that would assure
4328 <emphasis>compensation
</emphasis> without giving the past
4329 (broadcasters) control over the future (cable).
4331 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonmusicrecordings2' class='endofrange'
/>
4332 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawstatutorylicensesin2' class='endofrange'
/>
4333 <indexterm startref='idxcabletv2' class='endofrange'
/>
4334 <indexterm id='idxbetamax' class='startofrange'
><primary>Betamax
</primary></indexterm>
4335 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs1' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
4337 In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major
4338 producers and distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against
4339 another technology, the video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to
4340 them today, VCRs) that Sony had produced, the Betamax. Disney's and
4341 Universal's claim against Sony was relatively simple: Sony produced a
4342 device, Disney and Universal claimed, that enabled consumers to engage
4343 in copyright infringement. Because the device that Sony built had a
4344 <quote>record
</quote> button, the device could be used to record copyrighted movies
4345 and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the copyright
4346 infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and
4347 Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement.
4349 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws2' class='endofrange'
/>
4351 There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did
4352 decide to design its machine to make it very simple to record television
4353 shows. It could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct
4354 copying from a television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the
4355 machine to copy only if there were a special
<quote>copy me
</quote> signal on the
4356 line. It was clear that there were many television shows that did not
4357 grant anyone permission to copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no
4358 doubt the majority of shows would not have authorized copying. And
4359 <!-- PAGE BREAK 89 -->
4360 in the face of this obvious preference, Sony could have designed its
4361 system to minimize the opportunity for copyright infringement. It did
4362 not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold it responsible
4363 for the architecture it chose.
4365 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
4366 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on VCR technology
</secondary></indexterm>
4368 MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal
4369 champion. Valenti called VCRs
<quote>tapeworms.
</quote> He warned,
<quote>When there are
4370 20,
30,
40 million of these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by
4371 millions of `tapeworms,' eating away at the very heart and essence of
4372 the most precious asset the copyright owner has, his
4373 copyright.
</quote><footnote><para>
4375 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on
4376 S.
1758 Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary,
97th Cong.,
1st
4377 and
2nd sess.,
459 (
1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion
4378 Picture Association of America, Inc.).
4380 <quote>One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and
4381 creative judgment,
</quote> he told Congress,
<quote>to understand the devastation
4382 on the after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of
4383 tapings that will adversely impact on the future of the creative
4384 community in this country. It is simply a question of basic economics
4385 and plain common sense.
</quote><footnote><para>
4387 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders),
475.
4389 Indeed, as surveys would later show,
45
4390 percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or more
<footnote><para>
4392 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle>,
480 F. Supp.
429,
4395 — a use the Court would later hold was not
<quote>fair.
</quote> By
4396 <quote>allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the means of an exemption from
4397 copyright infringement without creating a mechanism to compensate
4398 copyright owners,
</quote> Valenti testified, Congress would
<quote>take from the
4399 owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive right to
4400 control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and thereby
4401 profit from its reproduction.
</quote><footnote><para>
4403 Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders),
485 (testimony
4407 <indexterm startref='idxbetamax' class='endofrange'
/>
4409 It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme
4410 Court. In the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which
4411 includes Hollywood in its jurisdiction
—leading Judge Alex
4412 Kozinski, who sits on that court, refers to it as the
<quote>Hollywood
4413 Circuit
</quote>—held that Sony would be liable for the copyright
4414 infringement made possible by its machines. Under the Ninth Circuit's
4415 rule, this totally familiar technology
—which Jack Valenti had
4416 called
<quote>the Boston Strangler of the American film industry
</quote> (worse
4417 yet, it was a
<emphasis>Japanese
</emphasis> Boston Strangler of the
4418 American film industry)
—was an illegal
4419 technology.
<footnote><para>
4421 <citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle>,
659 F.
2d
963 (
9th Cir.
4424 <indexterm><primary>Kozinski, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
4427 But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit.
4429 <!-- PAGE BREAK 90 -->
4430 And in its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of
4431 when and whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the
4436 Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference
4437 to Congress when major technological innovations alter the
4439 for copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional
4441 and the institutional ability to accommodate fully the
4442 varied permutations of competing interests that are inevitably
4444 by such new technology.
<footnote><para>
4446 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
431 (
1984).
4450 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws3' class='endofrange'
/>
4452 Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as
4453 with the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress
4454 ignored the request. Congress was convinced that American film got
4455 enough, this
<quote>taking
</quote> notwithstanding. If we put these cases
4456 together, a pattern is clear:
4459 <informaltable id=
"t1">
4460 <tgroup cols=
"4" align=
"left">
4464 <entry>WHOSE VALUE WAS
<quote>PIRATED
</quote></entry>
4465 <entry>RESPONSE OF THE COURTS
</entry>
4466 <entry>RESPONSE OF CONGRESS
</entry>
4471 <entry>Recordings
</entry>
4472 <entry>Composers
</entry>
4473 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4474 <entry>Statutory license
</entry>
4477 <entry>Radio
</entry>
4478 <entry>Recording artists
</entry>
4480 <entry>Nothing
</entry>
4483 <entry>Cable TV
</entry>
4484 <entry>Broadcasters
</entry>
4485 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4486 <entry>Statutory license
</entry>
4490 <entry>Film creators
</entry>
4491 <entry>No protection
</entry>
4492 <entry>Nothing
</entry>
4497 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs1' class='endofrange'
/>
4499 In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the
4500 way content was distributed.
<footnote><para>
4502 These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other
4503 cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example,
4504 was regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy
4505 Congress imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and
4506 controlling the technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of
4507 1992 (Title
17 of the
<citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>), Pub. L. No.
102-
563,
106 Stat.
4508 4237, codified at
17 U.S.C. §
1001. Again, however, this regulation did not
4509 eliminate the opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See
4510 Lessig,
<citetitle>Future
</citetitle>,
71. See also Picker,
<quote>From Edison to the Broadcast Flag,
</quote>
4511 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
293–96.
4512 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
4513 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
4515 In each case, throughout our history,
4516 that change meant that someone got a
<quote>free ride
</quote> on someone else's
4520 In
<emphasis>none
</emphasis> of these cases did either the courts or
4521 Congress eliminate all free riding. In
<emphasis>none
</emphasis> of
4522 these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the law should
4523 assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his copyright
4524 created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of
<quote>piracy.
</quote>
4525 In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy in
4526 the behavior of the
<quote>pirates.
</quote> In each case, Congress allowed some new
4527 technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the
4529 <!-- PAGE BREAK 91 -->
4531 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
4533 When you think across these examples, and the other examples that
4534 make up the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes
4535 sense. Was Walt Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators
4536 had to ask permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and
4537 spread images as a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better
4539 Is it really right that building a search engine should expose you
4540 to $
15 million in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had
4541 controlled film? Should every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get
4542 permission to record a song?
4544 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on balance of interests in copyright law
</secondary></indexterm>
4546 We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition
4547 has answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated,
4548 copyright
<quote>has never accorded the copyright owner complete control
4549 over all possible uses of his work.
</quote><footnote><para>
4551 <citetitle>Sony Corp. of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
4554 Instead, the particular uses that the law regulates have been defined
4555 by balancing the good that comes from granting an exclusive right
4556 against the burdens such an exclusive right creates. And this
4557 balancing has historically been done
<emphasis>after
</emphasis> a
4558 technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that
4559 facilitate the distribution of content.
4562 We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the
4563 Internet is changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet
4564 (wires vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network
4565 should not become a tool for
<quote>stealing
</quote> from artists. But neither
4566 should the law become a tool to entrench one particular way in which
4567 artists (or more accurately, distributors) get paid. As I describe in
4568 some detail in the last chapter of this book, we should be securing
4569 income to artists while we allow the market to secure the most
4570 efficient way to promote and distribute content. This will require
4571 changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes should be
4572 designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong
4573 public interest that innovation continue.
4577 <!-- PAGE BREAK 92 -->
4578 This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly
4579 superior mode of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies
4580 can be ideally efficient in moving content across a widely diverse
4581 network. Left to develop, they could make the network vastly more
4582 efficient. Yet these
<quote>potential public benefits,
</quote> as John Schwartz
4583 writes in
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>,
<quote>could be delayed in the P2P
4584 fight.
</quote><footnote><para>
4586 John Schwartz,
<quote>New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software
4587 Echoes Past Efforts,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
22 September
2003, C3.
4591 <emphasis role='strong'
>Yet when anyone
</emphasis> begins to talk
4592 about
<quote>balance,
</quote> the copyright warriors raise a different
4593 argument.
<quote>All this hand waving about balance and
4594 incentives,
</quote> they say,
<quote>misses a fundamental point. Our
4595 content,
</quote> the warriors insist,
<quote>is our
4596 <emphasis>property
</emphasis>. Why should we wait for Congress to
4597 `rebalance' our property rights? Do you have to wait before calling
4598 the police when your car has been stolen? And why should Congress
4599 deliberate at all about the merits of this theft? Do we ask whether
4600 the car thief had a good use for the car before we arrest him?
</quote>
4603 <quote>It is
<emphasis>our property
</emphasis>,
</quote> the warriors
4604 insist.
<quote>And it should be protected just as any other property
4605 is protected.
</quote>
4607 <!-- PAGE BREAK 93 -->
4611 <part id=
"c-property">
4612 <title><quote>PROPERTY
</quote></title>
4616 <!-- PAGE BREAK 94 -->
4617 <emphasis role='strong'
>The copyright warriors
</emphasis> are right: A
4618 copyright is a kind of property. It can be owned and sold, and the law
4619 protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the copyright owner gets to
4620 hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the supply and demand
4621 that partially determine the price she can get.
4624 But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a
<quote>property
</quote> right is a
4625 bit misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of
4626 property. Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any
4627 expression is very odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the
4628 picnic table you put in your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic
4629 table, and after I take it, you don't have it. But what am I taking
4630 when I take the good
<emphasis>idea
</emphasis> you had to put a picnic
4631 table in the backyard
—by, for example, going to Sears, buying a
4632 table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking
4635 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
4637 The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus
4638 ideas, though that's an important difference. The point instead is that
4639 <!-- PAGE BREAK 95 -->
4640 in the ordinary case
—indeed, in practically every case except for a
4642 range of exceptions
—ideas released to the world are free. I don't
4643 take anything from you when I copy the way you dress
—though I
4644 might seem weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a
4645 woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true
4646 when I copy the way someone else dresses),
<quote>He who receives an idea
4647 from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who
4648 lights his taper at mine, receives light without darkening me.
</quote><footnote><para>
4650 Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (
13 August
1813) in
4651 <citetitle>The Writings of Thomas Jefferson
</citetitle>, vol.
6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert
4652 Ellery Bergh, eds.,
1903),
330,
333–34.
4655 <indexterm><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>intangibility of
</secondary></indexterm>
4657 The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the
4658 reach of the law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that
4659 I won't discuss here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or
4661 without my permission: The law turns the intangible into
4665 But how, and to what extent, and in what form
—the details,
4666 in other words
—matter. To get a good sense of how this practice
4667 of turning the intangible into property emerged, we need to place this
4668 <quote>property
</quote> in its proper context.
<footnote><para>
4670 As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are
4671 intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has
4672 against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not
4673 attach to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if
4674 the object to which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See
4675 Adam Mossoff,
<quote>What Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together,
</quote>
4676 <citetitle>Arizona Law Review
</citetitle> 45 (
2003):
373,
429 n.
241.
4680 My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the
4681 preceding part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of
4682 <quote>copyright material is property
</quote> in context. Where did the idea come
4683 from? What are its limits? How does it function in practice? After
4684 these stories, the significance of this true
4685 statement
—<quote>copyright material is property
</quote>— will be a bit
4686 more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different
4687 from the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw.
4691 <!-- PAGE BREAK 96 -->
4692 <chapter label=
"6" id=
"founders">
4693 <title>Founders
</title>
4694 <indexterm id='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>English copyright law developed for
</secondary></indexterm>
4695 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
4696 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>English
</secondary></indexterm>
4697 <indexterm id='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='startofrange'
><primary>England, copyright laws developed in
</primary></indexterm>
4698 <indexterm id='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='startofrange'
><primary>United Kingdom
</primary><secondary>history of copyright law in
</secondary></indexterm>
4699 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
4700 <indexterm><primary>Henry V
</primary></indexterm>
4701 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
4702 <indexterm id='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='startofrange'
><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)
</primary></indexterm>
4704 <emphasis role='strong'
>William Shakespeare
</emphasis> wrote
4705 <citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> in
1595. The play was first
4706 published in
1597. It was the eleventh major play that Shakespeare had
4707 written. He would continue to write plays through
1613, and the plays
4708 that he wrote have continued to define Anglo-American culture ever
4709 since. So deeply have the works of a sixteenth-century writer seeped
4710 into our culture that we often don't even recognize their source. I
4711 once overheard someone commenting on Kenneth Branagh's adaptation of
4712 Henry V:
<quote>I liked it, but Shakespeare is so full of
4715 <indexterm><primary>Conger
</primary></indexterm>
4716 <indexterm id='idxtonsonjacob' class='startofrange'
><primary>Tonson, Jacob
</primary></indexterm>
4718 In
1774, almost
180 years after
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> was written, the
4719 <quote>copy-right
</quote> for the work was still thought by many to be the exclusive
4720 right of a single London publisher, Jacob Tonson.
<footnote><para>
4722 <indexterm><primary>Jonson, Ben
</primary></indexterm>
4723 <indexterm><primary>Dryden, John
</primary></indexterm>
4724 Jacob Tonson is typically remembered for his associations with prominent
4725 eighteenth-century literary figures, especially John Dryden, and for his
4726 handsome
<quote>definitive editions
</quote> of classic works. In addition to
<citetitle>Romeo and
4727 Juliet
</citetitle>, he published an astonishing array of works that still remain at the
4728 heart of the English canon, including collected works of Shakespeare, Ben
4729 Jonson, John Milton, and John Dryden. See Keith Walker,
<quote>Jacob Tonson,
4730 Bookseller,
</quote> <citetitle>American Scholar
</citetitle> 61:
3 (
1992):
424–31.
4732 Tonson was the most prominent of a small group of publishers called
4733 the Conger
<footnote><para>
4735 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective
</citetitle> (Nashville:
4736 Vanderbilt University Press,
1968),
151–52.
4738 who controlled bookselling in England during the eighteenth
4739 century. The Conger claimed a perpetual right to control the
<quote>copy
</quote> of
4740 books that they had acquired from authors. That perpetual right meant
4742 <!-- PAGE BREAK 97 -->
4743 one else could publish copies of a book to which they held the
4744 copyright. Prices of the classics were thus kept high; competition to
4745 produce better or cheaper editions was eliminated.
4747 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
4748 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
4749 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>renewability of
</secondary></indexterm>
4750 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
4752 Now, there's something puzzling about the year
1774 to anyone who
4753 knows a little about copyright law. The better-known year in the
4754 history of copyright is
1710, the year that the British Parliament
4755 adopted the first
<quote>copyright
</quote> act. Known as the Statute of Anne, the
4756 act stated that all published works would get a copyright term of
4757 fourteen years, renewable once if the author was alive, and that all
4758 works already published by
1710 would get a single term of twenty-one
4759 additional years.
<footnote><para>
4761 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
4762 As Siva Vaidhyanathan nicely argues, it is erroneous to call this a
4763 <quote>copyright law.
</quote> See Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
40.
4764 </para></footnote> Under this law,
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> should have been
4765 free in
1731. So why was there any issue about it still being under
4766 Tonson's control in
1774?
4768 <indexterm startref='idxromeoandjulietshakespeare' class='endofrange'
/>
4769 <indexterm startref='idxtonsonjacob' class='endofrange'
/>
4770 <indexterm id='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>common vs. positive
</secondary></indexterm>
4771 <indexterm><primary>positive law
</primary></indexterm>
4772 <indexterm><primary>Licensing Act (
1662)
</primary></indexterm>
4774 The reason is that the English hadn't yet agreed on what a
<quote>copyright
</quote>
4775 was
—indeed, no one had. At the time the English passed the
4776 Statute of Anne, there was no other legislation governing copyrights.
4777 The last law regulating publishers, the Licensing Act of
1662, had
4778 expired in
1695. That law gave publishers a monopoly over publishing,
4779 as a way to make it easier for the Crown to control what was
4780 published. But after it expired, there was no positive law that said
4781 that the publishers, or
<quote>Stationers,
</quote> had an exclusive right to print
4784 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof2' class='endofrange'
/>
4785 <indexterm><primary>common law
</primary></indexterm>
4787 There was no
<emphasis>positive
</emphasis> law, but that didn't mean
4788 that there was no law. The Anglo-American legal tradition looks to
4789 both the words of legislatures and the words of judges to know the
4790 rules that are to govern how people are to behave. We call the words
4791 from legislatures
<quote>positive law.
</quote> We call the words from judges
4792 <quote>common law.
</quote> The common law sets the background against which
4793 legislatures legislate; the legislature, ordinarily, can trump that
4794 background only if it passes a law to displace it. And so the real
4795 question after the licensing statutes had expired was whether the
4796 common law protected a copyright, independent of any positive law.
4798 <indexterm startref='idxlawcommonvspositive' class='endofrange'
/>
4799 <indexterm><primary>Conger
</primary></indexterm>
4800 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament' class='startofrange'
><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
4801 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers
</primary></indexterm>
4802 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne' class='startofrange'
><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
4804 This question was important to the publishers, or
<quote>booksellers,
</quote> as
4805 they were called, because there was growing competition from foreign
4806 publishers. The Scottish, in particular, were increasingly publishing
4807 and exporting books to England. That competition reduced the profits
4809 <!-- PAGE BREAK 98 -->
4810 of the Conger, which reacted by demanding that Parliament pass a law
4811 to again give them exclusive control over publishing. That demand
4813 resulted in the Statute of Anne.
4815 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>as narrow monopoly right
</secondary></indexterm>
4817 The Statute of Anne granted the author or
<quote>proprietor
</quote> of a book an
4818 exclusive right to print that book. In an important limitation,
4819 however, and to the horror of the booksellers, the law gave the
4820 bookseller that right for a limited term. At the end of that term, the
4821 copyright
<quote>expired,
</quote> and the work would then be free and could be
4822 published by anyone. Or so the legislature is thought to have
4825 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne' class='endofrange'
/>
4827 Now, the thing to puzzle about for a moment is this: Why would
4828 Parliament limit the exclusive right? Not why would they limit it to
4829 the particular limit they set, but why would they limit the right
4830 <emphasis>at all?
</emphasis>
4832 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament' class='endofrange'
/>
4833 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
4834 <indexterm><primary>Romeo and Juliet (Shakespeare)
</primary></indexterm>
4836 For the booksellers, and the authors whom they represented, had a very
4837 strong claim. Take
<citetitle>Romeo and Juliet
</citetitle> as an example: That play
4838 was written by Shakespeare. It was his genius that brought it into the
4839 world. He didn't take anybody's property when he created this play
4840 (that's a controversial claim, but never mind), and by his creating
4841 this play, he didn't make it any harder for others to craft a play. So
4842 why is it that the law would ever allow someone else to come along and
4843 take Shakespeare's play without his, or his estate's, permission? What
4844 reason is there to allow someone else to
<quote>steal
</quote> Shakespeare's work?
4846 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
4848 The answer comes in two parts. We first need to see something special
4849 about the notion of
<quote>copyright
</quote> that existed at the time of the
4850 Statute of Anne. Second, we have to see something important about
4851 <quote>booksellers.
</quote>
4853 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to
</secondary></indexterm>
4855 First, about copyright. In the last three hundred years, we have come
4856 to apply the concept of
<quote>copyright
</quote> ever more broadly. But in
1710, it
4857 wasn't so much a concept as it was a very particular right. The
4858 copyright was born as a very specific set of restrictions: It forbade
4859 others from reprinting a book. In
1710, the
<quote>copy-right
</quote> was a right
4860 to use a particular machine to replicate a particular work. It did not
4861 go beyond that very narrow right. It did not control any more
4863 <!-- PAGE BREAK 99 -->
4864 a work could be
<emphasis>used
</emphasis>. Today the right includes a
4865 large collection of restrictions on the freedom of others: It grants
4866 the author the exclusive right to copy, the exclusive right to
4867 distribute, the exclusive right to perform, and so on.
4869 <indexterm><primary>Branagh, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
4870 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
4872 So, for example, even if the copyright to Shakespeare's works were
4873 perpetual, all that would have meant under the original meaning of the
4874 term was that no one could reprint Shakespeare's work without the
4875 permission of the Shakespeare estate. It would not have controlled
4876 anything, for example, about how the work could be performed, whether
4877 the work could be translated, or whether Kenneth Branagh would be
4878 allowed to make his films. The
<quote>copy-right
</quote> was only an exclusive
4879 right to print
—no less, of course, but also no more.
4881 <indexterm><primary>Henry VIII, King of England
</primary></indexterm>
4882 <indexterm id='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='startofrange'
><primary>monopoly, copyright as
</primary></indexterm>
4883 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Monopolies (
1656)
</primary></indexterm>
4885 Even that limited right was viewed with skepticism by the British.
4886 They had had a long and ugly experience with
<quote>exclusive rights,
</quote>
4887 especially
<quote>exclusive rights
</quote> granted by the Crown. The English had
4888 fought a civil war in part about the Crown's practice of handing out
4889 monopolies
—especially monopolies for works that already
4890 existed. King Henry VIII granted a patent to print the Bible and a
4891 monopoly to Darcy to print playing cards. The English Parliament began
4892 to fight back against this power of the Crown. In
1656, it passed the
4893 Statute of Monopolies, limiting monopolies to patents for new
4894 inventions. And by
1710, Parliament was eager to deal with the growing
4895 monopoly in publishing.
4898 Thus the
<quote>copy-right,
</quote> when viewed as a monopoly right, was naturally
4899 viewed as a right that should be limited. (However convincing the
4900 claim that
<quote>it's my property, and I should have it forever,
</quote> try
4901 sounding convincing when uttering,
<quote>It's my monopoly, and I should
4902 have it forever.
</quote>) The state would protect the exclusive right, but
4903 only so long as it benefited society. The British saw the harms from
4904 specialinterest favors; they passed a law to stop them.
4906 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John
</primary></indexterm>
4907 <indexterm id='idxbooksellersenglish' class='startofrange'
><primary>booksellers, English
</primary></indexterm>
4908 <indexterm><primary>Conger
</primary></indexterm>
4909 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
4911 Second, about booksellers. It wasn't just that the copyright was a
4912 monopoly. It was also that it was a monopoly held by the booksellers.
4913 Booksellers sound quaint and harmless to us. They were not viewed
4914 as harmless in seventeenth-century England. Members of the Conger
4915 <!-- PAGE BREAK 100 -->
4917 were increasingly seen as monopolists of the worst
4918 kind
—tools of the Crown's repression, selling the liberty of
4919 England to guarantee themselves a monopoly profit. The attacks against
4920 these monopolists were harsh: Milton described them as
<quote>old patentees
4921 and monopolizers in the trade of book-selling
</quote>; they were
<quote>men who do
4922 not therefore labour in an honest profession to which learning is
4923 indetted.
</quote><footnote><para>
4926 Philip Wittenberg,
<citetitle>The Protection and Marketing of Literary
4927 Property
</citetitle> (New York: J. Messner, Inc.,
1937),
31.
4930 <indexterm><primary>Enlightenment
</primary></indexterm>
4931 <indexterm><primary>knowledge, freedom of
</primary></indexterm>
4933 Many believed the power the booksellers exercised over the spread of
4934 knowledge was harming that spread, just at the time the Enlightenment
4935 was teaching the importance of education and knowledge spread
4936 generally. The idea that knowledge should be free was a hallmark of
4937 the time, and these powerful commercial interests were interfering
4940 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament2' class='startofrange'
><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
4942 To balance this power, Parliament decided to increase competition
4943 among booksellers, and the simplest way to do that was to spread the
4944 wealth of valuable books. Parliament therefore limited the term of
4945 copyrights, and thereby guaranteed that valuable books would become
4946 open to any publisher to publish after a limited time. Thus the setting
4947 of the term for existing works to just twenty-one years was a
4949 to fight the power of the booksellers. The limitation on terms was
4950 an indirect way to assure competition among publishers, and thus the
4951 construction and spread of culture.
4953 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
4954 </primary></indexterm>
4955 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>in perpetuity
</secondary></indexterm>
4957 When
1731 (
1710 +
21) came along, however, the booksellers were
4958 getting anxious. They saw the consequences of more competition, and
4959 like every competitor, they didn't like them. At first booksellers simply
4960 ignored the Statute of Anne, continuing to insist on the perpetual right
4961 to control publication. But in
1735 and
1737, they tried to persuade
4962 Parliament to extend their terms. Twenty-one years was not enough,
4963 they said; they needed more time.
4966 Parliament rejected their requests. As one pamphleteer put it, in
4967 words that echo today,
4971 I see no Reason for granting a further Term now, which will not
4972 hold as well for granting it again and again, as often as the Old
4973 <!-- PAGE BREAK 101 -->
4974 ones Expire; so that should this Bill pass, it will in Effect be
4975 establishing a perpetual Monopoly, a Thing deservedly odious in the
4976 Eye of the Law; it will be a great Cramp to Trade, a Discouragement to
4977 Learning, no Benefit to the Authors, but a general Tax on the Publick;
4978 and all this only to increase the private Gain of the
4979 Booksellers.
<footnote><para>
4981 A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending
4982 in the House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the
4983 Eighth Year of the Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the
4984 Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in
4985 the Authors or Purchasers of such Copies, during the Times therein
4986 mentioned (London,
1735), in Brief Amici Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et
4987 al.,
8,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618).
4991 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne2' class='endofrange'
/>
4992 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity' class='endofrange'
/>
4993 <indexterm><primary>common law
</primary></indexterm>
4994 <indexterm><primary>law
</primary><secondary>common vs. positive
</secondary></indexterm>
4995 <indexterm><primary>positive law
</primary></indexterm>
4997 Having failed in Parliament, the publishers turned to the courts in a
4998 series of cases. Their argument was simple and direct: The Statute of
4999 Anne gave authors certain protections through positive law, but those
5000 protections were not intended as replacements for the common law.
5001 Instead, they were intended simply to supplement the common law.
5002 Under common law, it was already wrong to take another person's
5003 creative
<quote>property
</quote> and use it without his permission. The Statute of
5004 Anne, the booksellers argued, didn't change that. Therefore, just
5005 because the protections of the Statute of Anne expired, that didn't
5006 mean the protections of the common law expired: Under the common law
5007 they had the right to ban the publication of a book, even if its
5008 Statute of Anne copyright had expired. This, they argued, was the only
5009 way to protect authors.
5011 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament2' class='endofrange'
/>
5013 This was a clever argument, and one that had the support of some of
5014 the leading jurists of the day. It also displayed extraordinary
5015 chutzpah. Until then, as law professor Raymond Patterson has put it,
5016 <quote>The publishers
… had as much concern for authors as a cattle
5017 rancher has for cattle.
</quote><footnote><para>
5019 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
5020 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
5021 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<quote>Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use,
</quote> <citetitle>Vanderbilt
5022 Law Review
</citetitle> 40 (
1987):
28. For a wonderfully compelling account, see
5023 Vaidhyanathan,
37–48.
5025 The bookseller didn't care squat for the rights of the author. His
5026 concern was the monopoly profit that the author's work gave.
5028 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='startofrange'
><primary>Donaldson, Alexander
</primary></indexterm>
5029 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
5030 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Scottish publishers
</primary></indexterm>
5032 The booksellers' argument was not accepted without a fight.
5033 The hero of this fight was a Scottish bookseller named Alexander
5034 Donaldson.
<footnote><para>
5036 For a compelling account, see David Saunders,
<citetitle>Authorship and Copyright
</citetitle>
5037 (London: Routledge,
1992),
62–69.
5040 <indexterm id='idxstatuteofanne3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
5041 <indexterm id='idxconger' class='startofrange'
><primary>Conger
</primary></indexterm>
5042 <indexterm><primary>Boswell, James
</primary></indexterm>
5043 <indexterm><primary>Erskine, Andrew
</primary></indexterm>
5045 Donaldson was an outsider to the London Conger. He began his
5046 career in Edinburgh in
1750. The focus of his business was inexpensive
5047 reprints
<quote>of standard works whose copyright term had expired,
</quote> at least
5048 under the Statute of Anne.
<footnote><para>
5050 Mark Rose,
<citetitle>Authors and Owners
</citetitle> (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
5052 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark
</primary></indexterm>
5054 Donaldson's publishing house prospered
5055 <!-- PAGE BREAK 102 -->
5056 and became
<quote>something of a center for literary Scotsmen.
</quote> <quote>[A]mong
5057 them,
</quote> Professor Mark Rose writes, was
<quote>the young James Boswell
5058 who, together with his friend Andrew Erskine, published an anthology
5059 of contemporary Scottish poems with Donaldson.
</quote><footnote><para>
5064 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw' class='startofrange'
><primary>common law
</primary></indexterm>
5066 When the London booksellers tried to shut down Donaldson's shop in
5067 Scotland, he responded by moving his shop to London, where he sold
5068 inexpensive editions
<quote>of the most popular English books, in defiance
5069 of the supposed common law right of Literary
5070 Property.
</quote><footnote><para>
5072 <indexterm><primary>Patterson, Raymond
</primary></indexterm>
5073 Lyman Ray Patterson,
<citetitle>Copyright in Historical Perspective
</citetitle>,
167 (quoting
5076 His books undercut the Conger prices by
30 to
50 percent, and he
5077 rested his right to compete upon the ground that, under the Statute of
5078 Anne, the works he was selling had passed out of protection.
5080 <indexterm startref='idxconger' class='endofrange'
/>
5081 <indexterm id='idxmillarvtaylor' class='startofrange'
><primary>Millar v. Taylor
</primary></indexterm>
5083 The London booksellers quickly brought suit to block
<quote>piracy
</quote> like
5084 Donaldson's. A number of actions were successful against the
<quote>pirates,
</quote>
5085 the most important early victory being
<citetitle>Millar
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Taylor
</citetitle>.
5087 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander' class='endofrange'
/>
5088 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers' class='endofrange'
/>
5089 <indexterm id='idxthomsonjames' class='startofrange'
><primary>Thomson, James
</primary></indexterm>
5090 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>in perpetuity
</secondary></indexterm>
5091 <indexterm><primary>Seasons, The (Thomson)
</primary></indexterm>
5092 <indexterm><primary>Taylor, Robert
</primary></indexterm>
5094 Millar was a bookseller who in
1729 had purchased the rights to James
5095 Thomson's poem
<quote>The Seasons.
</quote> Millar complied with the requirements of
5096 the Statute of Anne, and therefore received the full protection of the
5097 statute. After the term of copyright ended, Robert Taylor began
5098 printing a competing volume. Millar sued, claiming a perpetual common
5099 law right, the Statute of Anne notwithstanding.
<footnote><para>
5101 Howard B. Abrams,
<quote>The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law:
5102 Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright,
</quote> <citetitle>Wayne Law Review
</citetitle> 29
5106 <indexterm id='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Mansfield, William Murray, Lord
</primary></indexterm>
5108 Astonishingly to modern lawyers, one of the greatest judges in English
5109 history, Lord Mansfield, agreed with the booksellers. Whatever
5110 protection the Statute of Anne gave booksellers, it did not, he held,
5111 extinguish any common law right. The question was whether the common
5112 law would protect the author against subsequent
<quote>pirates.
</quote>
5113 Mansfield's answer was yes: The common law would bar Taylor from
5114 reprinting Thomson's poem without Millar's permission. That common law
5115 rule thus effectively gave the booksellers a perpetual right to
5116 control the publication of any book assigned to them.
5118 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw' class='endofrange'
/>
5119 <indexterm startref='idxthomsonjames' class='endofrange'
/>
5120 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity2' class='endofrange'
/>
5121 <indexterm id='idxbritishparliament3' class='startofrange'
><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
5123 Considered as a matter of abstract justice
—reasoning as if
5124 justice were just a matter of logical deduction from first
5125 principles
—Mansfield's conclusion might make some sense. But
5126 what it ignored was the larger issue that Parliament had struggled
5127 with in
1710: How best to limit
5128 <!-- PAGE BREAK 103 -->
5129 the monopoly power of publishers? Parliament's strategy was to offer a
5130 term for existing works that was long enough to buy peace in
1710, but
5131 short enough to assure that culture would pass into competition within
5132 a reasonable period of time. Within twenty-one years, Parliament
5133 believed, Britain would mature from the controlled culture that the
5134 Crown coveted to the free culture that we inherited.
5136 <indexterm startref='idxmansfieldwilliammurraylord2' class='endofrange'
/>
5137 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Donaldson, Alexander
</primary></indexterm>
5138 <indexterm id='idxscottishpublishers2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Scottish publishers
</primary></indexterm>
5140 The fight to defend the limits of the Statute of Anne was not to end
5141 there, however, and it is here that Donaldson enters the mix.
5143 <indexterm><primary>Thomson, James
</primary></indexterm>
5144 <indexterm><primary>Beckett, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
5145 <indexterm id='idxhouseoflords' class='startofrange'
><primary>House of Lords
</primary></indexterm>
5146 <indexterm id='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='startofrange'
><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>House of Lords vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
5148 Millar died soon after his victory, so his case was not appealed. His
5149 estate sold Thomson's poems to a syndicate of printers that included
5150 Thomas Beckett.
<footnote><para>
5154 Donaldson then released an unauthorized edition
5155 of Thomson's works. Beckett, on the strength of the decision in
<citetitle>Millar
</citetitle>,
5156 got an injunction against Donaldson. Donaldson appealed the case to
5157 the House of Lords, which functioned much like our own Supreme
5158 Court. In February of
1774, that body had the chance to interpret the
5159 meaning of Parliament's limits from sixty years before.
5161 <indexterm startref='idxmillarvtaylor' class='endofrange'
/>
5162 <indexterm startref='idxbritishparliament3' class='endofrange'
/>
5163 <indexterm id='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='startofrange'
><primary>Donaldson v. Beckett
</primary></indexterm>
5164 <indexterm id='idxcommonlaw2' class='startofrange'
><primary>common law
</primary></indexterm>
5166 As few legal cases ever do,
<citetitle>Donaldson
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Beckett
</citetitle> drew an
5167 enormous amount of attention throughout Britain. Donaldson's lawyers
5168 argued that whatever rights may have existed under the common law, the
5169 Statute of Anne terminated those rights. After passage of the Statute
5170 of Anne, the only legal protection for an exclusive right to control
5171 publication came from that statute. Thus, they argued, after the term
5172 specified in the Statute of Anne expired, works that had been
5173 protected by the statute were no longer protected.
5175 <indexterm startref='idxstatuteofanne3' class='endofrange'
/>
5177 The House of Lords was an odd institution. Legal questions were
5178 presented to the House and voted upon first by the
<quote>law lords,
</quote>
5179 members of special legal distinction who functioned much like the
5180 Justices in our Supreme Court. Then, after the law lords voted, the
5181 House of Lords generally voted.
5183 <indexterm startref='idxsupremecourtushouseoflordsvs' class='endofrange'
/>
5184 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>in perpetuity
</secondary></indexterm>
5185 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of
</secondary></indexterm>
5187 The reports about the law lords' votes are mixed. On some counts,
5188 it looks as if perpetual copyright prevailed. But there is no ambiguity
5189 <!-- PAGE BREAK 104 -->
5190 about how the House of Lords voted as whole. By a two-to-one majority
5191 (
22 to
11) they voted to reject the idea of perpetual copyrights.
5192 Whatever one's understanding of the common law, now a copyright was
5193 fixed for a limited time, after which the work protected by copyright
5194 passed into the public domain.
5196 <indexterm><primary>Bacon, Francis
</primary></indexterm>
5197 <indexterm><primary>Bunyan, John
</primary></indexterm>
5198 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Samuel
</primary></indexterm>
5199 <indexterm><primary>Milton, John
</primary></indexterm>
5200 <indexterm><primary>Shakespeare, William
</primary></indexterm>
5202 <quote>The public domain.
</quote> Before the case of
<citetitle>Donaldson
</citetitle>
5203 v.
<citetitle>Beckett
</citetitle>, there was no clear idea of a public domain in
5204 England. Before
1774, there was a strong argument that common law
5205 copyrights were perpetual. After
1774, the public domain was
5206 born. For the first time in Anglo-American history, the legal control
5207 over creative works expired, and the greatest works in English
5208 history
—including those of Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson,
5209 and Bunyan
—were free of legal restraint.
5211 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonalexander2' class='endofrange'
/>
5212 <indexterm startref='idxscottishpublishers2' class='endofrange'
/>
5213 <indexterm startref='idxcommonlaw2' class='endofrange'
/>
5214 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity3' class='endofrange'
/>
5215 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainenglishlegalestablishmentof' class='endofrange'
/>
5216 <indexterm><primary>Scottish publishers
</primary></indexterm>
5218 It is hard for us to imagine, but this decision by the House of Lords
5219 fueled an extraordinarily popular and political reaction. In Scotland,
5220 where most of the
<quote>pirate publishers
</quote> did their work, people
5221 celebrated the decision in the streets. As the
<citetitle>Edinburgh Advertiser
</citetitle>
5222 reported,
<quote>No private cause has so much engrossed the attention of the
5223 public, and none has been tried before the House of Lords in the
5224 decision of which so many individuals were interested.
</quote> <quote>Great
5225 rejoicing in Edinburgh upon victory over literary property: bonfires
5226 and illuminations.
</quote><footnote><para>
5231 <indexterm startref='idxhouseoflords' class='endofrange'
/>
5233 In London, however, at least among publishers, the reaction was
5234 equally strong in the opposite direction. The
<citetitle>Morning Chronicle
</citetitle>
5239 By the above decision
… near
200,
000 pounds worth of what was
5240 honestly purchased at public sale, and which was yesterday thought
5241 property is now reduced to nothing. The Booksellers of London and
5242 Westminster, many of whom sold estates and houses to purchase
5243 Copy-right, are in a manner ruined, and those who after many years
5244 industry thought they had acquired a competency to provide for their
5245 families now find themselves without a shilling to devise to their
5246 successors.
<footnote><para>
5252 <indexterm><primary>House of Lords
</primary></indexterm>
5253 <indexterm><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>English legal establishment of
</secondary></indexterm>
5255 <!-- PAGE BREAK 105 -->
5256 <quote>Ruined
</quote> is a bit of an exaggeration. But it is not an exaggeration to
5257 say that the change was profound. The decision of the House of Lords
5258 meant that the booksellers could no longer control how culture in
5259 England would grow and develop. Culture in England was thereafter
5260 <emphasis>free
</emphasis>. Not in the sense that copyrights would not
5261 be respected, for of course, for a limited time after a work was
5262 published, the bookseller had an exclusive right to control the
5263 publication of that book. And not in the sense that books could be
5264 stolen, for even after a copyright expired, you still had to buy the
5265 book from someone. But
<emphasis>free
</emphasis> in the sense that the
5266 culture and its growth would no longer be controlled by a small group
5267 of publishers. As every free market does, this free market of free
5268 culture would grow as the consumers and producers chose. English
5269 culture would develop as the many English readers chose to let it
5270 develop
— chose in the books they bought and wrote; chose in the
5271 memes they repeated and endorsed. Chose in a
<emphasis>competitive
5272 context
</emphasis>, not a context in which the choices about what
5273 culture is available to people and how they get access to it are made
5274 by the few despite the wishes of the many.
5276 <indexterm startref='idxbooksellersenglish' class='endofrange'
/>
5277 <indexterm><primary>British Parliament
</primary></indexterm>
5279 At least, this was the rule in a world where the Parliament is
5280 antimonopoly, resistant to the protectionist pleas of publishers. In a
5281 world where the Parliament is more pliant, free culture would be less
5284 <indexterm startref='idxbooksenglishcopyrightlawdevelopedfor' class='endofrange'
/>
5285 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawdevelopmentof' class='endofrange'
/>
5286 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawenglish' class='endofrange'
/>
5287 <indexterm startref='idxenglandcopyrightlawsdevelopedin' class='endofrange'
/>
5288 <indexterm startref='idxunitedkingdomhistoryofcopyrightlawin' class='endofrange'
/>
5289 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightasnarrowmonopolyright' class='endofrange'
/>
5290 <indexterm startref='idxmonopolycopyrightas' class='endofrange'
/>
5291 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof3' class='endofrange'
/>
5292 <indexterm startref='idxdonaldsonvbeckett' class='endofrange'
/>
5293 <!-- PAGE BREAK 106 -->
5295 <chapter label=
"7" id=
"recorders">
5296 <title>Recorders
</title>
5297 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>fair use and
</secondary></indexterm>
5298 <indexterm id='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'
><primary>documentary film
</primary></indexterm>
5299 <indexterm id='idxelsejon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Else, Jon
</primary></indexterm>
5300 <indexterm id='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>in documentary film
</secondary></indexterm>
5301 <indexterm id='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='startofrange'
><primary>films
</primary><secondary>fair use of copyrighted material in
</secondary></indexterm>
5303 <emphasis role='strong'
>Jon Else
</emphasis> is a filmmaker. He is best
5304 known for his documentaries and has been very successful in spreading
5305 his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher myself, I envy the
5306 loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I met, by
5307 accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.)
5310 Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break,
5311 he told me a story about the freedom to create with film in America
5314 <indexterm id='idxwagnerrichard' class='startofrange'
><primary>Wagner, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
5315 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera
</primary></indexterm>
5317 In
1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring
5318 Cycle. The focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera.
5319 Stagehands are a particularly funny and colorful element of an opera.
5320 During a show, they hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and
5321 in the lighting loft. They make a perfect contrast to the art on the
5324 <indexterm id='idxsimpsonsthe' class='startofrange'
><primary>Simpsons, The
</primary></indexterm>
5326 During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands
5327 playing checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set.
5328 Playing on the television set, while the stagehands played checkers
5329 and the opera company played Wagner, was
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>. As Else judged
5330 <!-- PAGE BREAK 107 -->
5331 it, this touch of cartoon helped capture the flavor of what was special
5334 <indexterm startref='idxwagnerrichard' class='endofrange'
/>
5335 <indexterm><primary>films
</primary><secondary>multiple copyrights associated with
</secondary></indexterm>
5337 Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else
5338 attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>.
5339 For of course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use
5340 copyrighted material you need the permission of the copyright owner,
5341 unless
<quote>fair use
</quote> or some other privilege applies.
5343 <indexterm id='idxgraciefilms' class='startofrange'
><primary>Gracie Films
</primary></indexterm>
5344 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt' class='startofrange'
><primary>Groening, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
5346 Else called
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> creator Matt Groening's office to get permission.
5347 Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image
5348 on a tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt?
5349 Groening was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact
5350 Gracie Films, the company that produces the program.
5352 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='startofrange'
><primary>Fox (film company)
</primary></indexterm>
5354 Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted
5355 to be careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company.
5356 Else called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one
5357 room shot of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission,
5358 Else said. He was just confirming the permission with Fox.
5360 <indexterm startref='idxgraciefilms' class='endofrange'
/>
5362 Then, as Else told me,
<quote>two things happened. First we discovered
5363 … that Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation
—or at
5364 least that someone [at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation.
</quote>
5365 And second, Fox
<quote>wanted ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us
5366 to use this four-point-five seconds of
… entirely unsolicited
5367 <citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> which was in the corner of the shot.
</quote>
5369 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt' class='endofrange'
/>
5370 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany' class='endofrange'
/>
5371 <indexterm id='idxherrerarebecca' class='startofrange'
><primary>Herrera, Rebecca
</primary></indexterm>
5373 Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone
5374 he thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He
5375 explained to her,
<quote>There must be some mistake here.
… We're
5376 asking for your educational rate on this.
</quote> That was the educational
5377 rate, Herrera told Else. A day or so later, Else called again to
5378 confirm what he had been told.
5380 <indexterm><primary>Wagner, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
5382 <quote>I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight,
</quote> he told me.
<quote>Yes, you
5383 have your facts straight,
</quote> she said. It would cost $
10,
000 to use the
5384 clip of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle> in the corner of a shot in a documentary film
5387 <!-- PAGE BREAK 108 -->
5388 Wagner's Ring Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else,
<quote>And
5389 if you quote me, I'll turn you over to our attorneys.
</quote> As an assistant
5390 to Herrera told Else later on,
<quote>They don't give a shit. They just want
5393 <indexterm startref='idxherrerarebecca' class='endofrange'
/>
5394 <indexterm><primary>San Francisco Opera
</primary></indexterm>
5395 <indexterm><primary>Day After Trinity, The
</primary></indexterm>
5397 Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing
5398 on the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce
5399 this reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the
5400 very last minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally
5401 replaced the shot with a clip from another film that he had worked on,
5402 <citetitle>The Day After Trinity
</citetitle>, from ten years before.
5404 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Fox (film company)
</primary></indexterm>
5405 <indexterm id='idxgroeningmatt2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Groening, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
5407 There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the
5408 copyright to
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>. That copyright is their property. To use
5409 that copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of
5410 the copyright owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the
5411 <citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> copyright were one of the uses restricted by the law, then he
5412 would need to get the permission of the copyright owner before he
5413 could use the work in that way. And in a free market, it is the owner
5414 of the copyright who gets to set the price for any use that the law
5415 says the owner gets to control.
5418 For example,
<quote>public performance
</quote> is a use of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle> that the
5419 copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite
5420 episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see
<quote>My
5421 Favorite
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>,
</quote> then you need to get permission from the copyright
5422 owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge
5423 whatever she wants
—$
10 or $
1,
000,
000. That's her right, as set
5427 But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first
5428 thought is
<quote>fair use.
</quote><footnote><para>
5430 For an excellent argument that such use is
<quote>fair use,
</quote> but that
5431 lawyers don't permit recognition that it is
<quote>fair use,
</quote> see Richard
5432 A. Posner with William F. Patry,
<quote>Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the
5433 Wake of
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle></quote> (draft on file with author), University of Chicago
5434 Law School,
5 August
2003.
5436 Else's use of just
4.5 seconds of an indirect shot of a
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>
5437 episode is clearly a fair use of
<citetitle>The Simpsons
</citetitle>—and fair use does
5438 not require the permission of anyone.
5440 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany2' class='endofrange'
/>
5441 <indexterm startref='idxgroeningmatt2' class='endofrange'
/>
5443 <!-- PAGE BREAK 109 -->
5444 So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon
<quote>fair use.
</quote> Here's his reply:
5447 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against
</secondary></indexterm>
5449 The
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what
5450 lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly
5451 relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and
5452 broadcast documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was
<quote>clearly
5453 fair use
</quote> in an absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the
5454 concept in any concrete way. Here's why:
5456 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
5458 <indexterm><primary>Errors and Omissions insurance
</primary></indexterm>
5461 Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy
5462 Errors and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed
5463 <quote>visual cue sheet
</quote> listing the source and licensing status of each
5464 shot in the film. They take a dim view of
<quote>fair use,
</quote> and a claim of
5465 <quote>fair use
</quote> can grind the application process to a halt.
5468 <indexterm id='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='startofrange'
><primary>Fox (film company)
</primary></indexterm>
5469 <indexterm><primary>Groening, Matt
</primary></indexterm>
5470 <indexterm><primary>Lucas, George
</primary></indexterm>
5471 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Star Wars
</citetitle></primary></indexterm>
5474 I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first
5475 place. But I knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of
5476 tracking down and stopping unlicensed
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle> usage, just as George
5477 Lucas had a very high profile litigating
<citetitle>Star Wars
</citetitle> usage. So I decided
5478 to play by the book, thinking that we would be granted free or cheap
5479 license to four seconds of
<citetitle>Simpsons
</citetitle>. As a documentary producer working
5480 to exhaustion on a shoestring, the last thing I wanted was to risk
5481 legal trouble, even nuisance legal trouble, and even to defend a
5486 I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law
5487 School
… who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed
5488 that Fox would
<quote>depose and litigate you to within an inch of your
5489 life,
</quote> regardless of the merits of my claim. He made clear that it
5490 would boil down to who had the bigger legal department and the deeper
5491 pockets, me or them.
5492 <!-- PAGE BREAK 110 -->
5494 <indexterm startref='idxfoxfilmcompany3' class='endofrange'
/>
5498 The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the
5499 project, when we are up against a release deadline and out of
5504 <indexterm startref='idxsimpsonsthe' class='endofrange'
/>
5506 In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore
5507 supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But
5508 in practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of
5509 the law, tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed,
5510 means that the effective fair use for many types of creators is
5511 slight. The law has the right aim; practice has defeated the aim.
5514 This practice shows just how far the law has come from its
5515 eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect
5516 publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has
5517 matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or
5520 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand' class='endofrange'
/>
5521 <indexterm startref='idxdocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'
/>
5522 <indexterm startref='idxelsejon' class='endofrange'
/>
5523 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseindocumentaryfilm' class='endofrange'
/>
5524 <indexterm startref='idxfilmsfairuseofcopyrightedmaterialin' class='endofrange'
/>
5525 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst' class='endofrange'
/>
5526 <!-- PAGE BREAK 111 -->
5528 <chapter label=
"8" id=
"transformers">
5529 <title>Transformers
</title>
5530 <indexterm><primary>Allen, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
5531 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex1' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5532 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary></indexterm>
5534 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1993</emphasis>, Alex Alben was a lawyer
5535 working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an innovative company founded
5536 by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop digital
5537 entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave began
5538 investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in
5539 anticipation of the power of networks.
5541 <indexterm id='idxartistsretrospective' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>retrospective compilations on
</secondary></indexterm>
5542 <indexterm id='idxcdroms' class='startofrange'
><primary>CD-ROMs, film clips used in
</primary></indexterm>
5544 Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by
5545 the emerging market for CD-ROM technology
—not to distribute
5546 film, but to do things with film that otherwise would be very
5547 difficult. In
1993, he launched an initiative to develop a product to
5548 build retrospectives on the work of particular actors. The first actor
5549 chosen was Clint Eastwood. The idea was to showcase all of the work of
5550 Eastwood, with clips from his films and interviews with figures
5551 important to his career.
5554 At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and
5555 as a director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood,
5556 asking him about his career. Because Starwave produced those
5557 interviews, it was free to include them on the CD.
5560 <!-- PAGE BREAK 112 -->
5561 That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so
5562 Starwave wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career:
5563 posters, scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood
5564 made. Most of his career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was
5565 relatively easy to get permission for that content.
5568 Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips.
<quote>Our
5569 goal was that we were going to have a clip from every one of
5570 Eastwood's films,
</quote> Alben told me. It was here that the problem
5571 arose.
<quote>No one had ever really done this before,
</quote> Alben explained.
<quote>No
5572 one had ever tried to do this in the context of an artistic look at an
5573 actor's career.
</quote>
5576 Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave.
5577 Slade asked,
<quote>Well, what will it take?
</quote>
5580 Alben replied,
<quote>Well, we're going to have to clear rights from
5581 everyone who appears in these films, and the music and everything
5582 else that we want to use in these film clips.
</quote> Slade said,
<quote>Great! Go
5583 for it.
</quote><footnote>
5586 Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of
5587 publicity
—rights an artist has to control the commercial
5588 exploitation of his image. But these rights, too, burden
<quote>Rip, Mix,
5589 Burn
</quote> creativity, as this chapter evinces.
5590 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>publicity rights on images of
</secondary></indexterm>
5591 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5595 The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what
5596 clearing those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films
5597 could have a claim to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD-
5598 ROMs had not been specified in the contracts for the actors, so there
5599 was no clear way to know just what Starwave was to do.
5602 I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious
5603 pride in his resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his
5604 tale, Alben recounted just what they did:
5608 So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made
5609 some artistic decisions about what film clips to include
—of
5610 course we were going to use the
<quote>Make my day
</quote> clip from
<citetitle>Dirty
5611 Harry
</citetitle>. But you then need to get the guy on the ground who's wiggling
5612 under the gun and you need to get his permission. And then you have
5613 to decide what you are going to pay him.
5616 <!-- PAGE BREAK 113 -->
5617 We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate
5618 for the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of
5619 less than a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the
5620 rate at the time was about $
600. So we had to identify the
5621 people
—some of them were hard to identify because in Eastwood
5622 movies you can't tell who's the guy crashing through the
5623 glass
—is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And then we just,
5624 we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we just
5625 started calling people.
5628 <indexterm><primary>Sutherland, Donald
</primary></indexterm>
5630 Some actors were glad to help
—Donald Sutherland, for example,
5631 followed up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared.
5632 Others were dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask,
5633 <quote>Hey, can I pay you $
600 or maybe if you were in two films, you
5634 know, $
1,
200?
</quote> And they would say,
<quote>Are you for real? Hey, I'd love
5635 to get $
1,
200.
</quote> And some of course were a bit difficult (estranged
5636 ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and his team had
5637 cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint Eastwood's
5641 It was one
<emphasis>year
</emphasis> later
—<quote>and even then we
5642 weren't sure whether we were totally in the clear.
</quote>
5645 Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and
5646 the only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive
5647 project for the purpose of releasing a retrospective.
5651 Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their
5652 hands and said,
<quote>Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's
5653 the music, there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the
5654 actors.
</quote> But we just broke it down. We just put it into its
5655 constituent parts and said,
<quote>Okay, there's this many actors, this many
5656 directors,
… this many musicians,
</quote> and we just went at it very
5657 systematically and cleared the rights.
5662 <!-- PAGE BREAK 114 -->
5663 And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood
5664 loved it, and it sold very well.
5666 <indexterm><primary>Drucker, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
5668 But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to
5669 take a year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done
5670 this efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped,
<quote>There is
5671 nothing so useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done
5672 at all.
</quote><footnote><para>
5674 U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management,
<citetitle>Seven
5675 Steps to Performance-Based Services Acquisition
</citetitle>, available at
5676 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
22</ulink>.
5678 Did it make sense, I asked Alben, that this is the way a new work
5682 For, as he acknowledged,
<quote>very few
… have the time and resources,
5683 and the will to do this,
</quote> and thus, very few such works would ever be
5684 made. Does it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what
5685 anybody really thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that
5686 you would have to go clear rights for these kinds of clips?
5690 I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie,
5691 he or she gets paid very well.
… And then when
30 seconds of
5692 that performance is used in a new product that is a retrospective
5693 of somebody's career, I don't think that that person
… should be
5694 compensated for that.
5698 Or at least, is this
<emphasis>how
</emphasis> the artist should be
5699 compensated? Would it make sense, I asked, for there to be some kind
5700 of statutory license that someone could pay and be free to make
5701 derivative use of clips like this? Did it really make sense that a
5702 follow-on creator would have to track down every artist, actor,
5703 director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? Wouldn't a
5704 lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process could be
5705 made to be more clean?
5709 Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing
5710 mechanism
—where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't
5711 subject to estranged former spouses
—you'd see a lot more of this
5712 work, because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a
5713 <!-- PAGE BREAK 115 -->
5714 retrospective of someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with
5715 lots of media from that person's career. You'd build in a cost as the
5716 producer of one of these things. You'd build in a cost of paying X
5717 dollars to the talent that performed. But it would be a known
5718 cost. That's the thing that trips everybody up and makes this kind of
5719 product hard to get off the ground. If you knew I have a hundred
5720 minutes of film in this product and it's going to cost me X, then you
5721 build your budget around it, and you can get investments and
5722 everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say,
<quote>Oh, I
5723 want a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going
5724 to cost me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for
5725 money,
</quote> then it becomes difficult to put one of these things together.
5729 Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the
5730 richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access
5731 that the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a
5732 year, how long would it take someone else? And how much creativity is
5733 never made just because the costs of clearing the rights are so high?
5735 <indexterm startref='idxcdroms' class='endofrange'
/>
5736 <indexterm startref='idxartistsretrospective' class='endofrange'
/>
5738 These costs are the burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a
5739 Republican hat for a moment, and get angry for a bit. The government
5740 defines the scope of these rights, and the scope defined determines
5741 how much it's going to cost to negotiate them. (Remember the idea that
5742 land runs to the heavens, and imagine the pilot purchasing flythrough
5743 rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles to San Francisco.)
5744 These rights might well have once made sense; but as circumstances
5745 change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a well-trained,
5746 regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and ask,
5747 <quote>Does this still make sense?
</quote>
5749 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex1' class='endofrange'
/>
5751 I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only
5752 a few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California.
5753 The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I
5754 was asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer
5756 <!-- PAGE BREAK 116 -->
5757 from an L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a
5758 friend, Robert Fairbank, had produced.
5761 The video was a brilliant collage of film from every period in the
5762 twentieth century, all framed around the idea of a
<citetitle>60 Minutes
</citetitle> episode.
5763 The execution was perfect, down to the sixty-minute stopwatch. The
5764 judges loved every minute of it.
5766 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, David
</primary></indexterm>
5768 When the lights came up, I looked over to my copanelist, David
5769 Nimmer, perhaps the leading copyright scholar and practitioner in the
5770 nation. He had an astonished look on his face, as he peered across the
5771 room of over
250 well-entertained judges. Taking an ominous tone, he
5772 began his talk with a question:
<quote>Do you know how many federal laws
5773 were just violated in this room?
</quote>
5776 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
5777 <indexterm><primary>Boies, David
</primary></indexterm>
5778 <indexterm><primary>Court of Appeals
</primary><secondary>Ninth Circuit
</secondary></indexterm>
5779 <indexterm><primary>Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals
</primary></indexterm>
5780 <indexterm><primary>Napster
</primary></indexterm>
5781 For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this
5782 film hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the
5783 rights to these clips; technically, what they had done violated the
5784 law. Of course, it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be
5785 prosecuted for this violation (the presence of
250 judges and a gaggle
5786 of federal marshals notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an
5787 important point: A year before anyone would have heard of the word
5788 Napster, and two years before another member of our panel, David
5789 Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals,
5790 Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that the law would not be
5791 friendly to the capacities that this technology would
5792 enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you
5793 couldn't easily do them legally.
5796 We live in a
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> culture enabled by technology. Anyone
5797 building a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut
5798 and paste architecture of the Internet created
—in a second you can
5799 find just about any image you want; in another second, you can have it
5800 planted in your presentation.
5802 <indexterm><primary>Camp Chaos
</primary></indexterm>
5804 But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and
5805 <!-- PAGE BREAK 117 -->
5806 its archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound
5807 never before imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of
5808 clips on computers around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden
5809 takes images of politicians and blends them with music to create
5810 biting political commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced
5811 some of the most biting criticism of the record industry that there is
5812 through the mixing of Flash! and music.
5815 All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators
5816 wanted to be
<quote>legal,
</quote> the cost of complying with the law is impossibly
5817 high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is
5818 never made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the
5819 clearance rules, it doesn't get released.
5822 To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of
5823 rights so that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add
5824 or mix as they see fit. We could even make this change without
5825 necessarily requiring that the
<quote>free
</quote> use be free as in
<quote>free beer.
</quote>
5826 Instead, the system could simply make it easy for follow-on creators
5827 to compensate artists without requiring an army of lawyers to come
5828 along: a rule, for example, that says
<quote>the royalty owed the copyright
5829 owner of an unregistered work for the derivative reuse of his work
5830 will be a flat
1 percent of net revenues, to be held in escrow for the
5831 copyright owner.
</quote> Under this rule, the copyright owner could benefit
5832 from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full
5833 property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he
5837 Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be
5838 for objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made;
5839 which if made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists.
5840 What reason would anyone have to oppose it?
5843 <emphasis role='strong'
>In February
2003</emphasis>, DreamWorks
5844 studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, the comic genius of
5845 <citetitle>Saturday Night Live
</citetitle> and
5846 <!-- PAGE BREAK 118 -->
5847 Austin Powers. According to the announcement, Myers and Dream-Works
5848 would work together to form a
<quote>unique filmmaking pact.
</quote> Under the
5849 agreement, DreamWorks
<quote>will acquire the rights to existing motion
5850 picture hits and classics, write new storylines and
—with the use
5851 of stateof-the-art digital technology
—insert Myers and other
5852 actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece of
5853 entertainment.
</quote>
5856 The announcement called this
<quote>film sampling.
</quote> As Myers explained,
5857 <quote>Film Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing
5858 films and allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap
5859 artists have been doing this for years with music and now we are able
5860 to take that same concept and apply it to film.
</quote> Steven Spielberg is
5861 quoted as saying,
<quote>If anyone can create a way to bring old films to
5862 new audiences, it is Mike.
</quote>
5865 Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if
5866 you don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point
5867 about this announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage
5868 remains under copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks
5869 announcement is just this: It is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is
5870 free to sample. Any general freedom to build upon the film archive of
5871 our culture, a freedom in other contexts presumed for us all, is now a
5872 privilege reserved for the funny and famous
—and presumably rich.
5875 This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first
5876 continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of
<quote>fair use.
</quote>
5877 Much of
<quote>sampling
</quote> should be considered
<quote>fair use.
</quote> But few would
5878 rely upon so weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason
5879 that the privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the
5880 legal rights for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high.
5881 These costs mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to
5882 defend your fair use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions
5883 so you don't have to rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative
5884 process is a process of paying lawyers
—again a privilege, or perhaps a
5885 curse, reserved for the few.
5887 <!-- PAGE BREAK 119 -->
5889 <chapter label=
"9" id=
"collectors">
5890 <title>Collectors
</title>
5891 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital1' class='startofrange'
><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
5892 <indexterm><primary>bots
</primary></indexterm>
5894 <emphasis role='strong'
>In April
1996</emphasis>, millions of
5895 <quote>bots
</quote>—computer codes designed to
5896 <quote>spider,
</quote> or automatically search the Internet and copy
5897 content
—began running across the Net. Page by page, these bots
5898 copied Internet-based information onto a small set of computers
5899 located in a basement in San Francisco's Presidio. Once the bots
5900 finished the whole of the Internet, they started again. Over and over
5901 again, once every two months, these bits of code took copies of the
5902 Internet and stored them.
5904 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
5906 By October
2001, the bots had collected more than five years of
5907 copies. And at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the
5908 archive that these copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to
5909 the world. Using a technology called
<quote>the Way Back Machine,
</quote> you could
5910 enter a Web page, and see all of its copies going back to
1996, as
5911 well as when those pages changed.
5913 <indexterm id='idxorwellgeorge' class='startofrange'
><primary>Orwell, George
</primary></indexterm>
5915 This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have
5916 appreciated. In the dystopia described in
<citetitle>1984</citetitle>, old newspapers were
5917 constantly updated to assure that the current view of the world,
5918 approved of by the government, was not contradicted by previous news
5922 <!-- PAGE BREAK 120 -->
5923 Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was
5924 no way ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the
5925 story that was printed on the date published on the paper.
5928 It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today,
5929 there's no way for you to know whether the content you are reading is
5930 the same as the content you read before. The page may seem the same,
5931 but the content could easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's
5932 library
—constantly updated, without any reliable memory.
5934 <indexterm startref='idxorwellgeorge' class='endofrange'
/>
5935 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
5937 Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and
5938 the Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet
5939 was. You have the power to see what you remember. More importantly,
5940 perhaps, you also have the power to find what you don't remember and
5941 what others might prefer you forget.
<footnote><para>
5943 <indexterm><primary>Iraq war
</primary></indexterm>
5944 <indexterm><primary>White House press releases
</primary></indexterm>
5945 The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White
5946 House changes its own press releases without notice. A May
13,
2003,
5947 press release stated,
<quote>Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended.
</quote> That was
5948 later changed, without notice, to
<quote>Major Combat Operations in Iraq
5949 Have Ended.
</quote> E-mail from Brewster Kahle,
1 December
2003.
5952 <indexterm><primary>history, records of
</primary></indexterm>
5954 <emphasis role='strong'
>We take it
</emphasis> for granted that we can
5955 go back to see what we remember reading. Think about newspapers. If
5956 you wanted to study the reaction of your hometown newspaper to the
5957 race riots in Watts in
1965, or to Bull Connor's water cannon in
1963,
5958 you could go to your public library and look at the newspapers. Those
5959 papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they exist in
5960 paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back and
5961 remember
—not just what it is convenient to remember, but
5962 remember something close to the truth.
5965 It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to
5966 repeat it. That's not quite correct. We
<emphasis>all
</emphasis>
5967 forget history. The key is whether we have a way to go back to
5968 rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key is whether an
5969 objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by
5970 collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for
5971 researchers, for grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge.
5974 The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet
5975 Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the
5976 quintessentially transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more
5977 important in forming and reforming society, it becomes more and more
5978 <!-- PAGE BREAK 121 -->
5979 important to maintain in some historical form. It's just bizarre to
5980 think that we have scads of archives of newspapers from tiny towns
5981 around the world, yet there is but one copy of the Internet
—the
5982 one kept by the Internet Archive.
5985 Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very
5986 successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer
5987 researcher. In the
1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business
5988 success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he
5989 launched a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The
5990 Internet Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew
5991 Carnegie of the Internet. By December of
2002, the archive had over
10
5992 billion pages, and it was growing at about a billion pages a month.
5994 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress
</primary></indexterm>
5995 <indexterm><primary>Television Archive
</primary></indexterm>
5996 <indexterm><primary>Vanderbilt University
</primary></indexterm>
5997 <indexterm><primary>Way Back Machine
</primary></indexterm>
5998 <indexterm><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>archival function of
</secondary></indexterm>
5999 <indexterm id='idxnewscoverage2' class='startofrange'
><primary>news coverage
</primary></indexterm>
6001 The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in
6002 human history. At the end of
2002, it held
<quote>two hundred and thirty
6003 terabytes of material
</quote>—and was
<quote>ten times larger than the
6004 Library of Congress.
</quote> And this was just the first of the archives that
6005 Kahle set out to build. In addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has
6006 been constructing the Television Archive. Television, it turns out, is
6007 even more ephemeral than the Internet. While much of twentieth-century
6008 culture was constructed through television, only a tiny proportion of
6009 that culture is available for anyone to see today. Three hours of news
6010 are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt University
—thanks to a
6011 specific exemption in the copyright law. That content is indexed, and
6012 is available to scholars for a very low fee.
<quote>But other than that,
6013 [television] is almost unavailable,
</quote> Kahle told me.
<quote>If you were
6014 Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are
6015 just a graduate student?
</quote> As Kahle put it,
6018 <indexterm><primary>Quayle, Dan
</primary></indexterm>
6019 <indexterm><primary>60 Minutes
</primary></indexterm>
6021 Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown?
6022 Remember that back and forth surreal experience of a politician
6023 interacting with a fictional television character? If you were a
6024 graduate student wanting to study that, and you wanted to get those
6025 original back and forth exchanges between the two, the
6027 <!-- PAGE BREAK 122 -->
6028 <citetitle>60 Minutes
</citetitle> episode that came out after it
… it would be almost
6029 impossible.
… Those materials are almost unfindable.
…
6032 <indexterm><primary>newspapers
</primary><secondary>archives of
</secondary></indexterm>
6034 Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded
6035 in newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is
6036 recorded on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world
6037 where researchers trying to understand the effect of media on
6038 nineteenthcentury America will have an easier time than researchers
6039 trying to understand the effect of media on twentieth-century America?
6042 In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law,
6043 copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in
6044 libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread
6045 of knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around
6046 once the copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the
6049 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress
</primary></indexterm>
6050 <indexterm><primary>films
</primary><secondary>archive of
</secondary></indexterm>
6052 These rules applied to film as well. But in
1915, the Library
6053 of Congress made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so
6054 long as such deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to
6055 borrow back the deposits
—for an unlimited time at no cost. In
6056 1915 alone, there were more than
5,
475 films deposited and
<quote>borrowed
6057 back.
</quote> Thus, when the copyrights to films expire, there is no copy
6058 held by any library. The copy exists
—if it exists at
6059 all
—in the library archive of the film company.
<footnote><para>
6061 Doug Herrick,
<quote>Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at
6062 the Library of Congress,
</quote> <citetitle>Film Library Quarterly
</citetitle> 13 nos.
2–3
6063 (
1980):
5; Anthony Slide,
<citetitle>Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film
6064 Preservation in the United States
</citetitle> (Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland
&
6069 The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts
6070 were originally not copyrighted
—there was no way to capture the
6071 broadcasts, so there was no fear of
<quote>theft.
</quote> But as technology enabled
6072 capturing, broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law
6073 required they make a copy of each broadcast for the work to be
6074 <quote>copyrighted.
</quote> But those copies were simply kept by the
6075 broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the government didn't
6076 demand them. The content of this part of American culture is
6077 practically invisible to anyone who would look.
6079 <indexterm><primary>September
11,
2001, terrorist attacks of
</primary></indexterm>
6081 Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September
11,
2001, he and
6082 <!-- PAGE BREAK 123 -->
6083 his allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty
6084 stations from around the world and hit the Record button. After
6085 September
11, Kahle, working with dozens of others, selected twenty
6086 stations from around the world and, beginning October
11,
2001, made
6087 their coverage during the week of September
11 available free on-line.
6088 Anyone could see how news reports from around the world covered the
6091 <indexterm><primary>Movie Archive
</primary></indexterm>
6092 <indexterm><primary>archive.org
</primary><seealso>Internet Archive
</seealso></indexterm>
6093 <indexterm startref='idxnewscoverage2' class='endofrange'
/>
6094 <indexterm><primary>films
</primary><secondary>archive of
</secondary></indexterm>
6095 <indexterm><primary>Internet Archive
</primary></indexterm>
6096 <indexterm><primary>Duck and Cover film
</primary></indexterm>
6097 <indexterm><primary>ephemeral films
</primary></indexterm>
6098 <indexterm><primary>Prelinger, Rick
</primary></indexterm>
6100 Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose
6101 archive of film includes close to
45,
000 <quote>ephemeral films
</quote> (meaning
6102 films other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted),
6103 Kahle established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize
6104 1,
300 films in this archive and post those films on the Internet to be
6105 downloaded for free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells
6106 copies of these films as stock footage. What he has discovered is that
6107 after he made a significant chunk available for free, his stock
6108 footage sales went up dramatically. People could easily find the
6109 material they wanted to use. Some downloaded that material and made
6110 films on their own. Others purchased copies to enable other films to
6111 be made. Either way, the archive enabled access to this important
6112 part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the
<quote>Duck and Cover
</quote> film
6113 that instructed children how to save themselves in the middle of
6114 nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film in a
6115 few minutes
—for free.
6118 Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we
6119 otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of
6120 what defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The
6121 law doesn't require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be
6122 deposited in an archive by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way
6126 The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access
6127 to this content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to
6128 it. His aim is to ensure competition in access to this important part
6129 of our culture. Not during the commercial life of a bit of creative
6130 property, but during a second life that all creative property
6131 has
—a noncommercial life.
6134 For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit
6135 of creative property goes through different
<quote>lives.
</quote> In its first
6138 <!-- PAGE BREAK 124 -->
6139 creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial
6140 market is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative
6141 property doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that
6142 content, commercial life is extremely important. Without this
6143 commercial market, there would be, many argue, much less creativity.
6146 After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our
6147 tradition has always supported a second life as well. A newspaper
6148 delivers the news every day to the doorsteps of America. The very next
6149 day, it is used to wrap fish or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to
6150 build an archive of knowledge about our history. In this second life,
6151 the content can continue to inform even if that information is no
6154 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
6156 The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print
6157 very quickly (the average today is after about a year
<footnote><para>
6159 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
6160 Dave Barns,
<quote>Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord,
6161 Bar Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business,
</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
6162 5 September
1997, at Metro Lake
1L. Of books published between
1927
6163 and
1946, only
2.2 percent were in print in
2002. R. Anthony Reese,
6164 <quote>The First Sale Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston
6165 College Law Review
</citetitle> 44 (
2003):
593 n.
51.
6166 </para></footnote>). After
6167 it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores without the
6168 copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where many
6169 get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries
6170 are thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely
6171 important to the spread and stability of culture.
6174 Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for
6175 creative property does not hold true with the most important
6176 components of popular culture in the twentieth and twenty-first
6177 centuries. For these
—television, movies, music, radio, the
6178 Internet
—there is no guarantee of a second life. For these sorts
6179 of culture, it is as if we've replaced libraries with Barnes
&
6180 Noble superstores. With this culture, what's accessible is nothing but
6181 what a certain limited market demands. Beyond that, culture
6185 <emphasis role='strong'
>For most of
</emphasis> the twentieth century,
6186 it was economics that made this so. It would have been insanely
6187 expensive to collect and make accessible all television and film and
6188 music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily high. So even
6189 though the law in principle would have restricted the ability of a
6190 Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the
6191 <!-- PAGE BREAK 125 -->
6192 real restriction was economics. The market made it impossibly
6193 difficult to do anything about this ephemeral culture; the law had
6194 little practical effect.
6197 Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is
6198 that for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is
6199 feasible to imagine constructing archives that hold all culture
6200 produced or distributed publicly. Technology makes it possible to
6201 imagine an archive of all books published, and increasingly makes it
6202 possible to imagine an archive of all moving images and sound.
6205 The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined
6206 before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but
6207 we are for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As
6211 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>total number of
</secondary></indexterm>
6213 It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music.
6214 Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of
6215 movies,
… and about one to two million movies [distributed] during
6216 the twentieth century. There are about twenty-six million different
6217 titles of books. All of these would fit on computers that would fit in
6218 this room and be able to be afforded by a small company. So we're at
6219 a turning point in our history. Universal access is the goal. And the
6220 opportunity of leading a different life, based on this, is
6221 … thrilling. It could be one of the things humankind would be most
6222 proud of. Up there with the Library of Alexandria, putting a man on
6223 the moon, and the invention of the printing press.
6226 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
6228 Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only
6229 archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of
6230 libraries or archives could be.
<emphasis>When
</emphasis> the
6231 commercial life of creative property ends, I don't know. But it
6232 does. And whenever it does, Kahle and his archive hint at a world
6233 where this knowledge, and culture, remains perpetually available. Some
6234 will draw upon it to understand it;
6235 <!-- PAGE BREAK 126 -->
6236 some to criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to
6237 re-create the past for the future. These technologies promise
6238 something that had become unimaginable for much of our past
—a
6239 future
<emphasis>for
</emphasis> our past. The technology of digital
6240 arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria real again.
6243 Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an
6244 archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to
6245 call these
<quote>archives,
</quote> as warm as the idea of a
<quote>library
</quote> might seem,
6246 the
<quote>content
</quote> that is collected in these digital spaces is also
6247 someone's
<quote>property.
</quote> And the law of property restricts the freedoms
6248 that Kahle and others would exercise.
6250 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital1' class='endofrange'
/>
6251 <!-- PAGE BREAK 127 -->
6253 <chapter label=
"10" id=
"property-i">
6254 <title><quote>Property
</quote></title>
6255 <indexterm><primary>Johnson, Lyndon
</primary></indexterm>
6256 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.
</primary></indexterm>
6258 <emphasis role='strong'
>Jack Valenti
</emphasis> has been the president
6259 of the Motion Picture Association of America since
1966. He first came
6260 to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's
6261 administration
—literally. The famous picture of Johnson's
6262 swearing-in on Air Force One after the assassination of President
6263 Kennedy has Valenti in the background. In his almost forty years of
6264 running the MPAA, Valenti has established himself as perhaps the most
6265 prominent and effective lobbyist in Washington.
6267 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
6268 <indexterm><primary>Sony Pictures Entertainment
</primary></indexterm>
6269 <indexterm><primary>MGM
</primary></indexterm>
6270 <indexterm><primary>Paramount Pictures
</primary></indexterm>
6271 <indexterm><primary>Twentieth Century Fox
</primary></indexterm>
6272 <indexterm><primary>Universal Pictures
</primary></indexterm>
6273 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
6275 The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture
6276 Association. It was formed in
1922 as a trade association whose goal
6277 was to defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism.
6278 The organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and
6279 distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its
6280 board is made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major
6281 producers and distributors of motion picture and television programs
6282 in the United States: Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM,
6283 Paramount Pictures, Twentieth Century Fox, Universal Studios, and
6287 <!-- PAGE BREAK 128 -->
6288 Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before
6289 him has had as much influence over that organization, or over
6290 Washington. As a Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important
6291 political skill of a Southerner
—the ability to appear simple and
6292 slow while hiding a lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti
6293 plays the simple, humble man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four
6294 books, who finished high school at the age of fifteen and flew more
6295 than fifty combat missions in World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When
6296 Valenti went to Washington, he mastered the city in a quintessentially
6300 In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our
6301 culture depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting
6302 the MPAA rating system, it has probably avoided a great deal of
6303 speech-regulating harm. But there is an aspect to the organization's
6304 mission that is both the most radical and the most important. This is
6305 the organization's effort, epitomized in Valenti's every act, to
6306 redefine the meaning of
<quote>creative property.
</quote>
6309 In
1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy
6314 No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the
6315 counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men
6316 and women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central
6317 theme which animates this entire debate:
<emphasis>Creative property
6318 owners must be accorded the same rights and protection resident in all
6319 other property owners in the nation
</emphasis>. That is the issue.
6320 That is the question. And that is the rostrum on which this entire
6321 hearing and the debates to follow must rest.
<footnote><para>
6323 Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R.
4783, H.R.
6324 4794, H.R.
4808, H.R.
5250, H.R.
5488, and H.R.
5705 Before the
6325 Subcommittee on Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of
6326 Justice of the Committee on the Judiciary of the House of
6327 Representatives,
97th Cong.,
2nd sess. (
1982):
65 (testimony of Jack
6333 The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's
6334 rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The
6335 <quote>central theme
</quote> to which
<quote>reasonable men and women
</quote> will return is
6337 <!-- PAGE BREAK 129 -->
6338 <quote>Creative property owners must be accorded the same rights and
6339 protections resident in all other property owners in the nation.
</quote>
6340 There are no second-class citizens, Valenti might have
6341 continued. There should be no second-class property owners.
6344 This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated
6345 with such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we
6346 use elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more
6347 extreme a claim made by
<emphasis>anyone
</emphasis> who is serious in
6348 this debate than this claim of Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet
6349 and however brilliant, is perhaps the nation's foremost extremist when
6350 it comes to the nature and scope of
<quote>creative property.
</quote> His views
6351 have
<emphasis>no
</emphasis> reasonable connection to our actual legal
6352 tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly
6353 redefined that tradition, at least in Washington.
6356 While
<quote>creative property
</quote> is certainly
<quote>property
</quote> in a nerdy and
6357 precise sense that lawyers are trained to understand,
<footnote><para>
6359 Lawyers speak of
<quote>property
</quote> not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle
6360 of rights that are sometimes associated with a particular
6361 object. Thus, my
<quote>property right
</quote> to my car gives me the right to
6362 exclusive use, but not the right to drive at
150 miles an hour. For
6363 the best effort to connect the ordinary meaning of
<quote>property
</quote> to
6364 <quote>lawyer talk,
</quote> see Bruce Ackerman,
<citetitle>Private Property and the
6365 Constitution
</citetitle> (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1977),
26–27.
6366 </para></footnote> it has never been the case, nor should it be, that
6367 <quote>creative property owners
</quote> have been
<quote>accorded the same rights and
6368 protection resident in all other property owners.
</quote> Indeed, if creative
6369 property owners were given the same rights as all other property
6370 owners, that would effect a radical, and radically undesirable, change
6374 Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for
6375 our tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry
6376 that is instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British
6377 overturned in
1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create,
6378 a powerful few would exercise powerful control over how our creative
6379 culture would develop.
6382 I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you
6383 that, historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is
6384 to convince you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our
6385 history. We have always treated rights in creative property
6386 differently from the rights resident in all other property
6387 owners. They have never been the same. And they should never be the
6388 same, because, however counterintuitive this may seem, to make them
6389 the same would be to
6391 <!-- PAGE BREAK 130 -->
6392 fundamentally weaken the opportunity for new creators to create.
6393 Creativity depends upon the owners of creativity having less than
6397 Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful
6398 of the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric
6399 notwithstanding, in assuring that the new can displace them. No
6400 organization does. No person does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.)
6401 But what's good for the MPAA is not necessarily good for America. A
6402 society that defends the ideals of free culture must preserve
6403 precisely the opportunity for new creativity to threaten the old.
6406 <emphasis role='strong'
>To get
</emphasis> just a hint that there is
6407 something fundamentally wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no
6408 further than the United States Constitution itself.
6411 The framers of our Constitution loved
<quote>property.
</quote> Indeed, so strongly
6412 did they love property that they built into the Constitution an
6413 important requirement. If the government takes your property
—if
6414 it condemns your house, or acquires a slice of land from your
6415 farm
—it is required, under the Fifth Amendment's
<quote>Takings
6416 Clause,
</quote> to pay you
<quote>just compensation
</quote> for that taking. The
6417 Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a certain sense,
6418 sacred. It cannot
<emphasis>ever
</emphasis> be taken from the property
6419 owner unless the government pays for the privilege.
6422 Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what
6423 Valenti calls
<quote>creative property.
</quote> In the clause granting Congress the
6424 power to create
<quote>creative property,
</quote> the Constitution
6425 <emphasis>requires
</emphasis> that after a
<quote>limited time,
</quote> Congress
6426 take back the rights that it has granted and set the
<quote>creative
6427 property
</quote> free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, when
6428 the expiration of a copyright term
<quote>takes
</quote> your copyright and turns it
6429 over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to
6430 pay
<quote>just compensation
</quote> for this
<quote>taking.
</quote> Instead, the same
6431 Constitution that requires compensation for your land
6432 <!-- PAGE BREAK 131 -->
6433 requires that you lose your
<quote>creative property
</quote> right without any
6434 compensation at all.
6437 The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of
6438 property are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to
6439 be treated differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a
6440 change in our tradition when he argues that creative-property owners
6441 should be accorded the same rights as every other property-right
6442 owner. He is effectively arguing for a change in our Constitution
6445 <indexterm id='idxjeffersonthomas' class='startofrange'
><primary>Jefferson, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
6447 Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong.
6448 There was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong.
6449 The Constitution of
1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be
6450 appointed rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral
6451 college to produce a tie between the president and his own vice
6452 president (as it did in
1800). The framers were no doubt
6453 extraordinary, but I would be the first to admit that they made big
6454 mistakes. We have since rejected some of those mistakes; no doubt
6455 there could be others that we should reject as well. So my argument is
6456 not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too.
6459 Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at
6460 least try to understand
<emphasis>why
</emphasis>. Why did the framers,
6461 fanatical property types that they were, reject the claim that
6462 creative property be given the same rights as all other property? Why
6463 did they require that for creative property there must be a public
6466 <indexterm startref='idxjeffersonthomas' class='endofrange'
/>
6469 To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the
6470 history of these
<quote>creative property
</quote> rights, and the control that they
6471 enabled. Once we see clearly how differently these rights have been
6472 defined, we will be in a better position to ask the question that
6473 should be at the core of this war: Not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis>
6474 creative property should be protected, but how. Not
6475 <emphasis>whether
</emphasis> we will enforce the rights the law gives
6476 to creative-property owners, but what the particular mix of rights
6477 ought to be. Not
<emphasis>whether
</emphasis> artists should be paid,
6478 but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need
6479 also control how culture develops.
6481 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='startofrange'
><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>four modalities of constraint on
</secondary></indexterm>
6482 <indexterm id='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>regulation
</primary><secondary>four modalities of
</secondary></indexterm>
6483 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>as ex post regulation modality
</secondary></indexterm>
6484 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>as constraint modality
</secondary></indexterm>
6487 <!-- PAGE BREAK 132 -->
6488 To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about
6489 how property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way
6490 than the narrow language of the law allows. In
<citetitle>Code and Other Laws of
6491 Cyberspace
</citetitle>, I used a simple model to capture this more general
6492 perspective. For any particular right or regulation, this model asks
6493 how four different modalities of regulation interact to support or
6494 weaken the right or regulation. I represented it with this diagram:
6496 <figure id=
"fig-1331">
6498 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.svg" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
6500 <indexterm><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
6502 At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or
6503 group that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In
6504 each case throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as
6505 a right. For simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.)
6506 The ovals represent four ways in which the individual or group might
6507 be regulated
— either constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law
6508 is the most obvious constraint (to lawyers, at least). It constrains
6509 by threatening punishments after the fact if the rules set in advance
6510 are violated. So if, for example, you willfully infringe Madonna's
6511 copyright by copying a song from her latest CD and posting it on the
6512 Web, you can be punished
6513 <!-- PAGE BREAK 133 -->
6514 with a $
150,
000 fine. The fine is an ex post punishment for violating
6515 an ex ante rule. It is imposed by the state.
6516 <indexterm><primary>Madonna
</primary></indexterm>
6518 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6520 Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an
6521 individual for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is
6522 imposed by a community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be
6523 no law against spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished
6524 if you spit on the ground while standing in line at a movie. The
6525 punishment might not be harsh, though depending upon the community, it
6526 could easily be more harsh than many of the punishments imposed by the
6527 state. The mark of the difference is not the severity of the rule, but
6528 the source of the enforcement.
6530 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints' class='startofrange'
><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6532 The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected
6533 through conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you
6534 do N. These constraints are obviously not independent of law or
6535 norms
—it is property law that defines what must be bought if it
6536 is to be taken legally; it is norms that say what is appropriately
6537 sold. But given a set of norms, and a background of property and
6538 contract law, the market imposes a simultaneous constraint upon how an
6539 individual or group might behave.
6541 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6543 Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously,
6544 <quote>architecture
</quote>—the physical world as one finds it
—is a
6545 constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability
6546 to get across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of
6547 a community to integrate its social life. As with the market,
6548 architecture does not effect its constraint through ex post
6549 punishments. Instead, also as with the market, architecture effects
6550 its constraint through simultaneous conditions. These conditions are
6551 imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, or by police punishing
6552 theft, but by nature, by
<quote>architecture.
</quote> If a
500-pound boulder
6553 blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces this
6554 constraint. If a $
500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight
6555 to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint.
6557 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasexpostregulationmodality' class='endofrange'
/>
6558 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality' class='endofrange'
/>
6559 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints' class='endofrange'
/>
6560 <indexterm id='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>as constraint modality
</secondary></indexterm>
6563 <!-- PAGE BREAK 134 -->
6564 So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is
6565 obvious: They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be
6566 reinforced by another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be
6567 undermined by another.
6570 The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the
6571 effective freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any
6572 particular thing, we have to consider how these four modalities
6573 interact. Whether or not there are other constraints (there may well
6574 be; my claim is not about comprehensiveness), these four are among the
6575 most significant, and any regulator (whether controlling or freeing)
6576 must consider how these four in particular interact.
6578 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6579 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6580 <indexterm><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6581 <indexterm id='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='startofrange'
><primary>driving speed, constraints on
</primary></indexterm>
6582 <indexterm id='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='startofrange'
><primary>speeding, constraints on
</primary></indexterm>
6584 So, for example, consider the
<quote>freedom
</quote> to drive a car at a high
6585 speed. That freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that
6586 say how fast you can drive in particular places at particular
6587 times. It is in part restricted by architecture: speed bumps, for
6588 example, slow most rational drivers; governors in buses, as another
6589 example, set the maximum rate at which the driver can drive. The
6590 freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel efficiency drops as
6591 speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly constrains
6592 speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not constrain
6593 the freedom to speed. Drive at
50 mph by a school in your own
6594 neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The
6595 same norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night.
6598 The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear:
6599 While these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a
6600 special role in affecting the three.
<footnote><para>
6602 By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't
6603 mean to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they
6604 do. Law's only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a
6605 right self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the
6606 other three is more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig,
<citetitle>Code: And
6607 Other Laws of Cyberspace
</citetitle> (New York: Basic Books,
1999):
90–95;
6608 Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>The New Chicago School,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Legal Studies
</citetitle>,
6611 The law, in other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease
6612 the constraint of a particular modality. Thus, the law might be used
6613 to increase taxes on gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to
6614 drive more slowly. The law might be used to mandate more speed bumps,
6615 so as to increase the difficulty of driving rapidly. The law might be
6616 used to fund ads that stigmatize reckless driving. Or the law might be
6617 used to require that other laws be more
6618 <!-- PAGE BREAK 135 -->
6619 strict
—a federal requirement that states decrease the speed
6620 limit, for example
—so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast
6623 <indexterm startref='idxdrivingspeedconstraintson' class='endofrange'
/>
6624 <indexterm startref='idxspeedingconstraintson' class='endofrange'
/>
6625 <figure id=
"fig-1361">
6627 <graphic fileref=
"images/1361.svg" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
6630 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6632 These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To
6633 understand the effective protection of liberty or protection of
6634 property at any particular moment, we must track these changes over
6635 time. A restriction imposed by one modality might be erased by
6636 another. A freedom enabled by one modality might be displaced by
6640 Some people object to this way of talking about
<quote>liberty.
</quote> They object
6641 because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any
6642 particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the
6643 government. For instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people
6644 think it is meaningless to say that one's liberty has been
6645 restrained. A bridge has washed out, and it's harder to get from one
6646 place to another. To talk about this as a loss of freedom, they say,
6647 is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries of ordinary
6648 life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, which
6649 depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue
6650 against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view
6651 of liberty. As I argued in
<citetitle>Code
</citetitle>, we come from a
6652 long tradition of political thought with a broader focus than the
6653 narrow question of what the government did when. John Stuart Mill
6654 defended freedom of speech, for example, from the tyranny of narrow
6655 minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; John Stuart Mill,
6656 <citetitle>On Liberty
</citetitle> (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co.,
6657 1978),
19. John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of
6658 labor from constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons,
<quote>The
6659 Right to Work,
</quote> in Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds.,
6660 <citetitle>John R. Commons: Selected Essays
</citetitle> (London:
6661 Routledge:
1997),
62. The Americans with Disabilities Act increases
6662 the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the
6663 architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those
6664 places easier;
42 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
6665 12101 (
2000). Each of these interventions to change existing
6666 conditions changes the liberty of a particular group. The effect of
6667 those interventions should be accounted for in order to understand the
6668 effective liberty that each of these groups might face.
6669 <indexterm><primary>Americans with Disabilities Act (
1990)
</primary></indexterm>
6670 <indexterm><primary>Commons, John R.
</primary></indexterm>
6671 <indexterm><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6672 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6675 <indexterm startref='idxlawasconstraintmodality2' class='endofrange'
/>
6676 <section id=
"hollywood">
6677 <title>Why Hollywood Is Right
</title>
6678 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on
</secondary></indexterm>
6680 The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just
6681 how, Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress
6682 and the courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that
6683 rallying makes sense.
6686 Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the
6689 <figure id=
"fig-1371">
6691 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.svg" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
6694 <indexterm id='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='startofrange'
><primary>architecture, constraint effected through
</primary></indexterm>
6695 <indexterm><primary>law
</primary><secondary>as constraint modality
</secondary></indexterm>
6696 <indexterm id='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>norms, regulatory influence of
</primary></indexterm>
6698 <!-- PAGE BREAK 136 -->
6699 There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law
6700 limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on
6701 those who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by
6702 technologies that make it hard to copy and share content
6703 (architecture) and expensive to copy and share content
6704 (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by norms we all
6705 recognize
—kids, for example, taping other kids' records. These
6706 uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but the norms
6707 of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with
6708 this form of infringement.
6710 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>copyright regulatory balance lost with
</secondary></indexterm>
6711 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing
</primary><secondary>regulatory balance lost in
</secondary></indexterm>
6712 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
6713 <indexterm><primary>MP3s
</primary></indexterm>
6715 Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and
6716 p2p sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically,
6717 as does the constraint of the market. And as both the market and
6718 architecture relax the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The
6719 happy balance (for the warriors, at least) of life before the Internet
6720 becomes an effective state of anarchy after the Internet.
6722 <indexterm startref='idxarchitectureconstrainteffectedthrough' class='endofrange'
/>
6723 <indexterm startref='idxnormsregulatoryinfluenceof2' class='endofrange'
/>
6724 <indexterm><primary>technology
</primary><secondary>established industries threatened by changes in
</secondary></indexterm>
6726 Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response.
6727 Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this
6728 change, when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance
6729 of protection for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is
6731 <!-- PAGE BREAK 137 -->
6732 after the fall of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the
6733 looting that results.
6735 <figure id=
"fig-1381">
6737 <graphic fileref=
"images/1381.svg" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
6740 <indexterm><primary>Commerce, U.S. Department of
</primary></indexterm>
6741 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='startofrange'
><primary>regulation
</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism
</secondary></indexterm>
6743 Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the
6744 warriors. Indeed, in a
<quote>White Paper
</quote> prepared by the Commerce
6745 Department (one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in
1995,
6746 this mix of regulatory modalities had already been identified and the
6747 strategy to respond already mapped. In response to the changes the
6748 Internet had effected, the White Paper argued (
1) Congress should
6749 strengthen intellectual property law, (
2) businesses should adopt
6750 innovative marketing techniques, (
3) technologists should push to
6751 develop code to protect copyrighted material, and (
4) educators should
6752 educate kids to better protect copyright.
6754 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturefourmodalitiesofconstrainton' class='endofrange'
/>
6755 <indexterm startref='idxregulationfourmodalitiesof' class='endofrange'
/>
6756 <indexterm><primary>farming
</primary></indexterm>
6757 <indexterm><primary>steel industry
</primary></indexterm>
6759 This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed
—if it was to
6760 preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced
6761 by the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content
6762 industry to push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the
6763 happy life you have as an entitlement, and to look to the law to
6764 protect it if something comes along to change that happy
6765 life. Homeowners living in a
6767 <!-- PAGE BREAK 138 -->
6768 flood plain have no hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild
6769 (and rebuild again) when a flood (architecture) wipes away their
6770 property (law). Farmers have no hesitation appealing to the government
6771 to bail them out when a virus (architecture) devastates their
6772 crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to the government to bail
6773 them out when imports (market) wipe out the U.S. steel industry.
6775 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightfourregulatorymodalitieson' class='endofrange'
/>
6776 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightregulatorybalancelostwith' class='endofrange'
/>
6777 <indexterm><primary>Brown, John Seely
</primary></indexterm>
6779 Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's
6780 campaign to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a
6781 technological innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that
6782 the changing technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect
6783 on the content industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely
6784 Brown describes it, its
<quote>architecture of revenue.
</quote>
6786 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
6787 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>advertising on
</secondary></indexterm>
6788 <indexterm><primary>commercials
</primary></indexterm>
6789 <indexterm><primary>camera technology
</primary></indexterm>
6790 <indexterm><primary>digital cameras
</primary></indexterm>
6791 <indexterm><primary>Kodak cameras
</primary></indexterm>
6792 <indexterm><primary>railroad industry
</primary></indexterm>
6793 <indexterm><primary>remote channel changers
</primary></indexterm>
6795 But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it
6796 doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because
6797 technology has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't
6798 follow that the government should intervene to support that old way of
6799 doing business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as
20
6800 percent of their traditional film market to the emerging technologies
6801 of digital cameras.
<footnote><para>
6803 See Geoffrey Smith,
<quote>Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?
</quote>
6804 BusinessWeek online,
2 August
1999, available at
6805 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
23</ulink>. For a more
6806 recent analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana
6807 R. Schoenberger,
<quote>Can Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?
</quote> Forbes.com,
6
6808 October
2003, available at
6809 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
24</ulink>.
6812 Does anyone believe the government should ban digital cameras just to
6813 support Kodak? Highways have weakened the freight business for
6814 railroads. Does anyone think we should ban trucks from roads
6815 <emphasis>for the purpose of
</emphasis> protecting the railroads?
6816 Closer to the subject of this book, remote channel changers have
6817 weakened the
<quote>stickiness
</quote> of television advertising (if a boring
6818 commercial comes on the TV, the remote makes it easy to surf), and it
6819 may well be that this change has weakened the television advertising
6820 market. But does anyone believe we should regulate remotes to
6821 reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by limiting them to function
6822 only once a second, or to switch to only ten channels within an hour?)
6824 <indexterm id='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='startofrange'
><primary>free market, technological changes in
</primary></indexterm>
6825 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid
</primary></indexterm>
6826 <indexterm><primary>FM radio
</primary></indexterm>
6827 <indexterm><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>FM spectrum of
</secondary></indexterm>
6828 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
6829 <indexterm><primary>market competition
</primary></indexterm>
6830 <indexterm><primary>RCA
</primary></indexterm>
6832 The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no.
6833 In a free society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and
6834 free trade, the government's role is not to support one way of doing
6835 <!-- PAGE BREAK 139 -->
6836 business against others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect
6837 them against loss. If the government did this generally, then we would
6838 never have any progress. As Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in
6839 1991, in a memo criticizing software patents,
<quote>established companies
6840 have an interest in excluding future competitors.
</quote><footnote><para>
6842 Fred Warshofsky,
<citetitle>The Patent Wars
</citetitle> (New York: Wiley,
1994),
170–71.
6845 startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and
6846 FM radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight
6847 not only the market but also the government is a world in which
6848 competitors with new ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and
6849 increasingly concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under
6853 Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new
6854 technologies that change the way they do business to look to the
6855 government for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to
6856 guarantee that that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It
6857 is the duty of policy makers, in other words, to assure that the
6858 changes they create, in response to the request of those hurt by
6859 changing technology, are changes that preserve the incentives and
6860 opportunities for innovation and change.
6862 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>First Amendment to
</secondary></indexterm>
6863 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment
</primary></indexterm>
6864 <indexterm><primary>speech, freedom of
</primary><secondary>constitutional guarantee of
</secondary></indexterm>
6866 In the context of laws regulating speech
—which include,
6867 obviously, copyright law
—that duty is even stronger. When the
6868 industry complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to
6869 respond in a way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers
6870 should be especially wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for
6871 the government to get into the business of regulating speech
6872 markets. The risks and dangers of that game are precisely why our
6873 framers created the First Amendment to our Constitution:
<quote>Congress
6874 shall make no law
… abridging the freedom of speech.
</quote> So when
6875 Congress is being asked to pass laws that would
<quote>abridge
</quote> the freedom
6876 of speech, it should ask
— carefully
—whether such
6877 regulation is justified.
6879 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism' class='endofrange'
/>
6880 <indexterm startref='idxfreemarkettechnologicalchangesin' class='endofrange'
/>
6882 My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether
6883 <!-- PAGE BREAK 140 -->
6884 the changes that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are
6885 <quote>justified.
</quote> My argument is about their effect. For before we get to
6886 the question of justification, a hard question that depends a great
6887 deal upon your values, we should first ask whether we understand the
6888 effect of the changes the content industry wants.
6891 Here's the metaphor that will capture the argument to follow.
6893 <indexterm id='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='startofrange'
><primary>Müller, Paul Hermann
</primary></indexterm>
6894 <indexterm id='idxddt' class='startofrange'
><primary>DDT
</primary></indexterm>
6895 <indexterm id='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>insecticide, environmental consequences of
</primary></indexterm>
6896 <indexterm id='idxfarming' class='startofrange'
><primary>farming
</primary></indexterm>
6898 In
1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In
1948, Swiss
6899 chemist Paul Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work
6900 demonstrating the insecticidal properties of DDT. By the
1950s, the
6901 insecticide was widely used around the world to kill disease-carrying
6902 pests. It was also used to increase farm production.
6905 No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop
6906 production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was
6907 important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions.
6909 <indexterm><primary>Carson, Rachel
</primary></indexterm>
6910 <indexterm><primary>Silent Spring (Carson)
</primary></indexterm>
6911 <indexterm id='idxenvironmentalism' class='startofrange'
><primary>environmentalism
</primary></indexterm>
6913 But in
1962, Rachel Carson published
<citetitle>Silent Spring
</citetitle>, which argued that
6914 DDT, whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended
6915 environmental consequences. Birds were losing the ability to
6916 reproduce. Whole chains of the ecology were being destroyed.
6919 No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did
6920 not aim to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems
6921 produced another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than
6922 the problems that were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the
6923 problems DDT caused were worse than the problems it solved, at least
6924 when considering the other, more environmentally friendly ways to
6925 solve the problems that DDT was meant to solve.
6927 <indexterm startref='idxmllerpaulhermann' class='endofrange'
/>
6928 <indexterm><primary>Boyle, James
</primary></indexterm>
6929 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>innovative freedom balanced with fair compensation in
</secondary></indexterm>
6931 It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James
6932 Boyle appeals when he argues that we need an
<quote>environmentalism
</quote> for
6933 culture.
<footnote><para>
6935 See, for example, James Boyle,
<quote>A Politics of Intellectual Property:
6936 Environmentalism for the Net?
</quote> <citetitle>Duke Law Journal
</citetitle> 47 (
1997):
87.
6938 His point, and the point I want to develop in the balance of this
6939 chapter, is not that the aims of copyright are flawed. Or that authors
6940 should not be paid for their work. Or that music should be given away
6941 <quote>for free.
</quote> The point is that some of the ways in which we might
6942 protect authors will have unintended consequences for the cultural
6943 environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And just
6944 <!-- PAGE BREAK 141 -->
6945 as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on
6946 farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations
6947 protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on
6948 authors. It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we
6949 should be aware of our actions' effects on the environment.
6951 <indexterm startref='idxfarming' class='endofrange'
/>
6953 My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly
6954 this effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic
6955 effect on the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But
6956 there should also be little doubt that when you add together the
6957 changes in copyright law over time, plus the change in technology that
6958 the Internet is undergoing just now, the net effect of these changes will
6959 not be only that copyrighted work is effectively protected. Also, and
6960 generally missed, the net effect of this massive increase in protection
6961 will be devastating to the environment for creativity.
6963 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovativefreedombalancedwithfaircompensationin2' class='endofrange'
/>
6965 In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences
6966 for free culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will
6969 <indexterm startref='idxddt' class='endofrange'
/>
6970 <indexterm startref='idxinsecticideenvironmentalconsequencesof' class='endofrange'
/>
6971 <indexterm startref='idxenvironmentalism' class='endofrange'
/>
6973 <section id=
"beginnings">
6974 <title>Beginnings
</title>
6975 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on creative property
</secondary></indexterm>
6976 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='startofrange'
><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in
</secondary></indexterm>
6977 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of
</secondary></indexterm>
6978 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of
</secondary></indexterm>
6979 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
6980 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='startofrange'
><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary>constitutional tradition on
</secondary></indexterm>
6981 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause' class='startofrange'
><primary>Progress Clause
</primary></indexterm>
6982 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
6984 America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved
6985 English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of
<quote>creative
6986 property
</quote> rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English
6987 aim to avoid overly powerful publishers.
6989 <indexterm id='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>in constitutional Progress Clause
</secondary></indexterm>
6991 The power to establish
<quote>creative property
</quote> rights is granted to
6992 Congress in a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very
6993 odd. Article I, section
8, clause
8 of our Constitution states that:
6996 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and
6997 useful Arts, by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors
6998 the exclusive Right to their respective Writings and Discoveries.
7000 <!-- PAGE BREAK 142 -->
7001 We can call this the
<quote>Progress Clause,
</quote> for notice what this clause
7002 does not say. It does not say Congress has the power to grant
7003 <quote>creative property rights.
</quote> It says that Congress has the power
7004 <emphasis>to promote progress
</emphasis>. The grant of power is its
7005 purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching
7006 publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors.
7008 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusinconstitutionalprogressclause' class='endofrange'
/>
7009 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>as protection of creators
</secondary></indexterm>
7010 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>history of American
</secondary></indexterm>
7012 The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw
7013 in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"founders"/>,
7014 the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a few
7015 would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising
7016 disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers
7017 followed the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the
7018 English, the framers reinforced that objective, by requiring that
7019 copyrights extend
<quote>to Authors
</quote> only.
7021 <indexterm><primary>Senate, U.S.
</primary></indexterm>
7022 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>structural checks and balances of
</secondary></indexterm>
7023 <indexterm><primary>electoral college
</primary></indexterm>
7025 The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the
7026 Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers
7027 built structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they
7028 built a structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept
7029 them short. To prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned
7030 the federal government from establishing a church. To prevent
7031 concentrating power in the federal government, they built structures
7032 to reinforce the power of the states
—including the Senate, whose
7033 members were at the time selected by the states, and an electoral
7034 college, also selected by the states, to select the president. In each
7035 case, a
<emphasis>structure
</emphasis> built checks and balances into
7036 the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable
7037 concentrations of power.
7039 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof' class='endofrange'
/>
7040 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause' class='endofrange'
/>
7042 I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call
<quote>copyright
</quote>
7043 today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever
7044 considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our
7045 <quote>copyright
</quote> in context: We need to see how it has changed in the
210
7046 years since they first struck its design.
7048 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionuscopyrightpurposeestablishedin' class='endofrange'
/>
7049 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyconstitutionaltraditionon2' class='endofrange'
/>
7050 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawasprotectionofcreators' class='endofrange'
/>
7051 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>four regulatory modalities on
</secondary></indexterm>
7053 Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes
7054 in technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a
7055 <!-- PAGE BREAK 143 -->
7056 particular concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we
7059 <figure id=
"fig-1441">
7061 <graphic fileref=
"images/1331.svg" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
7066 <figure id=
"fig-1442">
7068 <graphic fileref=
"images/1442.svg" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
7072 <!-- PAGE BREAK 144 -->
7075 <section id=
"lawduration">
7076 <title>Law: Duration
</title>
7077 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
7078 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
7079 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact' class='startofrange'
><primary>Copyright Act (
1790)
</primary></indexterm>
7080 <indexterm><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary>common law protections of
</secondary></indexterm>
7081 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>balance of U.S. content in
</secondary></indexterm>
7083 When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it
7084 faced the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that
7085 the English had confronted in
1774. Many states had passed laws
7086 protecting creative property, and some believed that these laws simply
7087 supplemented common law rights that already protected creative
7088 authorship.
<footnote>
7091 William W. Crosskey,
<citetitle>Politics and the Constitution in the History of
7092 the United States
</citetitle> (London: Cambridge University Press,
1953), vol.
1,
7093 485–86:
<quote>extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme
7094 Law of the Land,'
<emphasis>the perpetual rights which authors had, or
7095 were supposed by some to have, under the Common Law
</emphasis></quote>
7097 <indexterm><primary>Crosskey, William W.
</primary></indexterm>
7099 This meant that there was no guaranteed public domain in the United
7100 States in
1790. If copyrights were protected by the common law, then
7101 there was no simple way to know whether a work published in the United
7102 States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering
7103 uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public
7104 domain to reprint and distribute works.
7106 <indexterm><primary>Statute of Anne (
1710)
</primary></indexterm>
7107 <indexterm id='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>federal vs. state
</secondary></indexterm>
7109 That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting
7110 copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law,
7111 federal protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law
7112 protections. Just as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant
7113 that the copyrights for all English works expired, a federal statute
7114 meant that any state copyrights expired as well.
7116 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>renewability of
</secondary></indexterm>
7118 In
1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a
7119 federal copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If
7120 the author was alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could
7121 opt to renew the copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not
7122 renew the copyright, his work passed into the public domain.
7124 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws5' class='endofrange'
/>
7126 While there were many works created in the United States in the first
7127 ten years of the Republic, only
5 percent of the works were actually
7128 registered under the federal copyright regime. Of all the work created
7129 in the United States both before
1790 and from
1790 through
1800,
95
7130 percent immediately passed into the public domain; the balance would
7131 pass into the pubic domain within twenty-eight years at most, and more
7132 likely within fourteen years.
<footnote><para>
7134 Although
13,
000 titles were published in the United States from
1790
7135 to
1799, only
556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel,
<citetitle>A
7136 History of Book Publishing in the United States
</citetitle>, vol.
1,
<citetitle>The Creation
7137 of an Industry,
1630–1865</citetitle> (New York: Bowker,
1972),
141. Of the
21,
000
7138 imprints recorded before
1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the
7139 1790 act; William J. Maher,
<citetitle>Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension
7140 and the Copyright Law of
1790 in Historical Context
</citetitle>,
7–10 (
2002),
7141 available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
7142 #
25</ulink>. Thus, the overwhelming majority of works fell
7143 immediately into the public domain. Even those works that were
7144 copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, because the term of
7145 copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was fourteen years,
7146 with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen years. Copyright
7147 Act of May
31,
1790, §
1,
1 stat.
124.
</para></footnote>
7149 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact' class='endofrange'
/>
7150 <indexterm startref='idxlawfederalvsstate' class='endofrange'
/>
7152 This system of renewal was a crucial part of the American system
7153 of copyright. It assured that the maximum terms of copyright would be
7154 <!-- PAGE BREAK 145 -->
7155 granted only for works where they were wanted. After the initial term
7156 of fourteen years, if it wasn't worth it to an author to renew his
7157 copyright, then it wasn't worth it to society to insist on the
7161 Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of
7162 copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small
7163 minority of them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the
7164 balance allowed their work to pass into the public
7165 domain.
<footnote><para>
7167 Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For
7168 instance, of the
25,
006 copyrights registered in
1883, only
894 were
7169 renewed in
1910. For a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal
7170 rates, see Barbara A. Ringer,
<quote>Study No.
31: Renewal of Copyright,
</quote>
7171 <citetitle>Studies on Copyright
</citetitle>, vol.
1 (New York: Practicing Law Institute,
7172 1963),
618. For a more recent and comprehensive analysis, see William
7173 M. Landes and Richard A. Posner,
<quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,
</quote>
7174 <citetitle>University of Chicago Law Review
</citetitle> 70 (
2003):
471,
498–501, and
7175 accompanying figures.
</para></footnote>
7177 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainbalanceofuscontentin' class='endofrange'
/>
7178 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
7179 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
7181 Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work
7182 has an actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall
7183 out of print after one year.
<footnote><para>
7185 See Ringer, ch.
9, n.
2.
</para></footnote> When that happens, the
7186 used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the books are
7187 no longer
<emphasis>effectively
</emphasis> controlled by
7188 copyright. The only practical commercial use of the books at that time
7189 is to sell the books as used books; that use
—because it does not
7190 involve publication
—is effectively free.
7192 <indexterm id='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
7193 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by
</secondary></indexterm>
7194 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>term extensions in
</secondary></indexterm>
7196 In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was
7197 changed once. In
1831, the term was increased from a maximum of
28
7198 years to a maximum of
42 by increasing the initial term of copyright
7199 from
14 years to
28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic,
7200 the term increased once again. In
1909, Congress extended the renewal
7201 term of
14 years to
28 years, setting a maximum term of
56 years.
7203 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='startofrange'
><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (
1998)
</primary></indexterm>
7204 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in
</secondary></indexterm>
7206 Then, beginning in
1962, Congress started a practice that has defined
7207 copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress
7208 has extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty
7209 years, Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the
7210 extensions of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years.
7211 In
1976, Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years.
7212 And in
1998, in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress
7213 extended the term of existing and future copyrights by twenty years.
7215 <indexterm><primary>patents
</primary><secondary>in public domain
</secondary></indexterm>
7217 The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing
7218 of works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the
7219 public domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five
7220 years, or
70 percent of the time since
1962. Thus, in the twenty years
7222 <!-- PAGE BREAK 146 -->
7223 after the Sonny Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the
7224 public domain, zero copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue
7225 of the expiration of a copyright term.
7227 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea' class='endofrange'
/>
7229 The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another,
7230 little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the
7231 framers established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright
7232 owner to renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of
7233 renewal meant that works that no longer needed copyright protection
7234 would pass more quickly into the public domain. The works remaining
7235 under protection would be those that had some continuing commercial
7238 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (
1998)
</primary></indexterm>
7239 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>of natural authors vs. corporations
</secondary></indexterm>
7240 <indexterm><primary>corporations
</primary><secondary>copyright terms for
</secondary></indexterm>
7242 The United States abandoned this sensible system in
1976. For
7243 all works created after
1978, there was only one copyright term
—the
7244 maximum term. For
<quote>natural
</quote> authors, that term was life plus fifty
7245 years. For corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in
1992,
7246 Congress abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created
7247 before
1978. All works still under copyright would be accorded the
7248 maximum term then available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term
7249 was ninety-five years.
7252 This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to
7253 assure that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public
7254 domain. And indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is
7255 even possible to put works into the public domain. The public domain
7256 is orphaned by these changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement
7257 that terms be
<quote>limited,
</quote> we have no evidence that anything will limit
7260 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawhistoryofamerican' class='endofrange'
/>
7261 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'
/>
7263 The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is
7264 dramatic. In
1973, more than
85 percent of copyright owners failed to
7265 renew their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright
7266 in
1973 was just
32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal
7267 requirement, the average term of copyright is now the maximum term.
7268 In thirty years, then, the average term has tripled, from
32.2 years to
95
7269 years.
<footnote><para>
7271 These statistics are understated. Between the years
1910 and
1962 (the
7272 first year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never
7273 more than thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and
7274 Posner,
<quote>Indefinitely Renewable Copyright,
</quote> loc. cit.
7277 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof4' class='endofrange'
/>
7278 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightrenewabilityof' class='endofrange'
/>
7279 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusoncopyrightlaws6' class='endofrange'
/>
7280 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby' class='endofrange'
/>
7281 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin' class='endofrange'
/>
7282 <!-- PAGE BREAK 147 -->
7284 <section id=
"lawscope">
7285 <title>Law: Scope
</title>
7286 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>scope of
</secondary></indexterm>
7288 The
<quote>scope
</quote> of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law.
7289 The scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those
7290 changes are not necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent
7291 of the changes if we're to keep this debate in context.
7293 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
7294 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>historical shift in copyright coverage of
</secondary></indexterm>
7296 In
1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only
<quote>maps,
7297 charts, and books.
</quote> That means it didn't cover, for example, music or
7298 architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave
7299 the author the exclusive right to
<quote>publish
</quote> copyrighted works. That
7300 means someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the
7301 work without the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted
7302 by a copyright was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right
7303 did not extend to what lawyers call
<quote>derivative works.
</quote> It would not,
7304 therefore, interfere with the right of someone other than the author to
7305 translate a copyrighted book, or to adapt the story to a different form
7306 (such as a drama based on a published book).
7309 This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright
7310 today are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the
7311 right covers practically any creative work that is reduced to a
7312 tangible form. It covers music as well as architecture, drama as well
7313 as computer programs. It gives the copyright owner of that creative
7314 work not only the exclusive right to
<quote>publish
</quote> the work, but also the
7315 exclusive right of control over any
<quote>copies
</quote> of that work. And most
7316 significant for our purposes here, the right gives the copyright owner
7317 control over not only his or her particular work, but also any
7318 <quote>derivative work
</quote> that might grow out of the original work. In this
7319 way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work
7320 more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way
7321 on the initial creative work.
7323 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>marking of
</secondary></indexterm>
7324 <indexterm id='idxformalities' class='startofrange'
><primary>formalities
</primary></indexterm>
7325 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>registration requirement of
</secondary></indexterm>
7327 At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural
7328 limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the
7329 complete removal of the renewal requirement in
1992. In addition
7330 <!-- PAGE BREAK 148 -->
7331 to the renewal requirement, for most of the history of American
7332 copyright law, there was a requirement that a work be registered
7333 before it could receive the protection of a copyright. There was also
7334 a requirement that any copyrighted work be marked either with that
7335 famous
© or the word
<emphasis>copyright
</emphasis>. And for most
7336 of the history of American copyright law, there was a requirement that
7337 works be deposited with the government before a copyright could be
7340 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkshistoricalshiftincopyrightcoverageof' class='endofrange'
/>
7342 The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible
7343 understanding that for most works, no copyright was required. Again,
7344 in the first ten years of the Republic,
95 percent of works eligible
7345 for copyright were never copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the
7346 norm: Most works apparently didn't need copyright, so registration
7347 narrowed the regulation of the law to the few that did. The same
7348 reasoning justified the requirement that a work be marked as
7349 copyrighted
—that way it was easy to know whether a copyright was
7350 being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure
7351 that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work
7352 somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the
7355 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>European
</secondary></indexterm>
7357 All of these
<quote>formalities
</quote> were abolished in the American system when
7358 we decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement
7359 that you register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is
7360 automatic; the copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with
7361 a
©; and the copyright exists whether or not you actually make a
7362 copy available for others to copy.
7364 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightmarkingof' class='endofrange'
/>
7365 <indexterm startref='idxformalities' class='endofrange'
/>
7366 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawregistrationrequirementof' class='endofrange'
/>
7368 Consider a practical example to understand the scope of these
7371 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightact2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Copyright Act (
1790)
</primary></indexterm>
7373 If, in
1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the
5 percent who
7374 actually copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you
7375 against another publisher's taking your book and republishing it
7376 without your permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers
7377 so as to prevent that kind of unfair competition. In
1790, there were
7378 174 publishers in the United States.
<footnote><para>
7380 See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner,
<quote>Poets, Pirates, and the
7381 Creation of American Literature,
</quote> 29 <citetitle>New York University Journal of
7382 International Law and Politics
</citetitle> 255 (
1997), and James Gilraeth, ed.,
7383 Federal Copyright Records,
1790–1800 (U.S. G.P.O.,
1987).
7386 The Copyright Act was thus a tiny
7387 regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative market in
7388 the United States
—publishers.
7390 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
7391 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7392 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7394 <!-- PAGE BREAK 149 -->
7395 The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem
7396 by hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act
7397 was totally unregulated by the
1790 act. If I took your novel and made
7398 a play based upon it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of
7399 those activities were regulated by the original copyright act. These
7400 creative activities remained free, while the activities of publishers
7403 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightact2' class='endofrange'
/>
7405 Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is
7406 automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail,
7407 every note to your spouse, every doodle,
<emphasis>every
</emphasis>
7408 creative act that's reduced to a tangible form
—all of this is
7409 automatically copyrighted. There is no need to register or mark your
7410 work. The protection follows the creation, not the steps you take to
7414 That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of
7415 fair use exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they
7416 copy it to republish it or to share an excerpt.
7419 That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would
7421 competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of
7422 today that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of
<quote>derivative
7423 rights.
</quote> If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your
7424 book without permission. No one can translate it without permission.
7425 CliffsNotes can't make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All
7426 of these derivative uses of your original work are controlled by the
7427 copyright holder. The copyright, in other words, is now not just an
7429 right to your writings, but an exclusive right to your writings
7430 and a large proportion of the writings inspired by them.
7432 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs3' class='endofrange'
/>
7434 It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our
7435 framers, though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this
7437 was created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower
7439 If I write a book, can you change one word and then claim a
7440 copyright in a new and different book? Obviously that would make a
7441 joke of the copyright, so the law was properly expanded to include
7442 those slight modifications as well as the verbatim original work.
7445 <!-- PAGE BREAK 150 -->
7446 In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power
7447 within a free culture
—at least, it's astonishing when you
7448 understand that the law applies not just to the commercial publisher
7449 but to anyone with a computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating
7450 and selling someone else's work. But whatever
7451 <emphasis>that
</emphasis> wrong is, transforming someone else's work
7452 is a different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at
7453 all
—they believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should
7454 not protect derivative rights at all.
<footnote><para>
7456 Jonathan Zittrain,
<quote>The Copyright Cage,
</quote> <citetitle>Legal
7457 Affairs
</citetitle>, July/August
2003, available at
7458 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
26</ulink>.
7459 <indexterm><primary>Zittrain, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
7461 Whether or not you go that far, it seems
7462 plain that whatever wrong is involved is fundamentally different from
7463 the wrong of direct piracy.
7466 Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I
7467 can go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I
7468 can go to court and get an injunction against your transformative use
7469 of my book.
<footnote><para>
7471 Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument
7472 about the difference that copyright law should draw (from the
7473 perspective of the First Amendment) between mere
<quote>copies
</quote> and
7474 derivative works. See Jed Rubenfeld,
<quote>The Freedom of Imagination:
7475 Copyright's Constitutionality,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law
7476 Journal
</citetitle> 112 (
2002):
1–60 (see especially
7478 <indexterm><primary>Rubenfeld, Jeb
</primary></indexterm>
7480 These two different uses of my creative work are treated the same.
7482 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs3' class='endofrange'
/>
7483 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
7484 <indexterm><primary>Mickey Mouse
</primary></indexterm>
7486 This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should
7487 you be able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from
7488 it without paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature
7489 called
<quote>Mickey Mouse,
</quote> why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse
7490 toys and be the one to trade on the value that Disney originally
7494 These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the
7495 derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower:
7496 simply to make clear that this expansion is a significant change from
7497 the rights originally granted.
7499 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightscopeof' class='endofrange'
/>
7500 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork2' class='endofrange'
/>
7502 <section id=
"lawreach">
7503 <title>Law and Architecture: Reach
</title>
7504 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of
</secondary></indexterm>
7505 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>scope of
</secondary></indexterm>
7507 Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in
7508 copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users,
7509 and authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making
7510 copies, and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.
<footnote><para>
7512 This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law
7513 certainly regulates more than
<quote>copies
</quote>—a public performance of a
7514 copyrighted song, for example, is regulated even though performance
7515 per se doesn't make a copy;
17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
7516 106(
4). And it certainly sometimes doesn't regulate a
<quote>copy
</quote>;
17
7517 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
112(a). But the presumption under the
7518 existing law (which regulates
<quote>copies;
</quote> 17 <citetitle>United States Code
</citetitle>, section
7519 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right.
7522 <indexterm><primary>Valenti, Jack
</primary><secondary>on creative property rights
</secondary></indexterm>
7523 <indexterm id='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>creative property
</primary><secondary>other property rights vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7525 <!-- PAGE BREAK 151 -->
7526 <quote>Copies.
</quote> That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for
7527 <emphasis>copy
</emphasis>right law to regulate. But as with Jack
7528 Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, that
<quote>creative
7529 property
</quote> deserves the
<quote>same rights
</quote> as all other property, it is the
7530 <emphasis>obvious
</emphasis> that we need to be most careful
7531 about. For while it may be obvious that in the world before the
7532 Internet, copies were the obvious trigger for copyright law, upon
7533 reflection, it should be obvious that in the world with the Internet,
7534 copies should
<emphasis>not
</emphasis> be the trigger for copyright
7535 law. More precisely, they should not
<emphasis>always
</emphasis> be
7536 the trigger for copyright law.
7538 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof' class='endofrange'
/>
7540 This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this
7541 very slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the
7542 Internet should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which
7543 the law of copyright automatically applies,
<footnote><para>
7545 Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law
7546 extends, we should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good
7547 argument for its extending where it does, and should not determine its
7548 reach on the basis of arbitrary and automatic changes caused by
7551 because it is clear that the
7552 current reach of copyright was never contemplated, much less chosen,
7553 by the legislators who enacted copyright law.
7555 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawscopeof' class='endofrange'
/>
7556 <indexterm startref='idxcreativepropertyotherpropertyrightsvs2' class='endofrange'
/>
7558 We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely
7561 <figure id=
"fig-1521">
7563 <graphic fileref=
"images/1521.svg" align=
"center" width=
"40%"></graphic>
7565 <indexterm id='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>three types of uses of
</secondary></indexterm>
7566 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of
</secondary></indexterm>
7567 <indexterm id='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>copyright applicability altered by technology of
</secondary></indexterm>
7568 <indexterm id='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='startofrange'
><primary>technology
</primary><secondary>copyright intent altered by
</secondary></indexterm>
7569 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>piracy vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7570 <indexterm id='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='startofrange'
><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>derivative work vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7572 <!-- PAGE BREAK 152 -->
7573 Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent
7574 all its potential
<emphasis>uses
</emphasis>. Most of these uses are
7575 unregulated by copyright law, because the uses don't create a copy. If
7576 you read a book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If you
7577 give someone the book, that act is not regulated by copyright law. If
7578 you resell a book, that act is not regulated (copyright law expressly
7579 states that after the first sale of a book, the copyright owner can
7580 impose no further conditions on the disposition of the book). If you
7581 sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your puppy chew
7582 it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because those
7583 acts do not make a copy.
7585 <figure id=
"fig-1531">
7587 <graphic fileref=
"images/1531.png" align=
"center" width=
"40%"></graphic>
7590 Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated
7591 by copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It
7592 is therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands
7593 at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the
7594 paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see
7595 diagram in figure
<xref xrefstyle=
"template:%n" linkend=
"fig-1541"/>).
7597 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkspiracyvs4' class='endofrange'
/>
7598 <indexterm startref='idxpiracyderivativeworkvs4' class='endofrange'
/>
7599 <indexterm id='idxfairuse' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary></indexterm>
7600 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>fair use and
</secondary></indexterm>
7602 Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses
7603 that remain unregulated because the law considers these
<quote>fair uses.
</quote>
7605 <!-- PAGE BREAK 153 -->
7606 <figure id=
"fig-1541">
7608 <graphic fileref=
"images/1541.svg" align=
"center" width=
"40%"></graphic>
7610 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>First Amendment to
</secondary></indexterm>
7611 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment
</primary></indexterm>
7613 These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law
7614 treats as unregulated because public policy demands that they remain
7615 unregulated. You are free to quote from this book, even in a review
7616 that is quite negative, without my permission, even though that
7617 quoting makes a copy. That copy would ordinarily give the copyright
7618 owner the exclusive right to say whether the copy is allowed or not,
7619 but the law denies the owner any exclusive right over such
<quote>fair uses
</quote>
7620 for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) reasons.
7622 <figure id=
"fig-1542">
7624 <graphic fileref=
"images/1542.svg" align=
"center" width=
"40%"></graphic>
7626 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to
</secondary></indexterm>
7628 <!-- PAGE BREAK 154 -->
7629 In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three
7630 sorts: (
1) unregulated uses, (
2) regulated uses, and (
3) regulated uses that
7631 are nonetheless deemed
<quote>fair
</quote> regardless of the copyright owner's views.
7633 <indexterm startref='idxbooksthreetypesofusesof' class='endofrange'
/>
7634 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
7635 <indexterm id='idxinternetbookson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>books on
</secondary></indexterm>
7636 <indexterm><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on
</secondary></indexterm>
7638 Enter the Internet
—a distributed, digital network where every use
7639 of a copyrighted work produces a copy.
<footnote><para>
7641 I don't mean
<quote>nature
</quote> in the sense that it couldn't be different, but
7642 rather that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks
7643 need not make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network
7644 could be designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number
7647 And because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a
7648 digital network, the scope of category
1 changes dramatically. Uses
7649 that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively
7650 regulated. No longer is there a set of presumptively unregulated uses
7651 that define a freedom associated with a copyrighted work. Instead,
7652 each use is now subject to the copyright, because each use also makes
7653 a copy
—category
1 gets sucked into category
2. And those who
7654 would defend the unregulated uses of copyrighted work must look
7655 exclusively to category
3, fair uses, to bear the burden of this
7658 <indexterm startref='idxfairuse' class='endofrange'
/>
7659 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand2' class='endofrange'
/>
7661 So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the
7662 Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would
7663 be no plausible
<emphasis>copyright
</emphasis>-related argument that
7664 the copyright owner could make to control that use of her
7665 book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about whether you read
7666 the book once, ten times, or every
7667 <!-- PAGE BREAK 155 -->
7668 night before you went to bed. None of those instances of
7669 use
—reading
— could be regulated by copyright law because
7670 none of those uses produced a copy.
7672 <indexterm id='idxebooks' class='startofrange'
><primary>e-books
</primary></indexterm>
7673 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>technological developments and
</secondary></indexterm>
7675 But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different
7676 set of rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book
7677 only once or only once a month, then
<emphasis>copyright
7678 law
</emphasis> would aid the copyright owner in exercising this degree
7679 of control, because of the accidental feature of copyright law that
7680 triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if you read the
7681 book ten times and the license says you may read it only five times,
7682 then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the
7683 fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the
7684 copyright owner's wish.
7686 <figure id=
"fig-1551">
7688 <graphic fileref=
"images/1551.svg" align=
"center" width=
"40%"></graphic>
7691 There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim
7692 just now is not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim
7693 is only to make clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other
7694 points also become clear:
7697 First, making category
1 disappear is not anything any policy maker
7698 ever intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the
7699 presumptively unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no
7700 evidence at all that policy makers had this idea in mind when they
7701 allowed our policy here to shift. Unregulated uses were an important
7702 part of free culture before the Internet.
7704 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>on republishing vs. transformation of original work
</secondary></indexterm>
7706 Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of
7707 transformative uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand
7708 the wrong in commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate
7709 <emphasis>any
</emphasis> transformation you make of creative work
7710 using a machine.
<quote>Copy and paste
</quote> and
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> become
7711 crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others exposes the
7712 tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However
7713 troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it
7714 is extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of
7717 <indexterm id='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>Internet burdens on
</secondary></indexterm>
7718 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>fair use and
</secondary></indexterm>
7719 <indexterm id='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='startofrange'
><primary>derivative works
</primary><secondary>fair use vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
7721 Third, this shift from category
1 to category
2 puts an extraordinary
7723 <!-- PAGE BREAK 156 -->
7724 burden on category
3 (
<quote>fair use
</quote>) that fair use never before had to
7725 bear. If a copyright owner now tried to control how many times I
7726 could read a book on-line, the natural response would be to argue that
7727 this is a violation of my fair use rights. But there has never been
7728 any litigation about whether I have a fair use right to read, because
7729 before the Internet, reading did not trigger the application of
7730 copyright law and hence the need for a fair use defense. The right to
7731 read was effectively protected before because reading was not
7734 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof2' class='endofrange'
/>
7735 <indexterm startref='idxinternetcopyrightapplicabilityalteredbytechnologyof' class='endofrange'
/>
7736 <indexterm startref='idxtechnologycopyrightintentalteredby' class='endofrange'
/>
7737 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworkstechnologicaldevelopmentsand' class='endofrange'
/>
7738 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawonrepublishingvstransformationoforiginalwork3' class='endofrange'
/>
7740 This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for
7741 free culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights
7742 depend upon fair use
—never even addressing the earlier question
7743 about the expansion in effective regulation. A thin protection
7744 grounded in fair use makes sense when the vast majority of uses are
7745 <emphasis>unregulated
</emphasis>. But when everything becomes
7746 presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not
7749 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto' class='endofrange'
/>
7750 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet' class='endofrange'
/>
7751 <indexterm startref='idxinternetbookson2' class='endofrange'
/>
7752 <indexterm startref='idxebooks' class='endofrange'
/>
7753 <indexterm startref='idxfairuseinternetburdenson' class='endofrange'
/>
7754 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawfairuseand3' class='endofrange'
/>
7755 <indexterm startref='idxderivativeworksfairusevs' class='endofrange'
/>
7756 <indexterm id='idxvideopipeline' class='startofrange'
><primary>Video Pipeline
</primary></indexterm>
7757 <indexterm id='idxadvertising' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
7758 <indexterm id='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='startofrange'
><primary>film industry
</primary><secondary>trailer advertisements of
</secondary></indexterm>
7760 The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was
7761 in the business of making
<quote>trailer
</quote> advertisements for movies available
7762 to video stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell
7763 videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put
7764 the trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores.
7766 <indexterm><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
7768 The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in
1997, it began
7769 to think about the Internet as another way to distribute these
7770 previews. The idea was to expand their
<quote>selling by sampling
</quote>
7771 technique by giving on-line stores the same ability to enable
7772 <quote>browsing.
</quote> Just as in a bookstore you can read a few pages of a book
7773 before you buy the book, so, too, you would be able to sample a bit
7774 from the movie on-line before you bought it.
7776 <indexterm id='idxdisneyinc2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Inc.
</primary></indexterm>
7777 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>fair use and
</secondary></indexterm>
7778 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>copies as core issue of
</secondary></indexterm>
7779 <indexterm id='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='startofrange'
><primary>fair use
</primary><secondary>legal intimidation tactics against
</secondary></indexterm>
7781 In
1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors
7782 that it intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet
7783 (rather than sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two
7784 years later, Disney told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video
7785 <!-- PAGE BREAK 157 -->
7786 Pipeline asked Disney to talk about the matter
—he had built a
7787 business on distributing this content as a way to help sell Disney
7788 films; he had customers who depended upon his delivering this
7789 content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video Pipeline stopped the
7790 distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it was within their
7791 <quote>fair use
</quote> rights to distribute the clips as they had. So they filed a
7792 lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in fact
7795 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising' class='endofrange'
/>
7796 <indexterm startref='idxfilmindustrytraileradvertisementsof' class='endofrange'
/>
7797 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>usage restrictions attached to
</secondary></indexterm>
7798 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>willful infringement findings in
</secondary></indexterm>
7799 <indexterm><primary>willful infringement
</primary></indexterm>
7801 Disney countersued
—for $
100 million in damages. Those damages
7802 were predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had
<quote>willfully
7803 infringed
</quote> on Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of
7804 willful infringement, it can award damages not on the basis of the
7805 actual harm to the copyright owner, but on the basis of an amount set
7806 in the statute. Because Video Pipeline had distributed seven hundred
7807 clips of Disney movies to enable video stores to sell copies of those
7808 movies, Disney was now suing Video Pipeline for $
100 million.
7811 Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video
7812 stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be
7813 able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim
7814 in court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were
7815 permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were
7816 not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without
7817 Disney's permission.
7819 <indexterm><primary>first-sale doctrine
</primary></indexterm>
7821 Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts
7822 would consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change
7823 that gives Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't
7824 really control how people got access to their content. Once a video
7825 was in the marketplace, the
<quote>first-sale doctrine
</quote> would free the
7826 seller to use the video as he wished, including showing portions of it
7827 in order to engender sales of the entire movie video. But with the
7828 Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to centralize control over
7829 access to this content. Because each use of the Internet produces a
7830 copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the copyright owner's
7831 control. The technology expands the scope of effective control,
7832 because the technology builds a copy into every transaction.
7834 <indexterm startref='idxvideopipeline' class='endofrange'
/>
7835 <indexterm startref='idxdisneyinc2' class='endofrange'
/>
7836 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawcopiesascoreissueof3' class='endofrange'
/>
7837 <indexterm startref='idxfairuselegalintimidationtacticsagainst2' class='endofrange'
/>
7838 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightusagerestrictionsattachedto2' class='endofrange'
/>
7839 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitswillfulinfringementfindingsin' class='endofrange'
/>
7840 <indexterm><primary>Barnes
& Noble
</primary></indexterm>
7841 <indexterm><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
7842 <indexterm><primary>market competition
</primary></indexterm>
7844 <!-- PAGE BREAK 158 -->
7845 No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for
7846 control is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes
& Noble has the
7847 right to say you can't touch a book in their store; property law gives
7848 them that right. But the market effectively protects against that
7849 abuse. If Barnes
& Noble banned browsing, then consumers would
7850 choose other bookstores. Competition protects against the
7851 extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does not even
7852 question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger when
7853 it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that
7854 authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you
7855 read a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But
7856 in a competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this
7857 happening are quite slight.
7860 Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed
7861 architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of
7862 copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by
7863 balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private
7864 owners choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But
7865 in some contexts it is a recipe for disaster.
7868 <section id=
"lawforce">
7869 <title>Architecture and Law: Force
</title>
7871 The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a
7872 second important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its
7873 significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright
7874 regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced.
7876 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>technology as automatic enforcer of
</secondary></indexterm>
7877 <indexterm><primary>technology
</primary><secondary>copyright enforcement controlled by
</secondary></indexterm>
7879 In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that
7880 controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law.
7881 The law, meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human,
7882 trained in the tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that
7883 tradition embraced, who said whether and how the law would restrict
7886 <indexterm><primary>Casablanca
</primary></indexterm>
7887 <indexterm id='idxmarxbrothers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Marx Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
7888 <indexterm id='idxwarnerbrothers' class='startofrange'
><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
7890 There's a famous story about a battle between the Marx Brothers
7891 and Warner Brothers. The Marxes intended to make a parody of
7892 <!-- PAGE BREAK 159 -->
7893 <citetitle>Casablanca
</citetitle>. Warner Brothers objected. They
7894 wrote a nasty letter to the Marxes, warning them that there would be
7895 serious legal consequences if they went forward with their
7896 plan.
<footnote><para>
7898 See David Lange,
<quote>Recognizing the Public Domain,
</quote> <citetitle>Law and
7899 Contemporary Problems
</citetitle> 44 (
1981):
172–73.
7903 This led the Marx Brothers to respond in kind. They warned
7904 Warner Brothers that the Marx Brothers
<quote>were brothers long before
7905 you were.
</quote><footnote><para>
7907 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
7908 Ibid. See also Vaidhyanathan,
<citetitle>Copyrights and
7909 Copywrongs
</citetitle>,
1–3.
7911 The Marx Brothers therefore owned the word
7912 <citetitle>brothers
</citetitle>, and if Warner Brothers insisted on
7913 trying to control
<citetitle>Casablanca
</citetitle>, then the Marx
7914 Brothers would insist on control over
<citetitle>brothers
</citetitle>.
7917 An absurd and hollow threat, of course, because Warner Brothers,
7918 like the Marx Brothers, knew that no court would ever enforce such a
7919 silly claim. This extremism was irrelevant to the real freedoms anyone
7920 (including Warner Brothers) enjoyed.
7922 <indexterm id='idxbooksoninternet2' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
7924 On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on
7925 the Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a
7926 machine: Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by
7927 the copyright owner, get built into the technology that delivers
7928 copyrighted content. It is code, rather than law, that rules. And the
7929 problem with code regulations is that, unlike law, code has no
7930 shame. Code would not get the humor of the Marx Brothers. The
7931 consequence of that is not at all funny.
7933 <indexterm startref='idxwarnerbrothers' class='endofrange'
/>
7934 <indexterm startref='idxmarxbrothers' class='endofrange'
/>
7936 <indexterm id='idxadobeebookreader' class='startofrange'
><primary>Adobe eBook Reader
</primary></indexterm>
7938 Consider the life of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7941 An e-book is a book delivered in electronic form. An Adobe eBook is
7942 not a book that Adobe has published; Adobe simply produces the
7943 software that publishers use to deliver e-books. It provides the
7944 technology, and the publisher delivers the content by using the
7949 <xref xrefstyle=
"template:%n" linkend=
"fig-example-adobe-ebook-reader"/>
7950 is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook Reader.
7953 As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this
7954 e-book library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the
7955 public domain:
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>, for example, is in
7956 the public domain. Some of them reproduce content that is not in the
7957 public domain: My own book
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>
7958 is not yet within the public domain. Consider
7959 <citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle> first. If you click on my e-book
7961 <!-- PAGE BREAK 160 -->
7962 <citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>, you'll see a fancy cover, and then
7963 a button at the bottom called Permissions.
7965 <figure id=
"fig-example-adobe-ebook-reader">
7967 <graphic fileref=
"images/example-adobe-ebook-reader.png" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
7970 If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the
7971 permissions that the publisher purports to grant with this book.
7973 <figure id=
"fig-1612">
7975 <graphic fileref=
"images/1612.png" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
7978 <!-- PAGE BREAK 161 -->
7979 According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the
7980 clipboard of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far,
7981 I've copied no text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to
7982 print ten pages from the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the
7983 permission to use the Read Aloud button to hear
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle>
7984 read aloud through the computer.
7986 <indexterm><primary>Aristotle
</primary></indexterm>
7987 <indexterm><primary><citetitle>Politics
</citetitle>, (Aristotle)
</primary></indexterm>
7989 Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the
7990 translation): Aristotle's
<citetitle>Politics
</citetitle>.
7992 <figure id=
"fig-1621">
7994 <graphic fileref=
"images/1621.png" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
7997 According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted
7998 at all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear
8001 <figure id=
"fig-1622">
8003 <graphic fileref=
"images/1622.png" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
8005 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)
</primary></indexterm>
8006 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary></indexterm>
8008 Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the
8009 original e-book version of my last book,
<citetitle>The Future of
8012 <!-- PAGE BREAK 162 -->
8013 <figure id=
"fig-1631">
8015 <graphic fileref=
"images/1631.png" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
8018 No copying, no printing, and don't you dare try to listen to this book!
8021 Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls
8022 <quote>permissions
</quote>— as if the publisher has the power to control how
8023 you use these works. For works under copyright, the copyright owner
8024 certainly does have the power
—up to the limits of the copyright
8025 law. But for work not under copyright, there is no such copyright
8026 power.
<footnote><para>
8028 In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might,
8029 for example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I
8030 will read it only three times, or that I promise to read it three
8031 times. But that obligation (and the limits for creating that
8032 obligation) would come from the contract, not from copyright law, and
8033 the obligations of contract would not necessarily pass to anyone who
8034 subsequently acquired the book.
8036 When my e-book of
<citetitle>Middlemarch
</citetitle> says I have the
8037 permission to copy only ten text selections into the memory every ten
8038 days, what that really means is that the eBook Reader has enabled the
8039 publisher to control how I use the book on my computer, far beyond the
8040 control that the law would enable.
8043 The control comes instead from the code
—from the technology
8044 within which the e-book
<quote>lives.
</quote> Though the e-book says that these are
8045 permissions, they are not the sort of
<quote>permissions
</quote> that most of us
8046 deal with. When a teenager gets
<quote>permission
</quote> to stay out till
8047 midnight, she knows (unless she's Cinderella) that she can stay out
8048 till
2 A.M., but will suffer a punishment if she's caught. But when
8049 the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the permission to make ten copies
8050 of the text into the computer's memory, that means that after I've
8051 made ten copies, the computer will not make any more. The same with
8052 the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook Reader will not
8053 print any more pages. It's the same with the silly restriction that
8054 says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my book
8055 aloud
—it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead,
8056 if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply
8059 <indexterm><primary>Marx Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
8060 <indexterm><primary>Warner Brothers
</primary></indexterm>
8062 <!-- PAGE BREAK 163 -->
8063 These are
<emphasis>controls
</emphasis>, not permissions. Imagine a
8064 world where the Marx Brothers sold word processing software that, when
8065 you tried to type
<quote>Warner Brothers,
</quote> erased
<quote>Brothers
</quote> from the
8069 This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright
8070 <emphasis>law
</emphasis> as copyright
<emphasis>code
</emphasis>. The
8071 controls over access to content will not be controls that are ratified
8072 by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls that
8073 are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into
8074 the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are
8075 built into the technology have no similar built-in check.
8078 How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the
8079 controls built into the technology? Software used to be sold with
8080 technologies that limited the ability of users to copy the software,
8081 but those were trivial protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial
8082 to defeat these protections as well?
8085 We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe
8088 <indexterm id='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alice's Adventures in Wonderland (Carroll)
</primary></indexterm>
8089 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>e-book restrictions on
</secondary></indexterm>
8091 Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public
8092 relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free
8093 on the Adobe site was a copy of
<citetitle>Alice's Adventures in
8094 Wonderland
</citetitle>. This wonderful book is in the public
8095 domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that book, you got the
8098 <figure id=
"fig-1641">
8100 <graphic fileref=
"images/1641.png" align=
"center" width=
"50%"></graphic>
8102 <!-- PAGE BREAK 164-->
8104 Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to
8105 copy, not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the
8106 <quote>permissions
</quote> indicated, not allowed to
<quote>read aloud
</quote>!
8109 The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission.
8110 For the text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read
8111 Aloud button; it said you did not have the permission to read the book
8112 aloud. That led some people to think that Adobe was restricting the
8113 right of parents, for example, to read the book to their children, which
8114 seemed, to say the least, absurd.
8117 Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying
8118 to restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only
8119 restricting the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book
8120 read aloud. But the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would
8121 Adobe thus agree that a consumer was free to use software to hack
8122 around the restrictions built into the eBook Reader? If some company
8123 (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to disable the technological
8124 protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a blind person, say,
8125 could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe agree that
8126 such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer because
8127 the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no.
8129 <indexterm startref='idxalicesadventuresinwonderlandcarroll' class='endofrange'
/>
8130 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainebookrestrictionson2' class='endofrange'
/>
8132 The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most
8133 innovative companies developing strategies to balance open access to
8134 content with incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's
8135 technology enables control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this
8136 control. That incentive is understandable, yet what it creates is
8139 <indexterm startref='idxadobeebookreader' class='endofrange'
/>
8140 <indexterm startref='idxbooksoninternet2' class='endofrange'
/>
8142 To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite
8143 story of mine that makes the same point.
8145 <indexterm id='idxaibo1' class='startofrange'
><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8146 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog1' class='startofrange'
><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8147 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo1' class='startofrange'
><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8149 Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named
<quote>Aibo.
</quote> The Aibo
8150 learns tricks, cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity
8151 and that doesn't leave that much of a mess (at least in your house).
8154 The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world
8155 have set up clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web
8156 site to enable information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set
8157 <!-- PAGE BREAK 165-->
8158 up aibopet.com (and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site),
8159 and on that site he provided information about how to teach an Aibo
8160 to do tricks in addition to the ones Sony had taught it.
8163 <quote>Teach
</quote> here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers.
8164 You teach a computer how to do something by programming it
8165 differently. So to say that aibopet.com was giving information about
8166 how to teach the dog to do new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com
8167 was giving information to users of the Aibo pet about how to hack
8168 their computer
<quote>dog
</quote> to make it do new tricks (thus, aibohack.com).
8170 <indexterm><primary>hacks
</primary></indexterm>
8172 If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word
8173 <citetitle>hack
</citetitle> has a particularly unfriendly
8174 connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or weeds. Nonprogrammers in
8175 horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or coders, as I call
8176 them,
<citetitle>hack
</citetitle> is a much more positive
8177 term.
<citetitle>Hack
</citetitle> just means code that enables the
8178 program to do something it wasn't originally intended or enabled to
8179 do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might find the
8180 old computer doesn't run, or
<quote>drive,
</quote> the printer. If you discovered
8181 that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by someone
8182 who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer
8186 Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a
8187 community like to challenge themselves and others with increasingly
8188 difficult tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack
8189 well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack
8193 The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program
8194 and offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to
8195 dance jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever
8196 bit of tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature
8197 than Sony had built.
8199 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo1' class='endofrange'
/>
8200 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog1' class='endofrange'
/>
8201 <indexterm startref='idxaibo1' class='endofrange'
/>
8203 I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the
8204 United States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience,
8205 is it permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We
8206 forget that stories about the backcountry still flow across much of
8209 <!-- PAGE BREAK 166 -->
8210 world. So let's just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime
8211 anywhere (anymore) to dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog
8212 to dance jazz. Nor should it be a crime (though we don't have a lot to
8213 go on here) to teach your robot dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a
8214 completely legal activity. One imagines that the owner of aibopet.com
8215 thought,
<emphasis>What possible problem could there be with teaching
8216 a robot dog to dance?
</emphasis>
8218 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>government case against
</secondary></indexterm>
8220 Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show
—
8221 not literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic
8222 named Ed Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic
8223 is well known and respected. He was hired by the government in the
8224 Microsoft case to test Microsoft's claims about what could and could
8225 not be done with its own code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his
8226 brilliance and his coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft
8227 lawyers, Ed Felten stood his ground. He was not about to be bullied
8228 into being silent about something he knew very well.
8231 But Felten's bravery was really tested in April
2001.
<footnote><para>
8233 See Pamela Samuelson,
<quote>Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science,
</quote>
8234 <citetitle>Science
</citetitle> 293 (
2001):
2028; Brendan I. Koerner,
<quote>Play Dead: Sony Muzzles
8235 the Techies Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks,
</quote> <citetitle>American Prospect
</citetitle>,
8236 January
2002;
<quote>Court Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to
8237 DMCA,
</quote> <citetitle>Intellectual Property Litigation Reporter
</citetitle>,
11 December
2001; Bill
8238 Holland,
<quote>Copyright Act Raising Free-Speech Concerns,
</quote> <citetitle>Billboard
</citetitle>,
8239 May
2001; Janelle Brown,
<quote>Is the RIAA Running Scared?
</quote> Salon.com,
8240 April
2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation,
<quote>Frequently Asked
8241 Questions about
<citetitle>Felten and USENIX
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>RIAA
</citetitle> Legal Case,
</quote> available at
8242 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
27</ulink>.
8243 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation
</primary></indexterm>
8245 He and a group of colleagues were working on a paper to be submitted
8246 at conference. The paper was intended to describe the weakness in an
8247 encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music
8248 Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music.
8251 The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content
8252 owners to exercise much better control over their content than the
8253 Internet, as it originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI
8254 hoped to develop a standard that would allow the content owner to say
8255 <quote>this music cannot be copied,
</quote> and have a computer respect that
8256 command. The technology was to be part of a
<quote>trusted system
</quote> of
8257 control that would get content owners to trust the system of the
8261 When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition.
8262 In exchange for providing contestants with the code to an
8263 SDMI-encrypted bit of content, contestants were to try to crack it
8264 and, if they did, report the problems to the consortium.
8267 <!-- PAGE BREAK 167 -->
8268 Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and
8269 the team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption
8270 systems would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team
8271 thought it worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption.
8274 Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United
8275 States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not
8276 just because it is the law, but also because it is a really great
8277 idea. A strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to
8278 encourage a wide range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in
8279 turn, to improve the systems or people or ideas criticized.
8282 What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper
8283 describing the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free
8284 music, or building and deploying this technology. The paper was an
8285 academic essay, unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the
8286 weakness in the SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently
8287 constituted, succeed.
8289 <indexterm id='idxaibo2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8290 <indexterm id='idxroboticdog2' class='startofrange'
><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8291 <indexterm id='idxsonyaibo2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8293 What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they
8294 then received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the
8295 aibopet.com hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony
8300 Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent
8301 AIBO-ware's copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the
8302 anti-circumvention provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act.
8305 <indexterm startref='idxsonyaibo2' class='endofrange'
/>
8306 <indexterm startref='idxroboticdog2' class='endofrange'
/>
8307 <indexterm startref='idxaibo2' class='endofrange'
/>
8309 And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system
8310 of encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter
8311 from an RIAA lawyer that read:
8315 Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the
8316 <!-- PAGE BREAK 168 -->
8317 Public Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by
8318 the Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions
8319 under the Digital Millennium Copyright Act (
<quote>DMCA
</quote>).
8323 In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the
8324 spread of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made
8325 spreading such information an offense.
8328 The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear
8329 about cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively
8330 dead; the response was to find technologies that might compensate.
8331 These new technologies would be copyright protection
8332 technologies
— technologies to control the replication and
8333 distribution of copyrighted material. They were designed as
8334 <emphasis>code
</emphasis> to modify the original
8335 <emphasis>code
</emphasis> of the Internet, to reestablish some
8336 protection for copyright owners.
8339 The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this
8340 code designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say,
8341 <emphasis>legal code
</emphasis> intended to buttress
8342 <emphasis>software code
</emphasis> which itself was intended to
8343 support the
<emphasis>legal code of copyright
</emphasis>.
8346 But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to
8347 the extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did
8348 not end at the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated
8349 devices that were designed to circumvent copyright protection
8350 measures. It was designed to ban those devices, whether or not the use
8351 of the copyrighted material made possible by that circumvention would
8352 have been a copyright violation.
8354 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8355 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8356 <indexterm><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8358 Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a
8359 copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to
8360 dance jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted
8361 material. But as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did
8362 not enable subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that
8363 aibopet.com's hack was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet
8364 fair use is not a defense to the DMCA. The question is not whether the
8365 <!-- PAGE BREAK 169 -->
8366 use of the copyrighted material was a copyright violation. The question
8367 is whether a copyright protection system was circumvented.
8370 The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the
8371 same line of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a
8372 copyright protection system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer
8373 suggested, Felten himself was distributing a circumvention technology.
8374 Thus, even though he was not himself infringing anyone's copyright,
8375 his academic paper was enabling others to infringe others' copyright.
8377 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
8378 <indexterm id='idxcassettevcrs2' class='startofrange'
><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
8380 The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in
8381 1981 by Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that
8382 the VCR could be banned because it was a copyright-infringing
8383 technology: It enabled consumers to copy films without the permission
8384 of the copyright owner. No doubt there were uses of the technology
8385 that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka
<quote><citetitle>Mr. Rogers
</citetitle>,
</quote>
8386 for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people to feel
8387 free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood.
8388 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8392 Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the
8393 <quote>Neighborhood
</quote> at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that
8394 it's a real service to families to be able to record such programs and
8395 show them at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the
8396 advent of all of this new technology that allows people to tape the
8397 <quote>Neighborhood
</quote> off-the-air, and I'm speaking for the
<quote>Neighborhood
</quote>
8398 because that's what I produce, that they then become much more active
8399 in the programming of their family's television life. Very frankly, I
8400 am opposed to people being programmed by others. My whole approach in
8401 broadcasting has always been
<quote>You are an important person just the way
8402 you are. You can make healthy decisions.
</quote> Maybe I'm going on too long,
8403 but I just feel that anything that allows a person to be more active
8404 in the control of his or her life, in a healthy way, is
8405 important.
<footnote><para>
8407 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
8408 <citetitle>Sony Corporation of America
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Universal City Studios, Inc
</citetitle>.,
464 U.S.
417,
8409 455 fn.
27 (
1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See
8410 James Lardner,
<citetitle>Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of
8411 the VCR
</citetitle> (New York: W. W. Norton,
1987),
270–71.
8412 <indexterm><primary>Rogers, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
8417 <!-- PAGE BREAK 170 -->
8418 Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were
8419 some uses that were illegal, the court held the companies producing
8420 the VCR responsible.
8423 This led Conrad to draw the cartoon in figure
8424 <xref xrefstyle=
"template:%n"
8425 linkend=
"fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/>, which we can adopt to the
8427 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8430 No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close.
8433 The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright
8434 circumvention technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for
8435 different ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive
8436 pirating of copyrighted material
—a bad end. Or they can be used
8437 to enable the use of particular copyrighted materials in ways that
8438 would be considered fair use
—a good end.
8440 <indexterm id='idxhandguns' class='startofrange'
><primary>handguns
</primary></indexterm>
8442 A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most
8443 <!-- PAGE BREAK 171 -->
8444 would agree such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target
8445 practice or to protect against an intruder. At least some would say that
8446 such a use would be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good
8449 <figure id=
"fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig" float=
"1">
8450 <title>— On which item have the courts ruled that manufacturers and
8451 retailers be held responsible for having supplied the
8453 <graphic fileref=
"images/1711.png" align=
"center" width=
"100%"></graphic>
8455 <indexterm><primary>Conrad, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
8457 The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world
8458 where guns are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and
8459 circumvention technologies) are illegal. Flash:
<emphasis>No one ever
8460 died from copyright circumvention
</emphasis>. Yet the law bans circumvention
8461 technologies absolutely, despite the potential that they might do some
8462 good, but permits guns, despite the obvious and tragic harm they do.
8464 <indexterm startref='idxhandguns' class='endofrange'
/>
8465 <indexterm startref='idxcassettevcrs2' class='endofrange'
/>
8466 <indexterm><primary>Aibo robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8467 <indexterm><primary>robotic dog
</primary></indexterm>
8468 <indexterm><primary>Sony
</primary><secondary>Aibo robotic dog produced by
</secondary></indexterm>
8470 The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are
8471 changing the balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright
8472 owners restrict fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would
8473 attempt to evade the restrictions on fair use that they impose through
8474 code. Technology becomes a means by which fair use can be erased; the
8475 law of the DMCA backs up that erasing.
8478 This is how
<emphasis>code
</emphasis> becomes
8479 <emphasis>law
</emphasis>. The controls built into the technology of
8480 copy and access protection become rules the violation of which is also
8481 a violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the
8482 law
—increasing its regulation, even if the subject it regulates
8483 (activities that would otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is
8484 beyond the reach of the law. Code becomes law; code extends the law;
8485 code thus extends the control that copyright owners effect
—at
8486 least for those copyright holders with the lawyers who can write the
8487 nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com received.
8490 There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and
8491 law that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is
8492 the ease with which infringements of the law can be detected. For
8493 contrary to the rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the
8494 Internet, no one knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing
8495 technologies deployed on the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who
8496 committed a legal wrong. The technologies of the Internet are open to
8497 snoops as well as sharers, and the snoops are increasingly good at
8498 tracking down the identity of those who violate the rules.
8502 <!-- PAGE BREAK 172 -->
8503 For example, imagine you were part of a
<citetitle>Star Trek
</citetitle> fan club. You
8504 gathered every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan
8505 fiction about the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain
8506 Kirk. The characters would begin with a plot from a real story, then
8507 simply continue it.
<footnote><para>
8509 For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet,
<quote>Legal Fictions,
8510 Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law,
</quote> <citetitle>Loyola of Los Angeles
8511 Entertainment Law Journal
</citetitle> 17 (
1997):
651.
8515 Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated
8516 activity. No matter what happened inside your club room, you would
8517 never be interfered with by the copyright police. You were free in
8518 that space to do as you wished with this part of our culture. You were
8519 allowed to build on it as you wished without fear of legal control.
8521 <indexterm><primary>bots
</primary></indexterm>
8523 But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally
8524 available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots
8525 scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would
8526 quickly find your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon
8527 the ownership of the series that you're depicting, could well inspire
8528 a lawyer's threat. And ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely
8529 costly indeed. The law of copyright is extremely efficient. The
8530 penalties are severe, and the process is quick.
8533 This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change
8534 in the ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts
8535 the law's balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at
8536 which you traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just
8537 one step before the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you
8538 transmitted. That is, in effect, what is happening here.
8541 <section id=
"marketconcentration">
8542 <title>Market: Concentration
</title>
8544 So copyright's duration has increased dramatically
—tripled in
8545 the past thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as
8546 well
—from regulating only publishers to now regulating just
8547 about everyone. And copyright's reach has changed, as every action
8548 becomes a copy and hence presumptively regulated. And as technologists
8550 <!-- PAGE BREAK 173 -->
8551 to control the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly
8552 enforced through technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is
8553 easier to find and easier to control. This regulation of the creative
8554 process, which began as a tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the
8555 market for creative work, has become the single most important
8556 regulator of creativity there is. It is a massive expansion in the
8557 scope of the government's control over innovation and creativity; it
8558 would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth to copyright's
8562 Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it
8563 weren't for one more change that we must also consider. This is a
8564 change that is in some sense the most familiar, though its significance
8565 and scope are not well understood. It is the one that creates precisely the
8566 reason to be concerned about all the other changes I have described.
8569 This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media.
8570 In the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone
8571 a radical alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the
8572 media. Before this change happened, the different forms of media were
8573 owned by separate media companies. Now, the media is increasingly
8574 owned by only a few companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC
8575 announced in June
2003, most expect that within a few years, we will
8576 live in a world where just three companies control more than
85 percent
8580 These changes are of two sorts: the scope of concentration, and its
8583 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
8584 <indexterm><primary>BMG
</primary></indexterm>
8585 <indexterm><primary>EMI
</primary></indexterm>
8586 <indexterm><primary>McCain, John
</primary></indexterm>
8587 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
8588 <indexterm><primary>Warner Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
8590 Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John
8591 McCain summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media
8592 ownership,
<quote>five companies control
85 percent of our media sources.
</quote><footnote><para>
8594 FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and
8595 Transportation Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st sess. (
22 May
2003)
8596 (statement of Senator John McCain).
</para></footnote>
8597 The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, BMG, Sony Music
8598 Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control
84.8 percent of the
8599 U.S. music market.
<footnote><para>
8601 Lynette Holloway,
<quote>Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to
8602 Slide,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
23 December
2002.
8604 The
<quote>five largest cable companies pipe
8605 programming to
74 percent of the cable subscribers nationwide.
</quote><footnote><para>
8607 Molly Ivins,
<quote>Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped,
</quote> <citetitle>Charleston Gazette
</citetitle>,
8612 The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation,
8613 the nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than
8614 <!-- PAGE BREAK 174 -->
8615 seventy-five stations. Today
<emphasis>one
</emphasis> company owns
8616 more than
1,
200 stations. During that period of consolidation, the
8617 total number of radio owners dropped by
34 percent. Today, in most
8618 markets, the two largest broadcasters control
74 percent of that
8619 market's revenues. Overall, just four companies control
90 percent of
8620 the nation's radio advertising revenues.
8622 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
8624 Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today,
8625 there are six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than
8626 there were eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the
8627 nation's circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in
8628 the United States. The top ten film studios receive
99 percent of all
8629 film revenue. The ten largest cable companies account for
85 percent
8630 of all cable revenue. This is a market far from the free press the
8631 framers sought to protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well
8632 protected
— by the market.
8634 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James
</primary></indexterm>
8636 Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious
8637 change is in the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows
8638 put it in a recent article about Rupert Murdoch,
8642 Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system
8643 unmatched in its integration. They supply content
—Fox movies
8644 … Fox TV shows
… Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus
8645 newspapers and books. They sell the content to the public and to
8646 advertisers
—in newspapers, on the broadcast network, on the
8647 cable channels. And they operate the physical distribution system
8648 through which the content reaches the customers. Murdoch's satellite
8649 systems now distribute News Corp. content in Europe and Asia; if
8650 Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that system will serve
8651 the same function in the United States.
<footnote><para>
8653 James Fallows,
<quote>The Age of Murdoch,
</quote> <citetitle>Atlantic Monthly
</citetitle> (September
8655 <indexterm><primary>Fallows, James
</primary></indexterm>
8660 The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not
8661 just large companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies
8662 owning as many outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this
8663 pattern better than a thousand words could do:
8665 <figure id=
"fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership">
8667 <graphic fileref=
"images/pattern-modern-media-ownership.png" align=
"center" width=
"90%"></graphic>
8670 <!-- PAGE BREAK 175 -->
8671 Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or
8672 what is distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and
8676 My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was
8677 nothing more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after
8678 reading and listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the
8679 contrary, I am beginning to change my mind.
8682 Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this
8683 integration may matter.
8685 <indexterm><primary>Lear, Norman
</primary></indexterm>
8686 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
8687 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family
</primary></indexterm>
8689 In
1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for
<citetitle>All in the Family
</citetitle>. He took
8690 the pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told
8691 Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the
8692 first. ABC was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear.
8693 We wanted less edgy, not more.
8696 Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS
8697 was happy to have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking.
8698 The copyrights that Lear held assured an independence from network
8699 control.
<footnote><para>
8701 Leonard Hill,
<quote>The Axis of Access,
</quote> remarks before Weidenbaum Center
8702 Forum,
<quote>Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry,
</quote> St. Louis,
8703 Missouri,
3 April
2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at
8704 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
28</ulink>;
8705 for the Lear story, not included in the prepared remarks, see
8706 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
29</ulink>).
8711 <!-- PAGE BREAK 176 -->
8712 The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade
8713 the networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law
8714 required a separation between the networks and the content producers;
8715 that separation would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as
1992,
8716 because of these rules, the vast majority of prime time
8717 television
—75 percent of it
—was
<quote>independent
</quote> of the
8721 In
1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence.
8722 After that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In
1985,
8723 there were twenty-five independent television production studios; in
8724 2002, only five independent television studios remained.
<quote>In
1992,
8725 only
15 percent of new series were produced for a network by a company
8726 it controlled. Last year, the percentage of shows produced by
8727 controlled companies more than quintupled to
77 percent.
</quote> <quote>In
1992,
16
8728 new series were produced independently of conglomerate control, last
8729 year there was one.
</quote><footnote><para>
8731 NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media
8732 Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st
8733 sess. (
2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union
8734 and the Consumer Federation of America), available at
8735 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
30</ulink>. Kimmelman
8736 quotes Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West,
8737 in her Remarks at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia,
27 February
8740 In
2002,
75 percent of prime time television was owned by the networks
8741 that ran it.
<quote>In the ten-year period between
1992 and
2002, the number
8742 of prime time television hours per week produced by network studios
8743 increased over
200%, whereas the number of prime time television hours
8744 per week produced by independent studios decreased
8745 63%.
</quote><footnote><para>
8750 <indexterm><primary>All in the Family
</primary></indexterm>
8752 Today, another Norman Lear with another
<citetitle>All in the Family
</citetitle> would
8753 find that he had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be
8754 fired: The content of any show developed for a network is increasingly
8755 owned by the network.
8757 <indexterm><primary>Diller, Barry
</primary></indexterm>
8758 <indexterm><primary>Moyers, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
8760 While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership
8761 of those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As
8762 Barry Diller said to Bill Moyers,
8766 Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on
8767 their channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes
8768 through their controlled distribution system, then what you get is
8769 fewer and fewer actual voices participating in the process. [We
8770 <!-- PAGE BREAK 177 -->
8771 u]sed to have dozens and dozens of thriving independent production
8772 companies producing television programs. Now you have less than a
8773 handful.
<footnote><para>
8775 <quote>Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation,
</quote> <citetitle>Now with Bill Moyers
</citetitle>, Bill
8776 Moyers,
25 April
2003, edited transcript available at
8777 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
31</ulink>.
8782 This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such
8783 large and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous.
8784 Increasingly safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows
8785 from networks like this is increasingly tailored to the message the
8786 network wants to convey. This is not the communist party, though from
8787 the inside, it must feel a bit like the communist party. No one can
8788 question without risk of consequence
—not necessarily banishment
8789 to Siberia, but punishment nonetheless. Independent, critical,
8790 different views are quashed. This is not the environment for a
8793 <indexterm><primary>Clark, Kim B.
</primary></indexterm>
8795 Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration
8796 affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the
<quote>Innovator's
8797 Dilemma
</quote>: the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore
8798 new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business.
8799 The same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media
8800 companies would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.
<footnote><para>
8802 Clayton M. Christensen,
<citetitle>The Innovator's Dilemma: The
8803 Revolutionary National Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business
</citetitle>
8804 (Cambridge: Harvard Business School Press,
1997). Christensen
8805 acknowledges that the idea was first suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See
8806 Kim B. Clark,
<quote>The Interaction of Design Hierarchies and Market
8807 Concepts in Technological Evolution,
</quote> <citetitle>Research Policy
</citetitle> 14 (
1985):
8808 235–51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and Sarah
8809 Kaplan,
<citetitle>Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last
8810 Underperform the Market
—and How to Successfully Transform Them
</citetitle>
8811 (New York: Currency/Doubleday,
2001).
</para></footnote>
8813 Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, sprint. Yet if the
8814 field is only open to the giants, there will be far too little
8816 <indexterm><primary>Christensen, Clayton M.
</primary></indexterm>
8819 I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media
8820 market to say with certainty what concentration and integration will
8821 do. The efficiencies are important, and the effect on culture is hard to
8825 But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly
8826 suggest the concern.
8829 In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug
8830 wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels;
8831 criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle.
8834 Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to
8835 any position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound
8836 mistake. I am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once
8838 <!-- PAGE BREAK 178 -->
8839 wrecked by drugs
—though the drugs that wrecked my family were
8840 all quite legal. I believe this war is a profound mistake because the
8841 collateral damage from it is so great as to make waging the war
8842 insane. When you add together the burdens on the criminal justice
8843 system, the desperation of generations of kids whose only real
8844 economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the queering of
8845 constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance this
8846 war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal
8847 systems of many South American nations because of the power of the
8848 local drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal
8849 benefit in reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly
8850 outweigh these costs.
8853 You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it
8854 is through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we
8855 depend fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about
8858 <indexterm id='idxadvertising3' class='startofrange'
><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
8859 <indexterm id='idxcommercials' class='startofrange'
><primary>commercials
</primary></indexterm>
8860 <indexterm id='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='startofrange'
><primary>television
</primary><secondary>advertising on
</secondary></indexterm>
8861 <indexterm><primary>Nick and Norm anti-drug campaign
</primary></indexterm>
8863 Beginning in
1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched
8864 a media campaign as part of the
<quote>war on drugs.
</quote> The campaign produced
8865 scores of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In
8866 one series (the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing
8867 the idea of legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral
8868 damage from the war. One advances an argument in favor of drug
8869 legalization. The other responds in a powerful and effective way
8870 against the argument of the first. In the end, the first guy changes
8871 his mind (hey, it's television). The plug at the end is a damning
8872 attack on the pro-legalization campaign.
8875 Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its
8876 message well. It's a fair and reasonable message.
8879 But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a
8880 countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to
8881 demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug
8885 Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the
8886 <!-- PAGE BREAK 179 -->
8887 money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in
8888 the world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your
8889 message will be heard then?
8891 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>First Amendment to
</secondary></indexterm>
8892 <indexterm><primary>First Amendment
</primary></indexterm>
8893 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on television advertising bans
</secondary></indexterm>
8894 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>controversy avoided by
</secondary></indexterm>
8896 No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding
8897 <quote>controversial
</quote> ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed
8898 uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are
8899 controversial. This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with
8900 the First Amendment, but the Supreme Court has held that stations have
8901 the right to choose what they run. Thus, the major channels of
8902 commercial media will refuse one side of a crucial debate the
8903 opportunity to present its case. And the courts will defend the
8904 rights of the stations to be this biased.
<footnote><para>
8906 <indexterm><primary>ABC
</primary></indexterm>
8907 <indexterm><primary>Comcast
</primary></indexterm>
8908 <indexterm><primary>Marijuana Policy Project
</primary></indexterm>
8909 <indexterm><primary>NBC
</primary></indexterm>
8910 <indexterm><primary>WJOA
</primary></indexterm>
8911 <indexterm><primary>WRC
</primary></indexterm>
8912 <indexterm><primary>advertising
</primary></indexterm>
8913 The Marijuana Policy Project, in February
2003, sought to place ads
8914 that directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within
8915 the Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as
<quote>against
8916 [their] policy.
</quote> The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads
8917 without reviewing them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally
8918 agreed to run the ads and accepted payment to do so, but later decided
8919 not to run the ads and returned the collected fees. Interview with
8920 Neal Levine,
15 October
2003. These restrictions are, of course, not
8921 limited to drug policy. See, for example, Nat Ives,
<quote>On the
8922 Issue of an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection from TV
8923 Networks,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
13 March
8924 2003, C4. Outside of election-related air time there is very little
8925 that the FCC or the courts are willing to do to even the playing
8926 field. For a general overview, see Rhonda Brown,
<quote>Ad Hoc Access:
8927 The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on Television and
8928 Radio,
</quote> <citetitle>Yale Law and Policy Review
</citetitle> 6
8929 (
1988):
449–79, and for a more recent summary of the stance of
8930 the FCC and the courts, see
<citetitle>Radio-Television News Directors
8931 Association
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>FCC
</citetitle>,
184 F.
3d
872
8932 (D.C. Cir.
1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as
8933 the networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San
8934 Francisco transit authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni
8935 diesel buses. Phillip Matier and Andrew Ross,
<quote>Antidiesel Group
8936 Fuming After Muni Rejects Ad,
</quote> SFGate.com,
16 June
2003,
8937 available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
8938 #
32</ulink>. The ground was that the criticism was
<quote>too
8939 controversial.
</quote>
8942 <indexterm startref='idxcommercials' class='endofrange'
/>
8943 <indexterm startref='idxtelevisionadvertisingon' class='endofrange'
/>
8945 I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well
—if we lived
8946 in a media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the
8947 media throws that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies
8948 control access to the media, and that handful of companies gets to
8949 decide which political positions it will allow to be promoted on its
8950 channels, then in an obvious and important way, concentration
8951 matters. You might like the positions the handful of companies
8952 selects. But you should not like a world in which a mere few get to
8953 decide which issues the rest of us get to know about.
8955 <indexterm startref='idxadvertising3' class='endofrange'
/>
8957 <section id=
"together">
8958 <title>Together
</title>
8960 There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the
8961 copyright warriors that the government should
<quote>protect my property.
</quote>
8962 In the abstract, it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally
8963 harmless. No sane sort who is not an anarchist could disagree.
8966 But when we see how dramatically this
<quote>property
</quote> has changed
—
8967 when we recognize how it might now interact with both technology and
8968 markets to mean that the effective constraint on the liberty to
8969 cultivate our culture is dramatically different
—the claim begins
8972 <!-- PAGE BREAK 180 -->
8973 less innocent and obvious. Given (
1) the power of technology to
8974 supplement the law's control, and (
2) the power of concentrated
8975 markets to weaken the opportunity for dissent, if strictly enforcing
8976 the massively expanded
<quote>property
</quote> rights granted by copyright
8977 fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture to cultivate and
8978 build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this property should
8982 Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish
8983 copyright or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total
8984 mistake, disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within
8988 But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture
8989 notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of
8990 copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content
8991 industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly
8992 enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider
8993 whether another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that
8994 increases copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its
8995 term. Rather, an adjustment to restore the balance that has
8996 traditionally defined copyright's regulation
—a weakening of that
8997 regulation, to strengthen creativity.
9000 Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of
9001 constant commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and
9002 geeks now flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a
9003 short period of time, as the technologies of distribution and creation
9004 have changed and as lobbyists have pushed for more control by
9005 copyright holders. Changes in the past in response to changes in
9006 technology suggest that we may well need similar changes in the
9007 future. And these changes have to be
<emphasis>reductions
</emphasis>
9008 in the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase
9009 in control that technology and the market enable.
9012 For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that
9013 we see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add
9014 <!-- PAGE BREAK 181 -->
9015 together the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and
9016 changing technology, together they produce an astonishing conclusion:
9017 <emphasis>Never in our history have fewer had a legal right to control
9018 more of the development of our culture than now
</emphasis>.
9021 Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were
9022 perpetual, they affected only that precise creative work. Not when
9023 only publishers had the tools to publish, for the market then was much
9024 more diverse. Not when there were only three television networks, for
9025 even then, newspapers, film studios, radio stations, and publishers
9026 were independent of the networks.
<emphasis>Never
</emphasis> has
9027 copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against as broad a
9028 range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form of
9029 regulation
—a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative
9030 energy of a nation at the founding
—is now a massive regulation
9031 of the overall creative process. Law plus technology plus the market
9032 now interact to turn this historically benign regulation into the most
9033 significant regulation of culture that our free society has
9034 known.
<footnote><para>
9036 <indexterm><primary>Vaidhyanathan, Siva
</primary></indexterm>
9037 Siva Vaidhyanathan captures a similar point in his
<quote>four surrenders
</quote> of
9038 copyright law in the digital age. See Vaidhyanathan,
159–60.
9042 <emphasis role='strong'
>This has been
</emphasis> a long chapter. Its
9043 point can now be briefly stated.
9046 At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and
9047 noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have
9048 distinguished between copying a work and transforming it. We can now
9049 combine these two distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes
9050 that copyright law has undergone. In
1790, the law looked like this:
9053 <informaltable id=
"t2">
9054 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
9058 <entry>PUBLISH
</entry>
9059 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
9064 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
9065 <entry>©</entry>
9069 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
9078 The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by
9079 copyright law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as
9080 copyright attached only with registration, and only those who intended
9082 <!-- PAGE BREAK 182 -->
9083 to benefit commercially would register, copying through publishing of
9084 noncommercial work was also free.
9087 By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this:
9090 <informaltable id=
"t3">
9091 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
9095 <entry>PUBLISH
</entry>
9096 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
9101 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
9102 <entry>©</entry>
9103 <entry>©</entry>
9106 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
9115 Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law
—if
9116 published, which again, given the economics of publishing at the time,
9117 means if offered commercially. But noncommercial publishing and
9118 transformation were still essentially free.
9121 In
1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after
9122 this change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the
9123 technology of copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law
9124 expanded. Thus by
1975, as photocopying machines became more common,
9125 we could say the law began to look like this:
9128 <informaltable id=
"t4">
9129 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
9134 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
9139 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
9140 <entry>©</entry>
9141 <entry>©</entry>
9144 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
9145 <entry>© / Free
</entry>
9153 The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say,
9154 copy machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial
9155 market remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital
9156 technologies, especially in the context of a digital network, means
9157 that the law now looks like this:
9160 <informaltable id=
"t5">
9161 <tgroup cols=
"3" align=
"left">
9166 <entry>TRANSFORM
</entry>
9171 <entry>Commercial
</entry>
9172 <entry>©</entry>
9173 <entry>©</entry>
9176 <entry>Noncommercial
</entry>
9177 <entry>©</entry>
9178 <entry>©</entry>
9185 Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most
9186 creativity was not. The law now regulates the full range of
9188 <!-- PAGE BREAK 183 -->
9189 commercial or not, transformative or not
—with the same rules
9190 designed to regulate commercial publishers.
9193 Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation
9194 that does no good. So the question that we should be asking just now
9195 is whether extending the regulations of copyright law into each of
9196 these domains actually does any good.
9199 I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying.
9200 But I also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when
9201 regulating (as it regulates just now) noncommercial copying and,
9202 especially, noncommercial transformation. And increasingly, for the
9203 reasons sketched especially in chapters
9204 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"recorders"/> and
9205 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"transformers"/>, one
9206 might well wonder whether it does more harm than good for commercial
9207 transformation. More commercial transformative work would be created
9208 if derivative rights were more sharply restricted.
9211 The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of
9212 course copyright is a kind of
<quote>property,
</quote> and of course, as with any
9213 property, the state ought to protect it. But first impressions
9214 notwithstanding, historically, this property right (as with all
9215 property rights
<footnote><para>
9217 <indexterm><primary>legal realist movement
</primary></indexterm>
9218 It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist
9219 movement to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to
9220 balance public and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey,
<quote>The
9221 Disintegration of Property,
</quote> in
<citetitle>Nomos XXII: Property
</citetitle>, J. Roland
9222 Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New York: New York University
9225 has been crafted to balance the important need to give authors and
9226 artists incentives with the equally important need to assure access to
9227 creative work. This balance has always been struck in light of new
9228 technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the
<quote>copyright
</quote>
9229 did not control
<emphasis>at all
</emphasis> the freedom of others to
9230 build upon or transform a creative work. American culture was born
9231 free, and for almost
180 years our country consistently protected a
9232 vibrant and rich free culture.
9234 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
9236 We achieved that free culture because our law respected important
9237 limits on the scope of the interests protected by
<quote>property.
</quote> The very
9238 birth of
<quote>copyright
</quote> as a statutory right recognized those limits, by
9239 granting copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the
9240 story of chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
9241 linkend=
"founders"/>). The tradition of
<quote>fair use
</quote> is
9242 animated by a similar concern that is increasingly under strain as the
9243 costs of exercising any fair use right become unavoidably high (the
9244 story of chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
9245 linkend=
"recorders"/>). Adding
9246 <!-- PAGE BREAK 184 -->
9247 statutory rights where markets might stifle innovation is another
9248 familiar limit on the property right that copyright is (chapter
<xref
9249 xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"transformers"/>). And
9250 granting archives and libraries a broad freedom to collect, claims of
9251 property notwithstanding, is a crucial part of guaranteeing the soul
9252 of a culture (chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
9253 linkend=
"collectors"/>). Free cultures, like free markets, are built
9254 with property. But the nature of the property that builds a free
9255 culture is very different from the extremist vision that dominates the
9259 Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In
9260 response to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the
9261 technologies of the Internet present to twentieth-century business
9262 models for producing and distributing culture, the law and technology
9263 are being transformed in a way that will undermine our tradition of
9264 free culture. The property right that is copyright is no longer the
9265 balanced right that it was, or was intended to be. The property right
9266 that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted toward an extreme. The
9267 opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened in a world in
9268 which creation requires permission and creativity must check with a
9271 <!-- PAGE BREAK 185 -->
9275 <part id=
"c-puzzles">
9276 <title>PUZZLES
</title>
9278 <!-- PAGE BREAK 186 -->
9279 <chapter label=
"11" id=
"chimera">
9280 <title>Chimera
</title>
9281 <indexterm id='idxchimera' class='startofrange'
><primary>chimeras
</primary></indexterm>
9282 <indexterm id='idxwells' class='startofrange'
><primary>Wells, H. G.
</primary></indexterm>
9283 <indexterm id='idxtcotb' class='startofrange'
><primary><quote>Country of the Blind, The
</quote> (Wells)
</primary></indexterm>
9286 <emphasis role='strong'
>In a well-known
</emphasis> short story by
9287 H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez trips (literally, down an
9288 ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in the Peruvian
9289 Andes.
<footnote><para>
9291 H. G. Wells,
<quote>The Country of the Blind
</quote> (
1904,
1911). See H. G. Wells,
9292 <citetitle>The Country of the Blind and Other Stories
</citetitle>, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New
9293 York: Oxford University Press,
1996).
9295 The valley is extraordinarily beautiful, with
<quote>sweet water, pasture,
9296 an even climate, slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub
9297 that bore an excellent fruit.
</quote> But the villagers are all blind. Nunez
9298 takes this as an opportunity.
<quote>In the Country of the Blind,
</quote> he tells
9299 himself,
<quote>the One-Eyed Man is King.
</quote> So he resolves to live with the
9300 villagers to explore life as a king.
9303 Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of
9304 sight to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are
9305 <quote>blind.
</quote> They don't have the word
<citetitle>blind
</citetitle>. They think he's just thick.
9306 Indeed, as they increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the
9307 sound of grass being stepped on, for example), they increasingly try
9308 to control him. He, in turn, becomes increasingly frustrated.
<quote>`You
9309 don't understand,' he cried, in a voice that was meant to be great and
9310 resolute, and which broke. `You are blind and I can see. Leave me
9314 <!-- PAGE BREAK 187 -->
9315 The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the
9316 virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his
9317 affection, a young woman who to him seems
<quote>the most beautiful thing in
9318 the whole of creation,
</quote> understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's
9319 description of what he sees
<quote>seemed to her the most poetical of
9320 fancies, and she listened to his description of the stars and the
9321 mountains and her own sweet white-lit beauty as though it was a guilty
9322 indulgence.
</quote> <quote>She did not believe,
</quote> Wells tells us, and
<quote>she could
9323 only half understand, but she was mysteriously delighted.
</quote>
9326 When Nunez announces his desire to marry his
<quote>mysteriously delighted
</quote>
9327 love, the father and the village object.
<quote>You see, my dear,
</quote> her
9328 father instructs,
<quote>he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do
9329 anything right.
</quote> They take Nunez to the village doctor.
9332 After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion.
<quote>His brain
9333 is affected,
</quote> he reports.
9336 <quote>What affects it?
</quote> the father asks.
<quote>Those queer things that are
9337 called the eyes
… are diseased
… in such a way as to affect
9341 The doctor continues:
<quote>I think I may say with reasonable certainty
9342 that in order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a
9343 simple and easy surgical operation
—namely, to remove these
9344 irritant bodies [the eyes].
</quote>
9347 <quote>Thank Heaven for science!
</quote> says the father to the doctor. They inform
9348 Nunez of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride.
9349 (You'll have to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I
9350 believe in free culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.)
9353 <emphasis role='strong'
>It sometimes
</emphasis> happens that the eggs
9354 of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a
9355 <quote>chimera.
</quote> A chimera is a single creature with two sets
9356 of DNA. The DNA in the blood, for example, might be different from the
9357 DNA of the skin. This possibility is an underused
9359 <!-- PAGE BREAK 188 -->
9360 plot for murder mysteries.
<quote>But the DNA shows with
100 percent
9361 certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at the
9362 scene.
…</quote>
9364 <indexterm startref='idxtcotb' class='endofrange'
/>
9365 <indexterm startref='idxwells'
class=
"endofrange"/>
9367 Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were
9368 impossible. A single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea
9369 of DNA is that it is the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only
9370 can two individuals have the same set of DNA (identical twins), but
9371 one person can have two different sets of DNA (a chimera). Our
9372 understanding of a
<quote>person
</quote> should reflect this reality.
9375 The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and
9376 culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not
9377 unfairly enough,
<quote>the copyright wars,
</quote> the more I think we're dealing
9378 with a chimera. For example, in the battle over the question
<quote>What is
9379 p2p file sharing?
</quote> both sides have it right, and both sides have it
9380 wrong. One side says,
<quote>File sharing is just like two kids taping each
9381 others' records
—the sort of thing we've been doing for the last
9382 thirty years without any question at all.
</quote> That's true, at least in
9383 part. When I tell my best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought,
9384 but rather than just send the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that
9385 is, in all relevant respects, just like what every executive in every
9386 recording company no doubt did as a kid: sharing music.
9389 But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is
9390 on a p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then
9391 sure, my friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of
9392 <quote>friends
</quote> beyond recognition to say
<quote>my ten thousand best friends
</quote> can
9393 get access. Whether or not sharing my music with my best friend is
9394 what
<quote>we have always been allowed to do,
</quote> we have not always been
9395 allowed to share music with
<quote>our ten thousand best friends.
</quote>
9398 Likewise, when the other side says,
<quote>File sharing is just like walking
9399 into a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out
9400 with it,
</quote> that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett
9401 (finally) releases a new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa
9402 and find a free copy to take, that is very much like stealing a copy
9404 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
9408 <!-- PAGE BREAK 189 -->
9409 But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD
9410 from Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a
9411 CD from Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and
9412 something to show on my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could
9413 also note that when I take a CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine
9414 that might be imposed on me, under California law, at least, is
9415 $
1,
000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if I download a ten-song
9416 CD, I'm liable for $
1,
500,
000 in damages.)
9419 The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is
9420 that it is both
—both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa
9421 describes it. It is a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the
9422 other side asserts, we need to begin to think about how we should
9423 respond to this chimera. What rules should govern it?
9426 We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We
9427 could, with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be
9428 a felony. We could prosecute families for millions of dollars in
9429 damages just because file sharing occurred on a family computer. And
9430 we can get universities to monitor all computer traffic to make sure
9431 that no computer is used to commit this crime. These responses might
9432 be extreme, but each of them has either been proposed or actually
9433 implemented.
<footnote><para>
9435 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
9436 For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the
9437 Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School,
9438 <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> 27 June
2003,
9440 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
9441 #
33</ulink>. Reps. John Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman
9442 (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill that would treat unauthorized
9443 on-line copying as a felony offense with punishments ranging as high
9444 as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey,
<quote>House Bill Aims to Up
9445 Stakes on Piracy,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
17 July
2003, available at
9446 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
34</ulink>. Civil
9447 penalties are currently set at $
150,
000 per copied song. For a recent
9448 (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand that an ISP
9449 reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than
600 songs
9450 through a family computer, see
<citetitle>RIAA
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Verizon Internet Services (In
9451 re. Verizon Internet Services)
</citetitle>,
240 F. Supp.
2d
24
9452 (D.D.C.
2003). Such a user could face liability ranging as high as $
90
9453 million. Such astronomical figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful
9454 arsenal in its prosecution of file sharers. Settlements ranging from
9455 $
12,
000 to $
17,
500 for four students accused of heavy file sharing on
9456 university networks must have seemed a mere pittance next to the $
98
9457 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter proceed to court. See
9458 Elizabeth Young,
<quote>Downloading Could Lead to Fines,
</quote> redandblack.com,
9459 August
2003, available at
9460 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
35</ulink>. For an
9461 example of the RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the
9462 subpoenas issued to universities to reveal student file-sharer
9463 identities, see James Collins,
<quote>RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to
9464 Name Students,
</quote> <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
8 August
2003, D3, available at
9465 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
36</ulink>.
9466 <indexterm><primary>Conyers, John, Jr.
</primary></indexterm>
9467 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.
</primary></indexterm>
9471 <indexterm startref='idxchimera' class='endofrange'
/>
9473 Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act
9474 as though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be
9475 no copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making
9476 copyrighted content available on the Net. Make file sharing like
9477 gossip: regulated, if at all, by social norms but not by law.
9480 Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake.
9481 Rather than embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace
9482 something that recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book
9483 with a sketch of a system that does just that, my aim in the next
9484 chapter is to show just how awful it would be for us to adopt the
9485 zero-tolerance extreme. I believe
<emphasis>either
</emphasis> extreme
9486 would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe the
9487 zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes.
9491 <!-- PAGE BREAK 190 -->
9492 Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the
9493 middle of the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary
9494 land grab is occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to
9495 give content holders a kind of control over our culture that they have
9496 never had before. And in this extremism, many an opportunity for new
9497 innovation and new creativity will be lost.
9500 I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to
<quote>steal
</quote> music. My
9501 focus instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war
9502 will also kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so
9503 broadly among our citizens, and we have just begun to see the
9504 innovation that this power will unleash. Yet the Internet has already
9505 seen the passing of one cycle of innovation around technologies to
9506 distribute content. The law is responsible for this passing. As the
9507 vice president for global public policy at one of these new
9508 innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added
9509 protection for copyrighted material,
9513 eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted
9514 material, and we want to protect those rights.
9517 But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the
9518 major labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright
9519 interests, nor is it necessarily the best. It is simply too early to
9520 answer that question. Market forces operating naturally may very well
9521 produce a totally different industry model.
9524 This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make
9525 with respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the
9526 market for digital media and the manner in which digital media
9527 are distributed. This in turn will directly influence the options
9528 that are available to consumers, both in terms of the ease with
9529 which they will be able to access digital media and the equipment
9530 that they will require to do so. Poor choices made this early in the
9531 game will retard the growth of this market, hurting everyone's
9532 interests.
<footnote><para>
9534 WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital
9535 Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the
9536 Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection,
9537 House Committee on Commerce,
106th Cong.
29 (
1999) (statement of Peter
9538 Harter, vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards,
9539 EMusic.com), available in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House
9540 Congressional Testimony File.
</para></footnote>
9543 <!-- PAGE BREAK 191 -->
9545 In April
2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal,
9546 one of
<quote>the major labels.
</quote> Its position on these matters has now
9548 <indexterm><primary>Vivendi Universal
</primary></indexterm>
9551 Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash
9552 piracy. It will sacrifice values that are important to this culture,
9553 and will kill opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable.
9556 <!-- PAGE BREAK 192 -->
9558 <chapter label=
"12" id=
"harms">
9559 <title>Harms
</title>
9561 <emphasis role='strong'
>To fight
</emphasis> <quote>piracy,
</quote> to
9562 protect
<quote>property,
</quote> the content industry has launched a
9563 war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the
9564 government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both
9565 direct and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these
9566 damages will be suffered most by our own people.
9569 My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in
9570 particular, the consequences for
<quote>free culture.
</quote> But my aim now is to
9571 extend this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war
9575 In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the
9576 first time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the
9577 power of the property called
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> is at its greatest in
9580 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
9581 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
9583 Yet
<quote>common sense
</quote> does not see it this way. Common sense is still on
9584 the side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims
9585 of control in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical
9586 rejection of
<quote>piracy
</quote> still has play.
9588 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
9590 <!-- PAGE BREAK 193 -->
9591 There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to
9592 describe just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite
9593 confident the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The
9594 first two protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in
9595 the wings to fight today's monopolists of culture.
9597 <section id=
"constrain">
9598 <title>Constraining Creators
</title>
9600 In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital
9601 technologies. These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture
9602 and share content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what
9603 humans have done since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and
9604 communicate. But capturing and sharing through digital technology is
9605 different. The fidelity and power are different. You could send an
9606 e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on Comedy Central, or you
9607 could send the clip. You could write an essay about the
9608 inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to
9609 hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against
9610 statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could
9611 weave together a string
—a mash-up
— of songs from your
9612 favorite artists in a collage and make it available on the Net.
9615 This digital
<quote>capturing and sharing
</quote> is in part an extension of the
9616 capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture,
9617 and in part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but
9618 it explodes the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology
9619 of digital
<quote>capturing and sharing
</quote> promises a world of extraordinarily
9620 diverse creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that
9621 creativity is applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of
9622 citizens to use technology to express and criticize and contribute to
9623 the culture all around.
9626 Technology has thus given us an opportunity to do something with
9627 culture that has only ever been possible for individuals in small groups,
9629 <!-- PAGE BREAK 194 -->
9631 isolated from others. Think about an old man telling a story to a
9632 collection of neighbors in a small town. Now imagine that same
9633 storytelling extended across the globe.
9636 Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In
9637 the current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for
9638 a moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web
9639 sites that offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites
9640 that catalog cartoons from the
1960s; sites that mix images and sound
9641 to criticize politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles
9642 on remote topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative
9643 work spread across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this
9644 work is presumptively illegal.
9646 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom
</primary></indexterm>
9647 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of
</secondary></indexterm>
9648 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>in recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
9649 <indexterm><primary>doctors malpractice claims against
</primary></indexterm>
9650 <indexterm><primary>Jordan, Jesse
</primary></indexterm>
9652 That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the
9653 examples of extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to
9654 proliferate. It is impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed
9655 and what's not, and at the same time, the penalties for crossing the
9656 line are astonishingly harsh. The four students who were threatened
9657 by the RIAA (Jesse Jordan of chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select:
9658 labelnumber" linkend=
"catalogs"/> was just one) were threatened with a
9659 $
98 billion lawsuit for building search engines that permitted songs
9660 to be copied. Yet World-Com
—which defrauded investors of $
11
9661 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in market capitalization of
9662 over $
200 billion
—received a fine of a mere $
750
9663 million.
<footnote><para>
9665 See Lynne W. Jeter,
<citetitle>Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom
</citetitle>
9666 (Hoboken, N.J.: John Wiley
& Sons,
2003),
176,
204; for details of
9667 the settlement, see MCI press release,
<quote>MCI Wins U.S. District Court
9668 Approval for SEC Settlement
</quote> (
7 July
2003), available at
9669 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
37</ulink>.
9670 <indexterm><primary>WorldCom
</primary></indexterm>
9672 And under legislation being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who
9673 negligently removes the wrong leg in an operation would be liable for
9674 no more than $
250,
000 in damages for pain and
9675 suffering.
<footnote>
9677 <!-- f2. --> The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the
9678 House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July
2003. For
9679 an overview, see Tanya Albert,
<quote>Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,'
9680 Say Tort Reformers,
</quote> amednews.com,
28 July
2003, available at
9681 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
38</ulink>,
9682 and
<quote>Senate Turns Back Malpractice Caps,
</quote> CBSNews.com,
9 July
2003,
9684 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
39</ulink>. President Bush has continued to urge tort reform in
9686 <indexterm><primary>Bush, George W.
</primary></indexterm>
9688 Can common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where
9689 the maximum fine for downloading two songs off the Internet is more
9690 than the fine for a doctor's negligently butchering a patient?
9692 <indexterm><primary>art, underground
</primary></indexterm>
9694 The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely
9695 high penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will
9696 either never be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive
9697 this creative process underground by branding the modern-day Walt
9698 Disneys
<quote>pirates.
</quote> We make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a
9699 public domain, because the boundaries of the public domain are
9702 <!-- PAGE BREAK 195 -->
9703 be unclear. It never pays to do anything except pay for the right
9704 to create, and hence only those who can pay are allowed to create. As
9705 was the case in the Soviet Union, though for very different reasons,
9706 we will begin to see a world of underground art
—not because the
9707 message is necessarily political, or because the subject is
9708 controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is legally
9709 fraught. Already, exhibits of
<quote>illegal art
</quote> tour the United
9710 States.
<footnote><para>
9713 See Danit Lidor,
<quote>Artists Just Wanna Be Free,
</quote> <citetitle>Wired
</citetitle>,
7 July
9715 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
40</ulink>. For an overview of the exhibition, see
9716 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
41</ulink>.
9718 In what does their
<quote>illegality
</quote> consist?
9719 In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that is
9720 critical or reflective.
9722 <indexterm><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
9724 Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the
9725 changing law. I described that change in detail in chapter
9726 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>. But an
9727 even bigger part has to do with the increasing ease with which
9728 infractions can be tracked. As users of file-sharing systems
9729 discovered in
2002, it is a trivial matter for copyright owners to get
9730 courts to order Internet service providers to reveal who has what
9731 content. It is as if your cassette tape player transmitted a list of
9732 the songs that you played in the privacy of your own home that anyone
9733 could tune into for whatever reason they chose.
9735 <indexterm><primary>images, ownership of
</primary></indexterm>
9737 Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether
9738 his painting infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day
9739 painter, using the tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web,
9740 must worry all the time. Images are all around, but the only safe images
9741 to use in the act of creation are those purchased from Corbis or another
9742 image farm. And in purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free
9743 market in pencils; we needn't worry about its effect on creativity. But
9744 there is a highly regulated, monopolized market in cultural icons; the
9745 right to cultivate and transform them is not similarly free.
9748 Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I
9749 described in chapter
9750 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"recorders"/>, in
9751 response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, I have
9752 been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was
9753 fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a
9758 <!-- PAGE BREAK 196 -->
9759 But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to
9760 defend your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system
9761 for defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad
—in
9762 practically every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it
9763 delivers too slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection
9764 to the justice underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable
9765 for the very rich. For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a
9766 tradition that prides itself on the rule of law.
9769 Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate
9770 <quote>breathing room
</quote> between regulation by the law and the access the law
9771 should allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system
9772 has become that anyone actually believes this. The rules that
9773 publishers impose upon writers, the rules that film distributors
9774 impose upon filmmakers, the rules that newspapers impose upon
9775 journalists
— these are the real laws governing creativity. And
9776 these rules have little relationship to the
<quote>law
</quote> with which judges
9780 For in a world that threatens $
150,
000 for a single willful
9781 infringement of a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of
9782 dollars to even defend against a copyright infringement claim, and
9783 which would never return to the wrongfully accused defendant anything
9784 of the costs she suffered to defend her right to speak
—in that
9785 world, the astonishingly broad regulations that pass under the name
9786 <quote>copyright
</quote> silence speech and creativity. And in that world, it takes
9787 a studied blindness for people to continue to believe they live in a
9788 culture that is free.
9791 As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me,
9795 We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people
9796 are being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being
9797 expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still
9798 won't get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made
… you're not
9799 going to get it distributed in the mainstream media unless
9800 <!-- PAGE BREAK 197 -->
9801 you've got a little note from a lawyer saying,
<quote>This has been
9802 cleared.
</quote> You're not even going to get it on PBS without that kind of
9803 permission. That's the point at which they control it.
9807 <section id=
"innovators">
9808 <title>Constraining Innovators
</title>
9809 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>innovation hampered by
</secondary></indexterm>
9810 <indexterm id='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='startofrange'
><primary>innovation
</primary><secondary>industry establishment opposed to
</secondary></indexterm>
9811 <indexterm id='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='startofrange'
><primary>regulation
</primary><secondary>as establishment protectionism
</secondary></indexterm>
9813 The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty
9814 story
—creativity quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada
9815 yada. Maybe that doesn't get you going. Maybe you think there's enough
9816 weird art out there, and enough expression that is critical of what
9817 seems to be just about everything. And if you think that, you might
9818 think there's little in this story to worry you.
9820 <indexterm id='idxmarketconstraints2' class='startofrange'
><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
9822 But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense.
9823 Indeed, it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme
9824 promarket ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special
9825 one at that,
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: pagenumber"
9826 linkend=
"innovators"/> pages into a book like this), then you
9827 can see this other aspect by substituting
<quote>free market
</quote>
9828 every place I've spoken of
<quote>free culture.
</quote> The point is
9829 the same, even if the interests affecting culture are more
9833 The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the
9834 same charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of
9835 course, concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary
—at
9836 a minimum, we need rules of property and contract, and courts to
9837 enforce both. Likewise, in this culture debate, everyone concedes that
9838 at least some framework of copyright is also required. But both
9839 perspectives vehemently insist that just because some regulation is
9840 good, it doesn't follow that more regulation is better. And both
9841 perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which regulation
9842 simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect themselves
9843 against the competitors of tomorrow.
9845 <indexterm startref='idxmarketconstraints2' class='endofrange'
/>
9846 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9847 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists
</primary></indexterm>
9849 This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory
9850 <!-- PAGE BREAK 198 -->
9851 strategy that I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select:
9852 labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>. The consequence of this massive
9853 threat of liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is
9854 that innovators who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate
9855 only if they have the sign-off from last generation's dominant
9856 industries. That lesson has been taught through a series of cases
9857 that were designed and executed to teach venture capitalists a
9858 lesson. That lesson
—what former Napster CEO Hank Barry calls a
9859 <quote>nuclear pall
</quote> that has fallen over the Valley
—has been learned.
9861 <indexterm><primary>Future of Ideas, The (Lessig)
</primary></indexterm>
9862 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary></indexterm>
9864 Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning
9865 I told in
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle> and which has progressed in a way that
9866 even I (pessimist extraordinaire) would never have predicted.
9868 <indexterm id='idxmpcom' class='startofrange'
><primary>MP3.com
</primary></indexterm>
9869 <indexterm id='idxmympcom' class='startofrange'
><primary>my.mp3.com
</primary></indexterm>
9870 <indexterm><primary>Roberts, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
9872 In
1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com
9873 was keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to
9874 facilitate new ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to
9875 facilitate new ways to create content. Unlike the major labels,
9876 MP3.com offered creators a venue to distribute their creativity,
9877 without demanding an exclusive engagement from the creators.
9879 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
9880 <indexterm id='idxcdsprefdata' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>preference data on
</secondary></indexterm>
9882 To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to
9883 recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to
9884 leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new
9885 artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie
9889 This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences.
9890 MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this
9891 preference data. In January
2000, the company launched a service
9892 called my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would
9893 sign into an account and then insert into her computer a CD. The
9894 software would identify the CD, and then give the user access to that
9895 content. So, for example, if you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then
9896 wherever you were
—at work or at home
—you could get access
9897 to that music once you signed into your account. The system was
9898 therefore a kind of music-lockbox.
9901 No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But
9902 that opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the
9904 <!-- PAGE BREAK 199 -->
9905 my.mp3.com service was to give users access to their own content, and
9906 as a by-product, by seeing the content they already owned, to discover
9907 the kind of content the users liked.
9909 <indexterm startref='idxcdsprefdata' class='endofrange'
/>
9911 To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy
50,
000
9912 CDs to a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who
9913 uploaded the music, but that would have taken a great deal of time,
9914 and would have produced a product of questionable quality.) It
9915 therefore purchased
50,
000 CDs from a store, and started the process
9916 of making copies of those CDs. Again, it would not serve the content
9917 from those copies to anyone except those who authenticated that they
9918 had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while this was
50,
000
9919 copies, it was
50,
000 copies directed at giving customers something
9920 they had already bought.
9922 <indexterm id='idxvivendiuniversal' class='startofrange'
><primary>Vivendi Universal
</primary></indexterm>
9923 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in
</secondary></indexterm>
9924 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>exaggerated claims of
</secondary></indexterm>
9925 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>in recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
9926 <indexterm><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits of
</secondary></indexterm>
9927 <indexterm><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>copyright infringement lawsuits filed by
</secondary></indexterm>
9928 <indexterm><primary>regulation
</primary><secondary>outsize penalties of
</secondary></indexterm>
9930 Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels,
9931 headed by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled
9932 with four of the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found
9933 MP3.com to have been guilty of willful infringement with respect to
9934 the fifth. Applying the law as it is, the judge imposed a fine against
9935 MP3.com of $
118 million. MP3.com then settled with the remaining
9936 plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over $
54 million. Vivendi
9937 purchased MP3.com just about a year later.
9940 That part of the story I have told before. Now consider its conclusion.
9943 After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a
9944 malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they
9945 had a good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be
9946 considered legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it
9947 should have been obvious that the courts would find this behavior
9948 illegal; therefore, this lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had
9949 dared to suggest that the law was less restrictive than the labels
9952 <indexterm startref='idxvivendiuniversal' class='endofrange'
/>
9954 The clear purpose of this lawsuit (which was settled for an
9955 unspecified amount shortly after the story was no longer covered in
9956 the press) was to send an unequivocal message to lawyers advising
9958 <!-- PAGE BREAK 200 -->
9959 space: It is not just your clients who might suffer if the content
9960 industry directs its guns against them. It is also you. So those of
9961 you who believe the law should be less restrictive should realize that
9962 such a view of the law will cost you and your firm dearly.
9964 <indexterm startref='idxmpcom' class='endofrange'
/>
9965 <indexterm startref='idxmympcom' class='endofrange'
/>
9966 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinfringementlawsuitsinrecordingindustry3' class='endofrange'
/>
9967 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9968 <indexterm><primary>copyright infringement lawsuits
</primary><secondary>distribution technology targeted in
</secondary></indexterm>
9969 <indexterm id='idxbmw' class='startofrange'
><primary>BMW
</primary></indexterm>
9970 <indexterm id='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>cars, MP3 sound systems in
</primary></indexterm>
9971 <indexterm><primary>EMI
</primary></indexterm>
9972 <indexterm><primary>Hummer, John
</primary></indexterm>
9973 <indexterm><primary>Barry, Hank
</primary></indexterm>
9974 <indexterm><primary>Hummer Winblad
</primary></indexterm>
9975 <indexterm><primary>MP3 players
</primary></indexterm>
9976 <indexterm><primary>Napster
</primary><secondary>venture capital for
</secondary></indexterm>
9977 <indexterm id='idxneedlemanrafe' class='startofrange'
><primary>Needleman, Rafe
</primary></indexterm>
9978 <indexterm><primary>Universal Music Group
</primary></indexterm>
9979 <indexterm><primary>venture capitalists
</primary></indexterm>
9981 This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April
2003,
9982 Universal and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the
9983 venture capital firm (VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of
9984 its development, its cofounder (John Hummer), and general partner
9985 (Hank Barry).
<footnote><para>
9987 See Joseph Menn,
<quote>Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9988 Times
</citetitle>,
23 April
2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on
9989 innovation in the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown,
<quote>The Music
9990 Revolution Will Not Be Digitized,
</quote> Salon.com,
1 June
2001, available
9991 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
42</ulink>.
9992 See also Jon Healey,
<quote>Online Music Services Besieged,
</quote> <citetitle>Los Angeles
9993 Times
</citetitle>,
28 May
2001.
9995 The claim here, as well, was that the VC should have recognized the
9996 right of the content industry to control how the industry should
9997 develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a company
9998 whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim of
9999 the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a
10000 company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at
10001 risk not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your
10002 investment buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit.
10003 So extreme has the environment become that even car manufacturers are
10004 afraid of technologies that touch content. In an article in
10005 <citetitle>Business
2.0</citetitle>, Rafe Needleman describes a
10006 discussion with BMW:
10010 I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in
10011 the car, there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW
10012 engineers in Germany had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via
10013 the car's built-in sound system, but that the company's marketing
10014 and legal departments weren't comfortable with pushing this
10015 forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are sold in the
10016 United States with bona fide MP3 players.
… <footnote>
10019 Rafe Needleman,
<quote>Driving in Cars with MP3s,
</quote> <citetitle>Business
2.0</citetitle>,
16 June
10021 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
43</ulink>. I am grateful
10022 to Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli for this example.
10023 <indexterm><primary>Needleman, Rafe
</primary></indexterm>
10027 <indexterm startref='idxbmw' class='endofrange'
/>
10028 <indexterm startref='idxcarsmpsoundsystemsin' class='endofrange'
/>
10029 <indexterm startref='idxneedlemanrafe' class='endofrange'
/>
10031 This is the world of the mafia
—filled with
<quote>your money or your
10032 life
</quote> offers, governed in the end not by courts but by the threats
10033 that the law empowers copyright holders to exercise. It is a system
10034 that will obviously and necessarily stifle new innovation. It is hard
10035 enough to start a company. It is impossibly hard if that company is
10036 constantly threatened by litigation.
10040 <!-- PAGE BREAK 201 -->
10041 The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal
10042 enterprises. The point is the definition of
<quote>illegal.
</quote> The law is a
10043 mess of uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply
10044 to new technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial
10045 deference, and by embracing the astonishingly high penalties that
10046 copyright law imposes, that uncertainty now yields a reality which is
10047 far more conservative than is right. If the law imposed the death
10048 penalty for parking tickets, we'd not only have fewer parking tickets,
10049 we'd also have much less driving. The same principle applies to
10050 innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this uncertain and
10051 unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation and
10052 much less creativity.
10054 <indexterm><primary>market constraints
</primary></indexterm>
10056 The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair
10057 use. Whatever the
<quote>real
</quote> law is, realism about the effect of law in
10058 both contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation
10059 will systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect
10060 some industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and
10061 creativity generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant
10062 competition. Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this
10063 kind of competition. The effect is to produce an overregulated
10064 culture, just as the effect of too much control in the market is to
10065 produce an overregulated-regulated market.
10068 The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is
10069 the first important way in which the changes I have described will
10070 burden innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's
10071 culture
—a culture in which the ability to create requires a call
10072 to your lawyer. Again, I am not antilawyer, at least when they're kept
10073 in their proper place. I am certainly not antilaw. But our profession
10074 has lost the sense of its limits. And leaders in our profession have
10075 lost an appreciation of the high costs that our profession imposes
10076 upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an embarrassment to our
10077 tradition. And while I believe our profession should therefore do
10078 everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at least
10079 do everything it can to limit the reach of the
10080 <!-- PAGE BREAK 202 -->
10081 law where the law is not doing any good. The transaction costs buried
10082 within a permission culture are enough to bury a wide range of
10083 creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of justifying to justify that
10087 <emphasis role='strong'
>The uncertainty
</emphasis> of the law is one
10088 burden on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more
10089 directly. This is the effort by many in the content industry to use
10090 the law to directly regulate the technology of the Internet so that it
10091 better protects their content.
10094 The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the
10095 efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the
10096 Internet's design. But from the perspective of the content industry,
10097 this feature is a
<quote>bug.
</quote> The efficient spread of content means that
10098 content distributors have a harder time controlling the distribution
10099 of content. One obvious response to this efficiency is thus to make
10100 the Internet less efficient. If the Internet enables
<quote>piracy,
</quote> then,
10101 this response says, we should break the kneecaps of the Internet.
10103 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
10105 The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of
10106 the content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that
10107 would require computers to determine whether the content they access
10108 is protected or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.
<footnote><para>
10109 <!-- f6. --> <quote>Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> GartnerG2 and
10110 the Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School
10111 (
2003),
33–35, available at
10112 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
44</ulink>.
10114 Congress has already launched proceedings to explore a mandatory
10115 <quote>broadcast flag
</quote> that would be required on any device capable of
10116 transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would disable
10117 the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast flag. Other
10118 members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers from
10119 liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down
10120 copyright violators and disable their machines.
<footnote><para>
10122 GartnerG2,
26–27.
10126 In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the
10127 code, why not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any
10128 regulation of technical infrastructure will always be tuned to the
10129 particular technology of the day. It will impose significant burdens
10131 <!-- PAGE BREAK 203 -->
10132 the technology, but will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly
10133 those requirements.
10135 <indexterm><primary>Intel
</primary></indexterm>
10137 In March
2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by
10138 Intel, tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation
10139 would impose.
<footnote><para>
10141 See David McGuire,
<quote>Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy,
</quote> Newsbytes,
10142 February
2002 (Entertainment).
10144 Their argument was obviously not that copyright should not be
10145 protected. Instead, they argued, any protection should not do more
10149 <emphasis role='strong'
>There is one
</emphasis> more obvious way in
10150 which this war has harmed innovation
—again, a story that will be
10151 quite familiar to the free market crowd.
10154 Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form
10155 of regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others.
10156 When done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done
10157 wrong, it is regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors.
10159 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
10160 <indexterm><primary>VCRs
</primary></indexterm>
10161 <indexterm><primary>statutory licenses
</primary></indexterm>
10162 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>statutory licenses in
</secondary></indexterm>
10164 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
10165 linkend=
"property-i"/>, despite this feature of copyright as
10166 regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by
10167 Jessica Litman in her book
<citetitle>Digital
10168 Copyright
</citetitle>,
<footnote><para>
10170 Jessica Litman,
<citetitle>Digital Copyright
</citetitle> (Amherst,
10171 N.Y.: Prometheus Books,
2001).
10172 <indexterm><primary>Digital Copyright (Litman)
</primary></indexterm>
10173 <indexterm><primary>Litman, Jessica
</primary></indexterm>
10175 overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter
10176 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/> details,
10177 when new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance
10178 to assure that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or
10179 statutory, licenses have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as
10180 in the case of the VCR) has been another.
10183 But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed
10184 with the rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between
10185 the claims of a new technology and the legitimate rights of content
10186 creators, both the courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions
10187 that will have the effect of smothering the new to benefit the old.
10189 <indexterm id='idxinternetradioon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>radio on
</secondary></indexterm>
10190 <indexterm id='idxradiooninternet' class='startofrange'
><primary>radio
</primary><secondary>on Internet
</secondary></indexterm>
10192 The response by the courts has been fairly universal.
<footnote><para>
10194 <indexterm><primary>Grokster, Ltd.
</primary></indexterm>
10195 The only circuit court exception is found in
<citetitle>Recording Industry
10196 Association of America (RIAA)
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Diamond Multimedia Systems
</citetitle>,
180 F.
3d
10197 1072 (
9th Cir.
1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit
10198 reasoned that makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for
10199 contributory copyright infringement for a device that is unable to
10200 record or redistribute music (a device whose only copying function is
10201 to render portable a music file already stored on a user's hard
10202 drive). At the district court level, the only exception is found in
10203 <citetitle>Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc
</citetitle>. v.
<citetitle>Grokster, Ltd
</citetitle>.,
259 F. Supp.
2d
10204 1029 (C.D. Cal.,
2003), where the court found the link between the
10205 distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to make the
10206 distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement
10209 It has been mirrored in the responses threatened and actually
10210 implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses
10211 here.
<footnote><para>
10213 <indexterm><primary>Tauzin, Billy
</primary></indexterm>
10214 <indexterm><primary>Berman, Howard L.
</primary></indexterm>
10215 <indexterm><primary>Hollings, Fritz
</primary></indexterm>
10216 <indexterm><primary>broadcast flag
</primary></indexterm>
10217 For example, in July
2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the
10218 Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R.
5211), which would immunize
10219 copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the
10220 copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In
10221 August
2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate
10222 that technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films
10223 broadcast on TV (i.e., computers) respect a
<quote>broadcast flag
</quote> that
10224 would disable copying of that content. And in March of the same year,
10225 Senator Fritz Hollings introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital
10226 Television Promotion Act, which mandated copyright protection
10227 technology in all digital media devices. See GartnerG2,
<quote>Copyright and
10228 Digital Media in a Post-Napster World,
</quote> 27 June
2003,
33–34,
10230 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
44</ulink>.
10232 But there is one example that captures the flavor of them all. This is
10233 the story of the demise of Internet radio.
10235 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10236 <indexterm><primary>Kennedy, John F.
</primary></indexterm>
10239 <!-- PAGE BREAK 204 -->
10240 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
10241 linkend=
"pirates"/>, when a radio station plays a song, the recording
10242 artist doesn't get paid for that
<quote>radio performance
</quote> unless he or she
10243 is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a
10244 version of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote>—to memorialize her famous
10245 performance before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden
—
10246 then whenever that recording was played on the radio, the current
10247 copyright owners of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> would get some money, whereas
10248 Marilyn Monroe would not.
10251 The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some
10252 sense. The justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The
10253 recording artist thus benefited because by playing her music, the
10254 radio station was making it more likely that her records would be
10255 purchased. Thus, the recording artist got something, even if only
10256 indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to do with the result
10257 than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists were quite good
10258 at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require compensation to the
10262 Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a
10263 technology to stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The
10264 broadcast travels across the Internet, not across the ether of radio
10265 spectrum. Thus, I can
<quote>tune in
</quote> to an Internet radio station in
10266 Berlin while sitting in San Francisco, even though there's no way for
10267 me to tune in to a regular radio station much beyond the San Francisco
10271 This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there
10272 are potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user
10273 could tune in to using her computer, whereas under the existing
10274 architecture for broadcast radio, there is an obvious limit to the
10275 number of broadcasters and clear broadcast frequencies. Internet radio
10276 could therefore be more competitive than regular radio; it could
10277 provide a wider range of selections. And because the potential
10278 audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche stations could
10279 easily develop and market their content to a relatively large number
10280 of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty
10281 million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio.
10283 <indexterm><primary>Armstrong, Edwin Howard
</primary></indexterm>
10286 <!-- PAGE BREAK 205 -->
10287 Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an
10288 improvement potentially vastly more significant than the FM
10289 improvement over AM, since not only is the technology better, so, too,
10290 is the competition. Indeed, there is a direct parallel between the
10291 fight to establish FM radio and the fight to protect Internet
10292 radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's struggle to enable
10297 An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the
10298 shortwaves, thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in
10299 the crowded longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of
10300 stations would be limited only by economics and competition rather
10301 than by technical restrictions.
… Armstrong likened the situation
10302 that had grown up in radio to that following the invention of the
10303 printing press, when governments and ruling interests attempted to
10304 control this new instrument of mass communications by imposing
10305 restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was broken only when it
10306 became possible for men freely to acquire printing presses and freely
10307 to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention as the
10308 printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its
10309 shackles.
<footnote><para>
10316 This potential for FM radio was never realized
—not
10317 because Armstrong was wrong about the technology, but because he
10318 underestimated the power of
<quote>vested interests, habits, customs and
10319 legislation
</quote><footnote><para>
10323 to retard the growth of this competing technology.
10326 Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For
10327 again, there is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of
10328 Internet radio stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are
10329 those imposed by the law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first
10330 question we should ask is, what copyright rules would govern Internet
10333 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10334 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on copyright laws
</secondary></indexterm>
10335 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on radio
</secondary></indexterm>
10336 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>on recording industry
</secondary></indexterm>
10337 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
10338 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>radio broadcast and
</secondary></indexterm>
10339 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>Internet radio hampered by
</secondary></indexterm>
10340 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees
</secondary></indexterm>
10341 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>lobbying power of
</secondary></indexterm>
10343 But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a
10344 new industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very
10346 <!-- PAGE BREAK 206 -->
10347 powerful lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon
10348 of Internet radio in
1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt
10349 a different rule for Internet radio than the rule that applies to
10350 terrestrial radio. While terrestrial radio does not have to pay our
10351 hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when it plays her hypothetical recording
10352 of
<quote>Happy Birthday
</quote> on the air,
<emphasis>Internet radio
10353 does
</emphasis>. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet
10354 radio
—the law actually burdens Internet radio more than it
10355 burdens terrestrial radio.
10358 This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor
10359 William Fisher estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree
10360 popular music to (on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four
10361 hours a day, the total artist fees that radio station would owe would be
10362 over $
1 million a year.
<footnote>
10365 This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright
10366 Arbitration Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an
10367 example offered by Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings,
10368 iLaw (Stanford),
3 July
2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher
10369 and Zittrain submitted testimony in the CARP proceeding that was
10370 ultimately rejected. See Jonathan Zittrain, Digital Performance Right
10371 in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral Recordings, Docket No.
2000-
9, CARP
10372 DTRA
1 and
2, available at
10373 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
45</ulink>.
10374 For an excellent analysis making a similar point, see Randal
10375 C. Picker,
<quote>Copyright as Entry Policy: The Case of Digital
10376 Distribution,
</quote> <citetitle>Antitrust Bulletin
</citetitle> (Summer/Fall
2002):
461:
<quote>This was
10377 not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry barriers. Analog
10378 radio stations are protected from digital entrants, reducing entry in
10379 radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of getting
10380 royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful
10381 interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way.
</quote>
10382 <indexterm><primary>CARP (Copyright Arbitration Royalty Panel)
</primary></indexterm>
10383 <indexterm><primary>Picker, Randal C.
</primary></indexterm>
10385 A regular radio station broadcasting the same content would pay no
10388 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto3' class='endofrange'
/>
10389 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin3' class='endofrange'
/>
10390 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryradiobroadcastand2' class='endofrange'
/>
10391 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees' class='endofrange'
/>
10392 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaalobbyingpowerof' class='endofrange'
/>
10394 The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were
10395 proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio
10396 station) would have to collect the following data from
<emphasis>every
10397 listening transaction
</emphasis>:
10399 <!-- PAGE BREAK 207 -->
10400 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
10402 name of the service;
10405 channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID);
10408 type of program (archived/looped/live);
10411 date of transmission;
10414 time of transmission;
10417 time zone of origination of transmission;
10420 numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program;
10423 duration of transmission (to nearest second);
10426 sound recording title;
10429 ISRC code of the recording;
10432 release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of the track;
10435 featured recording artist;
10438 retail album title;
10444 UPC code of the retail album;
10450 copyright owner information;
10453 musical genre of the channel or program (station format);
10456 name of the service or entity;
10459 channel or program;
10462 date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone);
10465 date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone);
10468 time zone where the signal was received (user);
10471 unique user identifier;
10474 the country in which the user received the transmissions.
10477 <indexterm><primary>Library of Congress
</primary></indexterm>
10479 The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting
10480 requirements, pending further study. And he also changed the original
10481 rates set by the arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the
10482 basic difference between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains:
10483 Internet radio has to pay a
<emphasis>type of copyright fee
</emphasis>
10484 that terrestrial radio does not.
10487 Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the
10488 economic consequences from Internet radio that would justify these
10489 differences? Was the motive to protect artists against piracy?
10491 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks
</primary></indexterm>
10492 <indexterm id='idxalbenalex2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
10493 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Recording Industry Association of America (RIAA)
</primary><secondary>on Internet radio fees
</secondary></indexterm>
10494 <indexterm id='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10495 <indexterm id='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='startofrange'
><primary>recording industry
</primary><secondary>artist remuneration in
</secondary></indexterm>
10497 In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious
10498 to everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public
10499 Policy at Real Networks, told me,
10503 The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented
10504 some testimony about what they thought a willing buyer would
10505 pay to a willing seller, and it was much higher. It was ten times
10506 higher than what radio stations pay to perform the same songs for
10507 the same period of time. And so the attorneys representing the
10508 webcasters asked the RIAA,
… <quote>How do you come up with a
10510 <!-- PAGE BREAK 208 -->
10511 rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because
10512 here we have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and
10513 that should establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so
10514 high, you're going to drive the small webcasters out of
10515 business.
…</quote>
10517 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
10519 And the RIAA experts said,
<quote>Well, we don't really model this as an
10520 industry with thousands of webcasters,
<emphasis>we think it should be
10521 an industry with, you know, five or seven big players who can pay a
10522 high rate and it's a stable, predictable market
</emphasis>.
</quote> (Emphasis
10526 <indexterm startref='idxalbenalex2' class='endofrange'
/>
10527 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryassociationofamericariaaoninternetradiofees2' class='endofrange'
/>
10528 <indexterm startref='idxartistsrecordingindustrypaymentsto4' class='endofrange'
/>
10529 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryartistremunerationin4' class='endofrange'
/>
10531 Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so
10532 that this platform of potentially immense competition, which would
10533 cause the diversity and range of content available to explode, would not
10534 cause pain to the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right
10535 or the left, who should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is
10536 practically no one, on either the right or the left, who is doing anything
10537 effective to prevent it.
10539 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawinnovationhamperedby' class='endofrange'
/>
10540 <indexterm startref='idxinnovationindustryestablishmentopposedto2' class='endofrange'
/>
10541 <indexterm startref='idxregulationasestablishmentprotectionism2' class='endofrange'
/>
10542 <indexterm startref='idxinternetradioon' class='endofrange'
/>
10543 <indexterm startref='idxradiooninternet' class='endofrange'
/>
10544 <indexterm startref='idxrecordingindustryinternetradiohamperedby' class='endofrange'
/>
10546 <section id=
"corruptingcitizens">
10547 <title>Corrupting Citizens
</title>
10549 Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives
10551 a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity
10552 for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables.
10555 In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was
10556 important to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation
10557 corrupts citizens and weakens the rule of law.
10560 The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with
10561 every war of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very
10562 large number of citizens. According to
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>,
43 million
10563 Americans downloaded music in May
2002.
<footnote><para>
10564 <!-- f15. --> Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie,
<quote>The Music Downloading Deluge,
</quote> Pew
10565 Internet and American Life Project (
24 April
2001), available at
10566 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
46</ulink>.
10567 The Pew Internet and American Life Project reported that
37 million
10568 Americans had downloaded music files from the Internet by early
2001.
10570 According to the RIAA,
10571 the behavior of those
43 million Americans is a felony. We thus have a
10572 set of rules that transform
20 percent of America into criminals. As the
10574 <!-- PAGE BREAK 209 -->
10575 RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of
10576 the world, but against students building search engines, and
10578 against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for
10579 sharing will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms
10580 race or a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more
10582 response by the other.
10585 The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American
10586 legal system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it
10587 knew that in Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The
10588 threat of having to pay either all the money in the world in damages
10589 ($
15,
000,
000) or almost all the money in the world to defend against
10590 paying all the money in the world in damages ($
250,
000 in legal fees)
10591 led Jordan to choose to pay all the money he had in the world
10592 ($
12,
000) to make the suit go away. The same strategy animates the
10593 RIAA's suits against individual users. In September
2003, the RIAA
10594 sued
261 individuals
—including a twelve-year-old girl living in public
10595 housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what file sharing
10596 was.
<footnote><para>
10598 Alex Pham,
<quote>The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case,
</quote> <citetitle>Los
10599 Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, Business.
10601 As these scapegoats discovered, it will always cost more to defend
10602 against these suits than it would cost to simply settle. (The twelve
10603 year old, for example, like Jesse Jordan, paid her life savings of $
2,
000
10604 to settle the case.) Our law is an awful system for defending rights. It
10605 is an embarrassment to our tradition. And the consequence of our law
10606 as it is, is that those with the power can use the law to quash any rights
10609 <indexterm><primary>alcohol prohibition
</primary></indexterm>
10611 Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just
10612 something more extreme than anything we've seen before. We
10613 experimented with alcohol prohibition, at a time when the per capita
10614 consumption of alcohol was
1.5 gallons per capita per year. The war
10615 against drinking initially reduced that consumption to just
30 percent
10616 of its preprohibition levels, but by the end of prohibition,
10617 consumption was up to
70 percent of the preprohibition
10618 level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast
10619 number were criminals.
<footnote><para>
10621 Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel,
<quote>Alcohol Consumption During
10622 Prohibition,
</quote> <citetitle>American Economic Review
</citetitle> 81, no.
2 (
1991):
242.
10625 <!-- PAGE BREAK 210 -->
10626 launched a war on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated
10627 narcotics that
7 percent (or
16 million) Americans now use.
<footnote><para>
10629 National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government
10630 Reform Committee,
108th Cong.,
1st sess. (
5 March
2003) (statement of
10631 John P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy).
10633 That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in
1979 of
14 percent of
10634 the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast
10635 majority of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex
10636 tax system that a majority of cash businesses regularly
10637 cheat.
<footnote><para>
10639 See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein,
<quote>Tax
10640 Compliance,
</quote> <citetitle>Journal of Economic Literature
</citetitle> 36 (
1998):
818 (survey of
10641 compliance literature).
10643 We pride ourselves on our
<quote>free society,
</quote> but an endless array of
10644 ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a result, a
10645 huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law.
10647 <indexterm><primary>law schools
</primary></indexterm>
10649 This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly
10650 salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law
10651 students about the importance of
<quote>ethics.
</quote> As my colleague Charlie
10652 Nesson told a class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands
10653 of students who have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed
10654 alcohol and sometimes drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes,
10655 illegally driven cars. These are kids for whom behaving illegally is
10656 increasingly the norm. And then we, as law professors, are supposed to
10657 teach them how to behave ethically
—how to say no to bribes, or
10658 keep client funds separate, or honor a demand to disclose a document
10659 that will mean that your case is over. Generations of
10660 Americans
—more significantly in some parts of America than in
10661 others, but still, everywhere in America today
—can't live their
10662 lives both normally and legally, since
<quote>normally
</quote> entails a certain
10663 degree of illegality.
10666 The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law
10667 more severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn
10668 how to make that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense
10669 depends, in part, at least, upon whether the costs of the law, both
10670 intended and collateral, outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended
10671 and collateral, do outweigh the benefits, then the law ought to be
10672 changed. Alternatively, if the costs of the existing system are much
10673 greater than the costs of an alternative, then we have a good reason
10674 to consider the alternative.
10678 <!-- PAGE BREAK 211 -->
10679 My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we
10680 should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics
10681 dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But
10682 that wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the
10683 week. A society is right to ban murder always and everywhere.
10686 My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations,
10687 but that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends
10688 upon people obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we
10689 as citizens experience violating the law, the less we respect the
10690 law. Obviously, in most cases, the important issue is the law, not
10691 respect for the law. I don't care whether the rapist respects the law
10692 or not; I want to catch and incarcerate the rapist. But I do care
10693 whether my students respect the law. And I do care if the rules of law
10694 sow increasing disrespect because of the extreme of regulation they
10695 impose. Twenty million Americans have come of age since the Internet
10696 introduced this different idea of
<quote>sharing.
</quote> We need to be able to
10697 call these twenty million Americans
<quote>citizens,
</quote> not
<quote>felons.
</quote>
10700 When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the
10701 Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways
10702 unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be
10703 asking is not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should
10704 be whether this particular prohibition is really necessary in order to
10705 achieve the proper ends that copyright law serves. Is there another
10706 way to assure that artists get paid without transforming forty-three
10707 million Americans into felons? Does it make sense if there are other
10708 ways to assure that artists get paid without transforming America into
10709 a nation of felons?
10712 This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example.
10715 We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces
10716 of plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The
10717 law protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a
10718 copyright infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a
10721 <!-- PAGE BREAK 212 -->
10722 record store and buy jazz records to replace them. That
<quote>use
</quote> of the
10723 recordings is free.
10726 But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of
10727 phonograph records that is effectively free. Because these recordings
10728 were made without copy-protection technologies, I am
<quote>free
</quote> to copy,
10729 or
<quote>rip,
</quote> music from my records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed,
10730 Apple Corporation went so far as to suggest that
<quote>freedom
</quote> was a
10731 right: In a series of commercials, Apple endorsed the
<quote>Rip, Mix, Burn
</quote>
10732 capacities of digital technologies.
10734 <indexterm><primary>Andromeda
</primary></indexterm>
10735 <indexterm id='idxcdsmix' class='startofrange'
><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>mix technology and
</secondary></indexterm>
10737 This
<quote>use
</quote> of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large
10738 process at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing
10739 them in one archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful
10740 program called Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our
10741 music: Bach, Baroque, Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant
10742 Others
—the potential is endless. And by reducing the costs of
10743 mixing play lists, these technologies help build a creativity with
10744 play lists that is itself independently valuable. Compilations of
10745 songs are creative and meaningful in their own right.
10748 This use is enabled by unprotected media
—either CDs or records.
10749 But unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens
10750 (or so the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn
10751 a fair return from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to
10752 experiment with technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These
10753 technologies, for example, would enable CDs that could not be
10754 ripped. Or they might enable spy programs to identify ripped content
10755 on people's machines.
10758 If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of
10759 your own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker
10760 circles, and get technology to disable the technologies that protect
10761 the content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that
10762 doesn't bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people,
10763 these protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving
10765 <!-- PAGE BREAK 213 -->
10766 use of CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to
10767 the world where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of
10768 plastic or were part of a massively complex
<quote>digital rights
10769 management
</quote> system.
10771 <indexterm startref='idxcdsmix' class='endofrange'
/>
10773 If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination
10774 of the ability to freely move content, then these technologies to
10775 interfere with the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But
10776 what if there were another way to assure that artists are paid,
10777 without locking down any content? What if, in other words, a different
10778 system could assure compensation to artists while also preserving the
10779 freedom to move content easily?
10782 My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer
10783 a version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now,
10784 the only point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different
10785 system achieved the same legitimate objectives that the existing
10786 copyright system achieved, but left consumers and creators much more
10787 free, then we'd have a very good reason to pursue this
10788 alternative
—namely, freedom. The choice, in other words, would
10789 not be between property and piracy; the choice would be between
10790 different property systems and the freedoms each allowed.
10793 I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without
10794 turning forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient
10795 feature of this alternative is that it would lead to a very different
10796 market for producing and distributing creativity. The dominant few,
10797 who today control the vast majority of the distribution of content in
10798 the world, would no longer exercise this extreme of control. Rather,
10799 they would go the way of the horse-drawn buggy.
10802 Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled
10803 Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this
10804 new form of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree
10805 million Americans as criminals and their own survival.
10808 It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not
10809 understandable why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack
10811 <!-- PAGE BREAK 214 -->
10813 Valenti is charming; but not so charming as to justify giving up a
10814 tradition as deep and important as our tradition of free culture.
10816 <indexterm><primary>Electronic Frontier Foundation
</primary></indexterm>
10817 <indexterm id='idxisps' class='startofrange'
><primary>ISPs (Internet service providers), user identities revealed by
</primary></indexterm>
10819 <emphasis role='strong'
>There's one more
</emphasis> aspect to this
10820 corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and
10821 follows directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier
10822 Foundation attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the
10823 <quote>collateral damage
</quote> that
<quote>arises whenever you turn
10824 a very large percentage of the population into criminals.
</quote> This
10825 is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally.
10827 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
10829 <quote>If you can treat someone as a putative lawbreaker,
</quote> von Lohmann
10834 then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections
10835 evaporate to one degree or another.
… If you're a copyright
10836 infringer, how can you hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a
10837 copyright infringer, how can you hope to be secure against seizures of
10838 your computer? How can you hope to continue to receive Internet
10839 access?
… Our sensibilities change as soon as we think,
<quote>Oh, well,
10840 but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker.
</quote> Well, what this campaign
10841 against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable percentage of the
10842 American Internet-using population into
<quote>lawbreakers.
</quote>
10846 And the consequence of this transformation of the American public
10847 into criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to
10848 effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume.
10851 Users of the Internet began to see this generally in
2003 as the RIAA
10852 launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over
10853 the names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright
10854 law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a
10855 judge, and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of
10856 an Internet user is revealed.
10859 <!-- PAGE BREAK 215 -->
10860 The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy
10861 to sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have
10862 downloaded copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've
10863 seen, the potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a
10864 family's computer is used to download a single CD's worth of music,
10865 the family could be liable for $
2 million in damages. That didn't stop
10866 the RIAA from suing a number of these families, just as they had sued
10867 Jesse Jordan.
<footnote><para>
10869 See Frank Ahrens,
<quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single
10870 Mother in Calif.,
12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants,
</quote>
10871 <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, E1; Chris Cobbs,
<quote>Worried Parents
10872 Pull Plug on File `Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on
10873 File Swapping, Parents are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid
10874 Being Sued,
</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune
</citetitle>,
30 August
2003, C1; Jefferson
10875 Graham,
<quote>Recording Industry Sues Parents,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
15 September
10876 2003,
4D; John Schwartz,
<quote>She Says She's No Music Pirate. No Snoop
10877 Fan, Either,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
25 September
2003, C1; Margo Varadi,
<quote>Is
10878 Brianna a Criminal?
</quote> <citetitle>Toronto Star
</citetitle>,
18 September
2003, P7.
10883 Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the
10884 RIAA. A report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the
10885 RIAA had adopted to track Napster users.
<footnote><para>
10887 See
<quote>Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses
10888 Some Methods Used,
</quote> CNN.com, available at
10889 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
47</ulink>.
10891 Using a sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in
10892 effect a fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of
10893 one of those MP3s will have the same
<quote>fingerprint.
</quote>
10896 So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a
10897 friend gives a CD to your daughter
—a collection of songs just
10898 like the cassettes you used to make as a kid. You don't know, and
10899 neither does your daughter, where these songs came from. But she
10900 copies these songs onto her computer. She then takes her computer to
10901 college and connects it to a college network, and if the college
10902 network is
<quote>cooperating
</quote> with the RIAA's espionage, and she hasn't
10903 properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to do
10904 that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter
10905 as a
<quote>criminal.
</quote> And under the rules that universities are beginning
10906 to deploy,
<footnote><para>
10908 See Jeff Adler,
<quote>Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent,
</quote>
10909 <citetitle>Boston Globe
</citetitle>,
18 May
2003, City Weekly,
1; Frank Ahrens,
<quote>Four
10910 Students Sued over Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at
10911 Colleges,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
4 April
2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong,
10912 <quote>Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at Their Own Risk,
</quote> <citetitle>Christian Science
10913 Monitor
</citetitle>,
2 September
2003,
20; Robert Becker and Angela Rozas,
<quote>Music
10914 Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students Names Are Handed Over;
10915 Lawsuit Possible,
</quote> <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
16 July
2003,
1C; Beth Cox,
<quote>RIAA
10916 Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities,
</quote> <citetitle>Internet News
</citetitle>,
30 January
10917 2003, available at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link
10918 #
48</ulink>; Benny Evangelista,
<quote>Download Warning
101: Freshman
10919 Orientation This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File
10920 Sharing,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
11 August
2003, E11;
<quote>Raid, Letters
10921 Are Weapons at Universities,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
26 September
2000,
3D.
10923 your daughter can lose the right to use the university's computer
10924 network. She can, in some cases, be expelled.
10926 <indexterm startref='idxisps' class='endofrange'
/>
10927 <indexterm><primary>von Lohmann, Fred
</primary></indexterm>
10929 Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire
10930 a lawyer for her (at $
300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can
10931 plead that she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or
10932 that they came from Napster. And it may well be that the university
10933 believes her. But the university might not believe her. It might treat
10934 this
<quote>contraband
</quote> as presumptive of guilt. And as any number of
10937 <!-- PAGE BREAK 216 -->
10938 have already learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in
10939 the middle of wars of prohibition. This war is no different.
10944 So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million
10945 Americans that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a
10946 situation where the civil liberties of those people are very much in
10947 peril in a general matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where
10948 you could randomly choose any person off the street and be confident
10949 that they were committing an unlawful act that could put them on the
10950 hook for potential felony liability or hundreds of millions of dollars
10951 of civil liability. Certainly we all speed, but speeding isn't the
10952 kind of an act for which we routinely forfeit civil liberties. Some
10953 people use drugs, and I think that's the closest analog, [but] many
10954 have noted that the war against drugs has eroded all of our civil
10955 liberties because it's treated so many Americans as criminals. Well, I
10956 think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of magnitude
10957 larger number of Americans than drug use.
… If forty to sixty
10958 million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a
10959 slippery slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty
10964 When forty to sixty million Americans are considered
<quote>criminals
</quote> under
10965 the law, and when the law could achieve the same objective
—
10966 securing rights to authors
—without these millions being
10967 considered
<quote>criminals,
</quote> who is the villain? Americans or the law?
10968 Which is American, a constant war on our own people or a concerted
10969 effort through our democracy to change our law?
10972 <!-- PAGE BREAK 217 -->
10976 <part id=
"c-balances">
10977 <title>BALANCES
</title>
10980 <!-- PAGE BREAK 218 -->
10982 <emphasis role='strong'
>So here's
</emphasis> the picture: You're
10983 standing at the side of the road. Your car is on fire. You are angry
10984 and upset because in part you helped start the fire. Now you don't
10985 know how to put it out. Next to you is a bucket, filled with
10986 gasoline. Obviously, gasoline won't put the fire out.
10989 As you ponder the mess, someone else comes along. In a panic, she
10990 grabs the bucket. Before you have a chance to tell her to
10991 stop
—or before she understands just why she should
10992 stop
—the bucket is in the air. The gasoline is about to hit the
10993 blazing car. And the fire that gasoline will ignite is about to ignite
10997 <emphasis role='strong'
>A war
</emphasis> about copyright rages all
10998 around
—and we're all focusing on the wrong thing. No doubt,
10999 current technologies threaten existing businesses. No doubt they may
11000 threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry and
11001 technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect
11002 themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire
11003 that if let alone would burn itself out.
11006 <!-- PAGE BREAK 219 -->
11007 Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed
11008 with plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to
11009 eliminate the problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is
11010 not the real threat this culture faces. For while we watch this small
11011 fire in the corner, there is a massive change in the way culture is
11012 made that is happening all around.
11015 Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important
11016 and fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring
11017 gasoline onto this fire.
11020 We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler,
11021 binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more
11022 broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to
11023 look at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road.
11026 This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been
11027 my failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small
11028 brace of efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this
11029 debate. We must understand these failures if we're to understand what
11030 success will require.
11034 <!-- PAGE BREAK 220 -->
11035 <chapter label=
"13" id=
"eldred">
11036 <title>Eldred
</title>
11037 <indexterm id='idxeldrederic' class='startofrange'
><primary>Eldred, Eric
</primary></indexterm>
11038 <indexterm id='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='startofrange'
><primary>Hawthorne, Nathaniel
</primary></indexterm>
11040 <emphasis role='strong'
>In
1995</emphasis>, a father was frustrated
11041 that his daughters didn't seem to like Hawthorne. No doubt there was
11042 more than one such father, but at least one did something about
11043 it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in New
11044 Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version,
11045 Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would
11046 make this nineteenth-century author's work come alive.
11048 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='startofrange'
><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>of public-domain literature
</secondary></indexterm>
11049 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>library of works derived from
</secondary></indexterm>
11051 It didn't work
—at least for his daughters. They didn't find
11052 Hawthorne any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment
11053 gave birth to a hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build
11054 a library of public domain works by scanning these works and making
11055 them available for free.
11057 <indexterm id='idxdisneywalt5' class='startofrange'
><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
11058 <indexterm><primary>Grimm fairy tales
</primary></indexterm>
11060 Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain
11061 works, though even a copy would have been of great value to people
11062 across the world who can't get access to printed versions of these
11063 works. Instead, Eldred was producing derivative works from these
11064 public domain works. Just as Disney turned Grimm into stories more
11065 <!-- PAGE BREAK 221 -->
11066 accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred transformed Hawthorne, and
11067 many others, into a form more accessible
—technically
11068 accessible
—today.
11070 <indexterm><primary>Scarlet Letter, The (Hawthorne)
</primary></indexterm>
11072 Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same
11073 source as Disney's. Hawthorne's
<citetitle>Scarlet Letter
</citetitle> had passed into the
11074 public domain in
1907. It was free for anyone to take without the
11075 permission of the Hawthorne estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover
11076 Press and Penguin Classics, take works from the public domain and
11077 produce printed editions, which they sell in bookstores across the
11078 country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories and turn them into
11079 animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (
<citetitle>Cinderella
</citetitle>), sometimes not
11080 (
<citetitle>The Hunchback of Notre Dame
</citetitle>,
<citetitle>Treasure Planet
</citetitle>). These are all
11081 commercial publications of public domain works.
11083 <indexterm startref='idxhawthornenathaniel' class='endofrange'
/>
11084 <indexterm startref='idxdisneywalt5' class='endofrange'
/>
11086 The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of
11087 public domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally
11088 thousands of others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have
11089 discovered this platform of expression and now use it to share works
11090 that are, by law, free for the taking. This has produced what we might
11091 call the
<quote>noncommercial publishing industry,
</quote> which before the
11092 Internet was limited to people with large egos or with political or
11093 social causes. But with the Internet, it includes a wide range of
11094 individuals and groups dedicated to spreading culture
11095 generally.
<footnote><para>
11097 <indexterm><primary>pornography
</primary></indexterm>
11098 There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to
11099 describe, but it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet
11100 created was a world of noncommercial pornographers
—people who
11101 were distributing porn but were not making money directly or
11102 indirectly from that distribution. Such a class didn't exist before
11103 the Internet came into being because the costs of distributing porn
11104 were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got special attention
11105 in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the Communications
11106 Decency Act of
1996. It was partly because of the burden on
11107 noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's
11108 power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial
11109 publishers after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the
11110 world before the Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it
11111 at least as important to protect the Eldreds of the world as to
11112 protect noncommercial pornographers.
</para></footnote>
11114 <indexterm id='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>copyright terms extended by
</secondary></indexterm>
11115 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
11116 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>term extensions in
</secondary></indexterm>
11117 <indexterm><primary>Frost, Robert
</primary></indexterm>
11118 <indexterm><primary>New Hampshire (Frost)
</primary></indexterm>
11119 <indexterm><primary>patents
</primary><secondary>in public domain
</secondary></indexterm>
11120 <indexterm id='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>patents
</primary><secondary>future patents vs. future copyrights in
</secondary></indexterm>
11122 As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In
1998, Robert Frost's
11123 collection of poems
<citetitle>New Hampshire
</citetitle> was slated to
11124 pass into the public domain. Eldred wanted to post that collection in
11125 his free public library. But Congress got in the way. As I described
11126 in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
11127 linkend=
"property-i"/>, in
1998, for the eleventh time in forty years,
11128 Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights
—this time by
11129 twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent
11130 than
1923 to his collection until
2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work
11131 would pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then,
11132 if Congress extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period,
11133 more than
1 million patents will pass into the public domain.
11135 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesofpublicdomainliterature' class='endofrange'
/>
11136 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlibraryofworksderivedfrom' class='endofrange'
/>
11137 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary
</primary></indexterm>
11138 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny
</primary></indexterm>
11139 <indexterm id='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='startofrange'
><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>in perpetuity
</secondary></indexterm>
11140 <indexterm id='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (
1998)
</primary></indexterm>
11143 <!-- PAGE BREAK 222 -->
11144 This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act
11145 (CTEA), enacted in memory of the congressman and former musician
11146 Sonny Bono, who, his widow, Mary Bono, says, believed that
11147 <quote>copyrights should be forever.
</quote><footnote><para>
11149 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Mary
</primary></indexterm>
11150 <indexterm><primary>Bono, Sonny
</primary></indexterm>
11151 The full text is:
<quote>Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright
11152 protection to last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change
11153 would violate the Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to
11154 strengthen our copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As
11155 you know, there is also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last
11156 forever less one day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next
11157 Congress,
</quote> 144 Cong. Rec. H9946,
9951-
2 (October
7,
1998).
11160 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsfuturepatentsvsfuturecopyrightsin' class='endofrange'
/>
11161 <indexterm><primary>copyright law
</primary><secondary>felony punishment for infringement of
</secondary></indexterm>
11162 <indexterm><primary>NET (No Electronic Theft) Act (
1998)
</primary></indexterm>
11163 <indexterm><primary>No Electronic Theft (NET) Act (
1998)
</primary></indexterm>
11164 <indexterm><primary>peer-to-peer (p2p) file sharing
</primary><secondary>felony punishments for
</secondary></indexterm>
11166 Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through
11167 civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he
11168 would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a
11169 second law passed in
1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act
11170 of publishing would make Eldred a felon
—whether or not anyone
11171 complained. This was a dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer
11174 <indexterm startref='idxsonnybonocopyrighttermextensionactctea2' class='endofrange'
/>
11175 <indexterm id='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of
</secondary></indexterm>
11176 <indexterm id='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>Progress Clause of
</secondary></indexterm>
11177 <indexterm id='idxprogressclause2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Progress Clause
</primary></indexterm>
11178 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of
</secondary></indexterm>
11180 It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a
11182 scholar whose first passion was constitutional
11184 And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the
11185 Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as
11187 different. As you know, the Constitution says,
11191 Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science
…
11192 by securing for limited Times to Authors
… exclusive Right to
11193 their
… Writings.
…
11196 <indexterm startref='idxeldrederic' class='endofrange'
/>
11198 As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting
11199 clause of Article I, section
8 of our Constitution. Every other clause
11200 granting power to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do
11201 something
—for example, to regulate
<quote>commerce among the several
11202 states
</quote> or
<quote>declare War.
</quote> But here, the
<quote>something
</quote> is something quite
11203 specific
—to
<quote>promote
… Progress
</quote>—through means that
11204 are also specific
— by
<quote>securing
</quote> <quote>exclusive Rights
</quote> (i.e.,
11205 copyrights)
<quote>for limited Times.
</quote>
11207 <indexterm startref='idxconstitutionusprogressclauseof2' class='endofrange'
/>
11208 <indexterm startref='idxprogressclause2' class='endofrange'
/>
11209 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceeldredcaseinvolvementof' class='endofrange'
/>
11210 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
11212 In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of
11213 extending existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me
11214 about this was, if Congress has the power to extend existing terms,
11215 then the Constitution's requirement that terms be
<quote>limited
</quote> will have
11216 <!-- PAGE BREAK 223 -->
11217 no practical effect. If every time a copyright is about to expire,
11218 Congress has the power to extend its term, then Congress can achieve
11219 what the Constitution plainly forbids
—perpetual terms
<quote>on the
11220 installment plan,
</quote> as Professor Peter Jaszi so nicely put it.
11222 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightinperpetuity4' class='endofrange'
/>
11223 <indexterm startref='idxcongressusconstitutionalpowersof' class='endofrange'
/>
11224 <indexterm><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary><secondary>Eldred case involvement of
</secondary></indexterm>
11226 As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember
11227 sitting late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious
11228 consideration of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's
11229 practice of extending existing terms. That failure may in part be why
11230 Congress seemed so untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that
11231 the practice had become so lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that
11232 copyright owners will be willing to pay a great deal of money to see
11233 their copyright terms extended. And so Congress is quite happy to keep
11234 this gravy train going.
11237 For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of
11238 government.
<quote>Corruption
</quote> not in the sense that representatives are
11239 bribed. Rather,
<quote>corruption
</quote> in the sense that the system induces the
11240 beneficiaries of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress
11241 to induce it to act. There's only so much time; there's only so much
11242 Congress can do. Why not limit its actions to those things it must
11243 do
—and those things that pay? Extending copyright terms pays.
11246 If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one
11247 of the very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to
11248 make money one hundred years after it was created. The Estate of
11249 Robert Frost is a good example. Frost died in
1963. His poetry
11250 continues to be extraordinarily valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate
11251 benefits greatly from any extension of copyright, since no publisher
11252 would pay the estate any money if the poems Frost wrote could be
11253 published by anyone for free.
11256 So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $
100,
000 a year from
11257 three of Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems
11258 is about to expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate.
11259 Your financial adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim
11263 <quote>Next year,
</quote> the adviser announces,
<quote>our copyrights in works A, B,
11265 <!-- PAGE BREAK 224 -->
11266 and C will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be
11267 receiving the annual royalty check of $
100,
000 from the publishers of
11268 those works.
</quote>
11271 <quote>There's a proposal in Congress, however,
</quote> she continues,
<quote>that
11272 could change this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the
11273 terms of copyright by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily
11274 valuable to us. So we should hope this bill passes.
</quote>
11277 <quote>Hope?
</quote> a fellow board member says.
<quote>Can't we be doing something
11281 <quote>Well, obviously, yes,
</quote> the adviser responds.
<quote>We could contribute
11282 to the campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that
11283 they support the bill.
</quote>
11286 You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want
11287 to know whether this disgusting practice is worth it.
<quote>How much
11288 would we get if this extension were passed?
</quote> you ask the adviser.
<quote>How
11289 much is it worth?
</quote>
11292 <quote>Well,
</quote> the adviser says,
<quote>if you're confident that you will continue
11293 to get at least $
100,
000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the
11294 `discount rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (
6 percent),
11295 then this law would be worth $
1,
146,
000 to the estate.
</quote>
11298 You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the
11299 correct conclusion:
11302 <quote>So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than
11303 $
1,
000,
000 in campaign contributions if we were confident those
11305 would assure that the bill was passed?
</quote>
11308 <quote>Absolutely,
</quote> the adviser responds.
<quote>It is worth it to you to
11310 up to the `present value' of the income you expect from these
11311 copyrights. Which for us means over $
1,
000,
000.
</quote>
11314 You quickly get the point
—you as the member of the board and, I
11315 trust, you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every
11316 beneficiary in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same
11317 choice: If they can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights,
11318 <!-- PAGE BREAK 225 -->
11319 they will benefit greatly from that extension. And so each time
11321 are about to expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get
11322 the copyright term extended.
11325 Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation
11326 can be bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in
11327 the world to buy further extensions of copyright.
11330 In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono
11332 Term Extension Act, this
<quote>theory
</quote> about incentives was proved
11333 real. Ten of the thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House
11334 received the maximum contribution from Disney's political action
11335 committee; in the Senate, eight of the twelve sponsors received
11336 contributions.
<footnote><para>
11337 <!-- f3. --> Associated Press,
<quote>Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey
11338 Mouse Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators
20 More Years,
</quote>
11339 <citetitle>Chicago Tribune
</citetitle>,
17 October
1998,
22.
11341 The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over
11342 $
1.5 million lobbying in the
1998 election cycle. They paid out more
11343 than $
200,
000 in campaign contributions.
<footnote><para>
11344 <!-- f4. --> See Nick Brown,
<quote>Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information
11345 Age,
</quote> available at
11346 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
49</ulink>.
11348 Disney is estimated to have
11349 contributed more than $
800,
000 to reelection campaigns in the
11350 cycle.
<footnote><para>
11352 Alan K. Ota,
<quote>Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars,
</quote>
11353 <citetitle>Congressional Quarterly This Week
</citetitle>,
8 August
1990, available at
11354 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
50</ulink>.
11359 <emphasis role='strong'
>Constitutional law
</emphasis> is not oblivious
11360 to the obvious. Or at least, it need not be. So when I was considering
11361 Eldred's complaint, this reality about the never-ending incentives to
11362 increase the copyright term was central to my thinking. In my view, a
11363 pragmatic court committed to interpreting and applying the
11364 Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the power
11365 to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective
11366 constitutional requirement that terms be
<quote>limited.
</quote> If
11367 they could extend it once, they would extend it again and again and
11370 <indexterm startref='idxcongressuscopyrighttermsextendedby2' class='endofrange'
/>
11371 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightdurationof6' class='endofrange'
/>
11372 <indexterm startref='idxcopyrightlawtermextensionsin2' class='endofrange'
/>
11374 It was also my judgment that
<emphasis>this
</emphasis> Supreme Court
11375 would not allow Congress to extend existing terms. As anyone close to
11376 the Supreme Court's work knows, this Court has increasingly restricted
11377 the power of Congress when it has viewed Congress's actions as
11378 exceeding the power granted to it by the Constitution. Among
11379 constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this trend was the
11382 <!-- PAGE BREAK 226 -->
11383 decision in
1995 to strike down a law that banned the possession of
11387 Since
1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted
11388 powers very broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the
11389 power to regulate only
<quote>commerce among the several states
</quote> (aka
11391 commerce
</quote>), the Supreme Court had interpreted that power to
11392 include the power to regulate any activity that merely affected
11397 As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was
11398 no limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every
11399 activity, when considered on a national scale, affects interstate
11400 commerce. A Constitution designed to limit Congress's power was
11401 instead interpreted to impose no limit.
11403 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.
</primary></indexterm>
11405 The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed
11406 that in
<citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. The government had
11407 argued that possessing guns near schools affected interstate
11408 commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, crime lowers property
11409 values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief Justice asked the
11410 government whether there was any activity that would not affect
11411 interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The
11412 government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects
11413 interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate
11414 commerce. The Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the
11415 position to second-guess Congress.
11418 <quote>We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments,
</quote>
11419 the Chief Justice wrote.
<footnote><para>
11420 <!-- f6. --> <citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>,
514 U.S.
549,
564 (
1995).
11422 If anything Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be
11423 considered interstate commerce, then there would be no limit to
11424 Congress's power. The decision in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> was reaffirmed five years
11425 later in
<citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Morrison
</citetitle>.
<footnote><para>
11427 <citetitle>United States
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Morrison
</citetitle>,
529 U.S.
598 (
2000).
11431 If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress
11432 Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.
<footnote><para>
11434 If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle
11435 carries from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in
11436 the context of the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered
11437 by the government would allow the government unending power to
11438 regulate commerce
—the limitation to interstate commerce
11439 notwithstanding. The same point is true in the context of the
11440 Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's interpretation would
11441 allow the government unending power to regulate copyrights
—the
11442 limitation to
<quote>limited times
</quote> notwithstanding.
11444 And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should
11445 yield the conclusion that Congress
11446 <!-- PAGE BREAK 227 -->
11447 can't extend an existing term. If Congress could extend an existing
11448 term, then there would be no
<quote>stopping point
</quote> to Congress's power over
11449 terms, though the Constitution expressly states that there is such a
11450 limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to grant
11451 copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the
11452 term of existing copyrights.
11455 <emphasis>If
</emphasis>, that is, the principle announced in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>
11456 stood for a principle. Many believed the decision in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> stood for
11457 politics
—a conservative Supreme Court, which believed in states'
11458 rights, using its power over Congress to advance its own personal
11459 political preferences. But I rejected that view of the Supreme Court's
11460 decision. Indeed, shortly after the decision, I wrote an article
11461 demonstrating the
<quote>fidelity
</quote> in such an interpretation of the
11462 Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides cases based upon
11463 its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was not going to
11464 devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine Justices
11465 were going to be petty politicians.
11467 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>copyright purpose established in
</secondary></indexterm>
11468 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>constitutional purpose of
</secondary></indexterm>
11469 <indexterm><primary>copyright
</primary><secondary>duration of
</secondary></indexterm>
11470 <indexterm><primary>Disney, Walt
</primary></indexterm>
11472 <emphasis role='strong'
>Now let's pause
</emphasis> for a moment to
11473 make sure we understand what the argument in
11474 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was not about. By insisting on the
11475 Constitution's limits to copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing
11476 piracy. Indeed, in an obvious sense, he was fighting a kind of
11477 piracy
—piracy of the public domain. When Robert Frost wrote his
11478 work and when Walt Disney created Mickey Mouse, the maximum copyright
11479 term was just fifty-six years. Because of interim changes, Frost and
11480 Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year monopoly for their
11481 work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the Constitution
11482 envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six years,
11483 they created new work. But now these entities were using their
11484 power
—expressed through the power of lobbyists' money
—to
11485 get another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop
11486 would be taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a
11487 piracy that affects us all.
11489 <indexterm><primary>Nashville Songwriters Association
</primary></indexterm>
11491 Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief
11493 <!-- PAGE BREAK 228 -->
11494 before the Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association
11495 wrote that the public domain is nothing more than
<quote>legal piracy.
</quote><footnote><para>
11497 Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle>
11498 v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618), n
.10, available
11499 at
<ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
51</ulink>.
11501 But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our constitutional
11502 system, our law requires it. Some may not like the Constitution's
11503 requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a pirate's
11507 As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on
11509 as a way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily
11511 the development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric
11512 Eldred discovered, we have set up a system that assures that copyright
11513 terms will be repeatedly extended, and extended, and extended. We
11514 have created the perfect storm for the public domain. Copyrights have
11515 not expired, and will not expire, so long as Congress is free to be
11516 bought to extend them again.
11519 <emphasis role='strong'
>It is valuable
</emphasis> copyrights that are
11520 responsible for terms being extended. Mickey Mouse and
11521 <quote>Rhapsody in Blue.
</quote> These works are too valuable for
11522 copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from
11523 copyright extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's.
11524 Forget Mickey Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from
11525 the
1920s and
1930s that have continuing commercial value. The real
11526 harm of term extension comes not from these famous works. The real
11527 harm is to the works that are not famous, not commercially exploited,
11528 and no longer available as a result.
11531 If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (
1923 to
11532 1942) affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act,
11533 2 percent of that work has any continuing commercial value. It was the
11534 copyright holders for that
2 percent who pushed the CTEA through.
11535 But the law and its effect were not limited to that
2 percent. The law
11536 extended the terms of copyright generally.
<footnote><para>
11537 <!-- f10. --> The figure of
2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the
11539 Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal ranges. See Brief
11540 of Petitioners,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
7, available at
11541 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
52</ulink>.
11546 Think practically about the consequence of this
11547 extension
—practically,
11548 as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal
11550 <!-- PAGE BREAK 229 -->
11551 work. In
1930,
10,
047 books were published. In
2000,
174 of those
11552 books were still in print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you
11553 wanted to make available to the world in your iArchive project the
11555 9,
873. What would you have to do?
11557 <indexterm><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
11559 Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the
9,
873 books were
11560 still under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are
11561 not on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the
11562 titles and authors of the
9,
873 books with the copyright registration
11563 and renewal records for works published in
1930. That will produce a
11564 list of books still under copyright.
11567 Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate
11568 the current copyright owners. How would you do that?
11571 Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright
11573 somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be
11574 thousands and thousands of government monopolies without there
11575 being at least a list?
11578 But there is no list. There may be a name from
1930, and then in
11579 1959, of the person who registered the copyright. But just think
11581 about how impossibly difficult it would be to track down
11583 of such records
—especially since the person who registered is
11584 not necessarily the current owner. And we're just talking about
1930!
11587 <quote>But there isn't a list of who owns property generally,
</quote> the
11588 apologists for the system respond.
<quote>Why should there be a list of
11589 copyright owners?
</quote>
11592 Well, actually, if you think about it, there
<emphasis>are
</emphasis>
11593 plenty of lists of who owns what property. Think about deeds on
11594 houses, or titles to cars. And where there isn't a list, the code of
11595 real space is pretty good at suggesting who the owner of a bit of
11596 property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably yours.) So
11597 formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who owns
11598 what tangible property.
11601 So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who
11602 owns the house by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see
11603 a car, there is ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the
11605 <!-- PAGE BREAK 230 -->
11606 car. If you see a bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a
11607 house, it's fairly easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you
11609 to see a baseball lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look
11610 around for a second for some kids playing ball. If you don't see any
11611 kids, then okay: Here's a bit of property whose owner we can't easily
11612 determine. It is the exception that proves the rule: that we ordinarily
11613 know quite well who owns what property.
11616 Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library.
11617 The library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've
11619 described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors'
11620 names, of course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or
11621 passed down in an estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who
11622 owns what, you would have to hire a private detective. The bottom
11623 line: The owner cannot easily be located. And in a regime like ours, in
11624 which it is a felony to use such property without the property owner's
11625 permission, the property isn't going to be used.
11628 The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be
11629 digitized, and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the
11631 for other creative works is much more dire.
11633 <indexterm id='idxageemichael' class='startofrange'
><primary>Agee, Michael
</primary></indexterm>
11634 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios
</primary></indexterm>
11635 <indexterm><primary>Laurel and Hardy Films
</primary></indexterm>
11636 <indexterm><primary>Lucky Dog, The
</primary></indexterm>
11638 Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios,
11639 which owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a
11640 direct beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were
11641 made between
1921 and
1951. Only one of these films,
<citetitle>The Lucky Dog
</citetitle>, is
11642 currently out of copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after
1923
11643 would have begun entering the public domain. Because Agee controls the
11644 exclusive rights for these popular films, he makes a great deal of
11645 money. According to one estimate,
<quote>Roach has sold about
60,
000
11646 videocassettes and
50,
000 DVDs of the duo's silent
11647 films.
</quote><footnote><para>
11649 See David G. Savage,
<quote>High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law,
</quote>
11650 <citetitle>Los Angeles Times
</citetitle>,
6 October
2002; David Streitfeld,
<quote>Classic Movies,
11651 Songs, Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking
11652 Down Copyright Extension,
</quote> <citetitle>Orlando Sentinel Tribune
</citetitle>,
9 October
2002.
11656 Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in
11657 this culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme
11658 Court that the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left
11659 standing, destroy a whole generation of American film.
11662 His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has
11664 <!-- PAGE BREAK 231 -->
11665 any continuing commercial value. The rest
—to the extent it
11666 survives at all
—sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that
11667 some of this work not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be
11668 valuable by the owners of the vaults. For this to occur, however, the
11669 commercial benefit from the work must exceed the costs of making the
11670 work available for distribution.
11673 We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs.
11674 For most of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very
11675 high; digital technology has lowered these costs substantially. While
11676 it cost more than $
10,
000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white
11677 film in
1993, it can now cost as little as $
100 to digitize one hour of
11678 8 mm film.
<footnote><para>
11680 Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae
11681 Supporting the Petitoners,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537
11682 U.S.
186 (
2003) (No.
01-
618),
12. See also Brief of Amicus Curiae
11683 filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet Archive,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle>
11684 v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>, available at
11685 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
53</ulink>.
11690 Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most
11692 Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In
11693 addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights.
11694 And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to
11695 locate the copyright owner.
11698 Or more accurately,
<emphasis>owners
</emphasis>. As we've seen, there
11699 isn't only a single copyright associated with a film; there are
11700 many. There isn't a single person whom you can contact about those
11701 copyrights; there are as many as can hold the rights, which turns out
11702 to be an extremely large number. Thus the costs of clearing the rights
11703 to these films is exceptionally high.
11706 <quote>But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the
11707 copyright owner when she shows up?
</quote> Sure, if you want to commit a
11708 felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when
11709 she does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you
11710 have made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be
11711 getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you
11712 won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way,
11713 you have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have
11714 to talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money.
11717 For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed
11719 <!-- PAGE BREAK 232 -->
11720 these costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the
11722 would outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old
11723 films, Agee argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until
11724 the copyright expires.
11726 <indexterm startref='idxageemichael' class='endofrange'
/>
11728 But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will
11729 have expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and
11730 nitrate stock dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal
11732 in which they are now stored will be filled with nothing more
11736 <emphasis role='strong'
>Of all the
</emphasis> creative work produced
11737 by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has continuing commercial
11738 value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a crucially important
11739 legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright creates incentives
11740 to produce and distribute the creative work. For that tiny fraction,
11741 the copyright acts as an
<quote>engine of free expression.
</quote>
11744 But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the
11745 creative work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've
11747 most books go out of print within one year. The same is true of
11748 music and film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving.
11749 And when a creative work falls out of favor with the commercial
11751 the commercial life ends.
11754 Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't
11755 keep libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes
& Noble, and
11756 we don't have archives of films because we expect people to choose
11758 spending Friday night watching new movies and spending
11760 night watching a
1930 news documentary. The noncommercial life
11761 of culture is important and valuable
—for entertainment but also, and
11762 more importantly, for knowledge. To understand who we are, and
11763 where we came from, and how we have made the mistakes that we
11764 have, we need to have access to this history.
11767 Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression.
11769 <!-- PAGE BREAK 233 -->
11770 In this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in
11771 this context do no good.
11774 Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of
11775 our history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no
11776 <emphasis>copyright-related use
</emphasis> that would be inhibited by
11777 an exclusive right. When a book went out of print, you could not buy
11778 it from a publisher. But you could still buy it from a used book
11779 store, and when a used book store sells it, in America, at least,
11780 there is no need to pay the copyright owner anything. Thus, the
11781 ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended was a use that
11782 was independent of copyright law.
11785 The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring
11786 a film
—the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs
—were
11787 so high, it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore
11788 film. Like the remains of a great dinner, when it's over, it's
11789 over. Once a film passed out of its commercial life, it may have been
11790 archived for a bit, but that was the end of its life so long as the
11791 market didn't have more to offer.
11794 In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most
11795 of our history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works
11796 that lost their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works
11797 would not have interfered with anything.
11800 But this situation has now changed.
11802 <indexterm id='idxarchivesdigital2' class='startofrange'
><primary>archives, digital
</primary></indexterm>
11804 One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital
11805 technologies is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of.
11806 Digital technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access
11807 to all sorts of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now
11808 imagine digitizing it and making it available to everyone,
11809 forever. Once a film goes out of distribution, we could digitize it
11810 and make it available to everyone, forever. Digital technologies give
11811 new life to copyrighted material after it passes out of its commercial
11812 life. It is now possible to preserve and assure universal access to
11813 this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not.
11816 <!-- PAGE BREAK 234 -->
11817 And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing
11818 this digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right
11819 of copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires
11820 permission of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any
11821 other aspect of our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make
11822 these things available to history, or to researchers, or to those who
11823 just want to explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were
11824 written for a radically different context.
11827 Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that
11828 technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law
11829 gets in the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful
11830 <emphasis>copyright
</emphasis> purpose, for the purpose of copyright
11831 is to enable the commercial market that spreads culture. No, we are
11832 talking about culture after it has lived its commercial life. In this
11833 context, copyright is serving no purpose
<emphasis>at all
</emphasis>
11834 related to the spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not
11835 an engine of free expression. Copyright is a brake.
11838 You may well ask,
<quote>But if digital technologies lower the costs for
11839 Brewster Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too.
11840 So won't Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading
11841 culture widely?
</quote>
11844 Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that
11845 publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes
& Noble
11846 offered to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that
11847 eliminate the need for libraries? Only if you think that the only role
11848 of a library is to serve what
<quote>the market
</quote> would demand. But if you
11849 think the role of a library is bigger than this
—if you think its
11850 role is to archive culture, whether there's a demand for any
11851 particular bit of that culture or not
—then we can't count on the
11852 commercial market to do our library work for us.
11854 <indexterm startref='idxarchivesdigital2' class='endofrange'
/>
11856 I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We
11857 should rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable
11858 culture. My message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the
11859 market is not doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the
11861 <!-- PAGE BREAK 235 -->
11862 freedom to fill the gaps. As one researcher calculated for American
11863 culture,
94 percent of the films, books, and music produced between
11864 1923 and
1946 is not commercially available. However much you love the
11865 commercial market, if access is a value, then
6 percent is a failure
11866 to provide that value.
<footnote><para>
11868 Jason Schultz,
<quote>The Myth of the
1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory,
</quote> 20
11869 December
2002, available at
11870 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
54</ulink>.
11875 <emphasis role='strong'
>In January
1999</emphasis>, we filed a lawsuit
11876 on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal district court in Washington, D.C.,
11877 asking the court to declare the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension
11878 Act unconstitutional. The two central claims that we made were (
1)
11879 that extending existing terms violated the Constitution's
11880 <quote>limited Times
</quote> requirement, and (
2) that extending terms
11881 by another twenty years violated the First Amendment.
11884 The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an
11885 argument. A panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also
11886 dismissed our claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But
11887 that decision at least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative
11888 judges on that court. That dissent gave our claims life.
11891 Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that
11892 copyrights be for
<quote>limited Times
</quote> only. His argument was as elegant as
11893 it was simple: If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no
11894 <quote>stopping point
</quote> to Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The
11895 power to extend existing terms means Congress is not required to grant
11896 terms that are
<quote>limited.
</quote> Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had
11897 to interpret the term
<quote>limited Times
</quote> to give it meaning. And the best
11898 interpretation, Judge Sentelle argued, would be to deny Congress the
11899 power to extend existing terms.
11902 We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to
11903 hear the case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for
11904 important cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a
11905 whole, where the court will sit
<quote>en banc
</quote> to hear the case.
11907 <indexterm><primary>Tatel, David
</primary></indexterm>
11909 The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc.
11910 This time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the
11912 <!-- PAGE BREAK 236 -->
11913 D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the
11914 most liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had
11915 overstepped its bounds.
11918 It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the
11919 Supreme Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It
11920 hears about one hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand
11921 appeals.) And it practically never reviews a decision that upholds a
11922 statute when no other court has yet reviewed the statute.
11925 But in February
2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by
11926 granting our petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument
11927 was set for October of
2002. The summer would be spent writing
11928 briefs and preparing for argument.
11931 <emphasis role='strong'
>It is over
</emphasis> a year later as I write
11932 these words. It is still astonishingly hard. If you know anything at
11933 all about this story, you know that we lost the appeal. And if you
11934 know something more than just the minimum, you probably think there
11935 was no way this case could have been won. After our defeat, I received
11936 literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and supporters,
11937 thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed cause. And
11938 none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail from my
11939 client, Eric Eldred.
11942 But my client and these friends were wrong. This case could have
11943 been won. It should have been won. And no matter how hard I try to
11944 retell this story to myself, I can never escape believing that my own
11947 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey
</primary></indexterm>
11949 <emphasis role='strong'
>The mistake
</emphasis> was made early, though
11950 it became obvious only at the very end. Our case had been supported
11951 from the very beginning by an extraordinary lawyer, Geoffrey Stewart,
11952 and by the law firm he had moved to, Jones, Day, Reavis and
11953 Pogue. Jones Day took a great deal of heat
11954 <!-- PAGE BREAK 237 -->
11955 from its copyright-protectionist clients for supporting us. They
11956 ignored this pressure (something that few law firms today would ever
11957 do), and throughout the case, they gave it everything they could.
11959 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
11960 <indexterm><primary>Bromberg, Dan
</primary></indexterm>
11961 <indexterm><primary>Steward, Geoffrey
</primary></indexterm>
11963 There were three key lawyers on the case from Jones Day. Geoff
11964 Stewart was the first, but then Dan Bromberg and Don Ayer became
11965 quite involved. Bromberg and Ayer in particular had a common view
11966 about how this case would be won: We would only win, they repeatedly
11967 told me, if we could make the issue seem
<quote>important
</quote> to the Supreme
11968 Court. It had to seem as if dramatic harm were being done to free
11969 speech and free culture; otherwise, they would never vote against
<quote>the
11970 most powerful media companies in the world.
</quote>
11973 I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act
11974 was a dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still
11975 think it is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based
11976 on how important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be
11977 <quote>right
</quote> as in
<quote>true,
</quote> I thought, but it is
<quote>wrong
</quote> as in
<quote>it just shouldn't be
11978 that way.
</quote> As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the
11979 framers of our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the
11980 CTEA was unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful
11982 of what the First Amendment means would yield the
11983 conclusion that the power to extend existing copyright terms is
11985 I was not persuaded that we had to sell our case like soap.
11986 Just as a law that bans the swastika is unconstitutional not because the
11987 Court likes Nazis but because such a law would violate the
11989 so too, in my view, would the Court decide whether Congress's
11990 law was constitutional based on the Constitution, not based on whether
11991 they liked the values that the framers put in the Constitution.
11994 In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and
11995 the harm caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review?
11996 There was no reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they
11997 weren't convinced that this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we
11998 didn't need to persuade them that this law was bad, we needed to show
11999 why it was unconstitutional.
12002 There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter
12004 <!-- PAGE BREAK 238 -->
12005 and in which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced
12006 that the Court would not hear our arguments if it thought these were
12007 just the arguments of a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was
12008 not about to launch into a new field of judicial review if it seemed
12009 that this field of review was simply the preference of a small
12010 political minority. Although my focus in the case was not to
12011 demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to demonstrate that it
12012 was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument against a
12013 background of briefs that covered the full range of political
12014 views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in
12015 <emphasis>law
</emphasis> and not politics, then, we tried to gather
12016 the widest range of credible critics
—credible not because they
12017 were rich and famous, but because they, in the aggregate, demonstrated
12018 that this law was unconstitutional regardless of one's politics.
12020 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum
</primary></indexterm>
12021 <indexterm><primary>Schlafly, Phyllis
</primary></indexterm>
12023 The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's
12024 organization, Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the
12025 very beginning. Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by
12026 Congress. In November
1998, she wrote a stinging editorial attacking
12027 the Republican Congress for allowing the law to pass. As she wrote,
12028 <quote>Do you sometimes wonder why bills that create a financial windfall to
12029 narrow special interests slide easily through the intricate
12030 legislative process, while bills that benefit the general public seem
12031 to get bogged down?
</quote> The answer, as the editorial documented, was the
12032 power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's contributions to the key
12033 players on the committees. It was money, not justice, that gave Mickey
12034 Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, Schlafly argued.
12037 In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief
12038 supporting our position. Their brief made the argument that became the
12039 core claim in the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of
12040 existing copyrights, there is no limit to Congress's power to set
12041 terms. That strong conservative argument persuaded a strong
12042 conservative judge, Judge Sentelle.
12044 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
12045 <indexterm><primary>Intel
</primary></indexterm>
12046 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
12047 <indexterm><primary>Eagle Forum
</primary></indexterm>
12049 In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as
12050 it gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free
12052 <!-- PAGE BREAK 239 -->
12053 Software Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/Linux
12054 possible). They included a powerful brief about the costs of
12055 uncertainty by Intel. There were two law professors' briefs, one by
12056 copyright scholars and one by First Amendment scholars. There was an
12057 exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the world's experts in the
12058 history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there was a new brief
12059 by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments.
12061 <indexterm><primary>American Association of Law Libraries
</primary></indexterm>
12062 <indexterm><primary>National Writers Union
</primary></indexterm>
12064 Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal
12065 argument, there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and
12066 archives, including the Internet Archive, the American Association of
12067 Law Libraries, and the National Writers Union.
12069 <indexterm><primary>Hal Roach Studios
</primary></indexterm>
12071 But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the
12072 argument I've already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued
12073 that unless the law was struck, a whole generation of American film
12074 would disappear. The other made the economic argument absolutely
12077 <indexterm><primary>Akerlof, George
</primary></indexterm>
12078 <indexterm><primary>Arrow, Kenneth
</primary></indexterm>
12079 <indexterm><primary>Buchanan, James
</primary></indexterm>
12080 <indexterm><primary>Coase, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
12081 <indexterm><primary>Friedman, Milton
</primary></indexterm>
12083 This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including
12084 five Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan,
12085 Milton Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as
12086 the list of Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political
12087 spectrum. Their conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible
12088 claim that extending the terms of existing copyrights would do
12089 anything to increase incentives to create. Such extensions were
12090 nothing more than
<quote>rent-seeking
</quote>—the fancy term economists use
12091 to describe special-interest legislation gone wild.
12093 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12094 <indexterm><primary>Morrison, Alan
</primary></indexterm>
12095 <indexterm><primary>Public Citizen
</primary></indexterm>
12096 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
12098 The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered
12099 to write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with
12100 us from the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we
12101 added three lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan
12102 Morrison, a lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had
12103 made constitutional history with a series of seminal victories in the
12104 Supreme Court defending individual rights; my colleague and dean,
12105 Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued many cases in the Court, and
12107 <!-- PAGE BREAK 240 -->
12108 who had advised us early on about a First Amendment strategy; and
12109 finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried.
12111 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12112 <indexterm><primary>Congress, U.S.
</primary><secondary>constitutional powers of
</secondary></indexterm>
12113 <indexterm><primary>Constitution, U.S.
</primary><secondary>Commerce Clause of
</secondary></indexterm>
12115 Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor
12116 general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give
12117 media companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried
12118 was the only one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up
12119 for something he believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer
12120 in the Supreme Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that
12121 limited Congress's power in the context of the Commerce Clause. And
12122 while he had argued many positions in the Supreme Court that I
12123 personally disagreed with, his joining the cause was a vote of
12124 confidence in our argument.
12127 The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of
12128 friends, as well. Significantly, however, none of these
<quote>friends
</quote> included
12129 historians or economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were
12130 written exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and
12134 The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain
12135 from the law. The congressmen were not surprising either
—they
12136 were defending their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of
12137 contributions such power induced. And of course it was not surprising
12138 that the copyright holders would defend the idea that they should
12139 continue to have the right to control who did what with content they
12142 <indexterm><primary>Gershwin, George
</primary></indexterm>
12143 <indexterm><primary>Porgy and Bess
</primary></indexterm>
12144 <indexterm><primary>pornography
</primary></indexterm>
12146 Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was
12147 better for the Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to
12148 Dr. Seuss's work
— better than allowing it to fall into the
12149 public domain
—because if this creativity were in the public
12150 domain, then people could use it to
<quote>glorify drugs or to create
12151 pornography.
</quote><footnote><para>
12153 Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al.,
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>,
537
12154 U.S. (
2003) (No.
01-
618),
19.
12156 That was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its
12157 <quote>protection
</quote> of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example,
12158 to license
<citetitle>Porgy and Bess
</citetitle> to anyone who refuses to use African
12159 Americans in the cast.
<footnote><para>
12161 Dinitia Smith,
<quote>Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey
12162 Mouse Joins the Fray,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Times
</citetitle>,
28 March
1998, B7.
12165 <!-- PAGE BREAK 241 -->
12166 their view of how this part of American culture should be controlled,
12167 and they wanted this law to help them effect that control.
12170 This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this
12171 debate. When Congress decides to extend the term of existing
12172 copyrights, Congress is making a choice about which speakers it will
12173 favor. Famous and beloved copyright owners, such as the Gershwin
12174 estate and Dr. Seuss, come to Congress and say,
<quote>Give us twenty years
12175 to control the speech about these icons of American culture. We'll do
12176 better with them than anyone else.
</quote> Congress of course likes to reward
12177 the popular and famous by giving them what they want. But when
12178 Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak in a certain way,
12179 that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally meant to block.
12182 We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA
12183 mean that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend
12184 copyrights
—extensions that would further concentrate the market;
12185 it would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play
12186 favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak.
12189 <emphasis role='strong'
>Between February
</emphasis> and October, there
12190 was little I did beyond preparing for this case. Early on, as I said,
12191 I set the strategy.
12193 <indexterm><primary>Rehnquist, William H.
</primary></indexterm>
12194 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day
</primary></indexterm>
12196 The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we
12197 called
<quote>the Conservatives.
</quote> The other we called
<quote>the Rest.
</quote> The
12198 Conservatives included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor,
12199 Justice Scalia, Justice Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had
12200 been the most consistent in limiting Congress's power. They were the
12201 five who had supported the
<citetitle>Lopez/Morrison
</citetitle> line
12202 of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be interpreted to
12203 assure that Congress's powers had limits.
12205 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12206 <indexterm id='idxginsburg' class='startofrange'
><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader
</primary></indexterm>
12208 The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on
12209 Congress's power. These four
—Justice Stevens, Justice Souter,
12210 Justice Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer
—had repeatedly argued that
12212 <!-- PAGE BREAK 242 -->
12213 gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement its
12214 powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's
12215 role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four
12216 justices were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed
12217 with, they were also the votes that we were least likely to get.
12220 In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to
12221 her general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of
12222 gender are involved), she had been particularly deferential in the
12223 context of intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an
12224 excellent and well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from
12225 the same intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with
12226 the writings of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this
12227 context to do as it wished, even if what Congress wished made little
12230 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12232 Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as
12233 unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly
12234 favored deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were
12235 also very sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly
12236 believed, there was a very important free speech argument against
12237 these retrospective extensions.
12239 <indexterm startref='idxginsburg' class='endofrange'
/>
12241 The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice
12242 Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest
12243 judges on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just
12244 means that no simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he
12245 had consistently argued for limits in the context of intellectual property
12246 generally. We were fairly confident he would recognize limits here.
12249 This analysis of
<quote>the Rest
</quote> showed most clearly where our focus had to
12250 be: on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these
12251 five and get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single
12252 overriding argument that animated our claim rested on the
12253 Conservatives' most important jurisprudential innovation
—the
12254 argument that Judge Sentelle had relied upon in the Court of Appeals,
12255 that Congress's power must be interpreted so that its enumerated
12256 powers have limits.
12259 This then was the core of our strategy
—a strategy for which I am
12260 responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the
12261 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>
12262 <!-- PAGE BREAK 243 -->
12263 case, under the government's argument here, Congress would always have
12264 unlimited power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about
12265 Congress's power under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was
12266 supposed to be
<quote>limited.
</quote> Our aim would be to get the Court to
12267 reconcile
<citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> with
12268 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>: If Congress's power to regulate commerce
12269 was limited, then so, too, must Congress's power to regulate copyright
12273 <emphasis role='strong'
>The argument
</emphasis> on the government's
12274 side came down to this: Congress has done it before. It should be
12275 allowed to do it again. The government claimed that from the very
12276 beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing
12277 copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say
12278 that practice is unconstitutional.
12281 There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We
12282 certainly agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in
1831
12283 and in
1909. And of course, in
1962, Congress began extending
12285 terms regularly
—eleven times in forty years.
12288 But this
<quote>consistency
</quote> should be kept in perspective. Congress
12290 existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic.
12291 It then extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare
12292 extensions are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending
12294 terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that
12296 was now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there
12297 was no reason to expect that cycle would end. This Court had not
12299 to intervene where Congress was in a similar cycle of extension.
12300 There was no reason it couldn't intervene here.
12303 <emphasis role='strong'
>Oral argument
</emphasis> was scheduled for the
12304 first week in October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the
12305 argument. During those two weeks, I was repeatedly
12306 <quote>mooted
</quote> by lawyers who had volunteered to
12308 <!-- PAGE BREAK 244 -->
12309 help in the case. Such
<quote>moots
</quote> are basically practice rounds, where
12310 wannabe justices fire questions at wannabe winners.
12313 I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a
12314 single point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to
12315 the power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that
12316 terms would be effectively unlimited; going with us would give
12318 a clear line to follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots
12319 were an effective practice; I found ways to take every question back to
12322 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12323 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
12324 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12326 One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the
12327 skeptic. He had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor
12328 General Charles Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme
12329 Court. And in his review of the moot, he let his concern speak:
12332 <quote>I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be
12333 willing to upset this practice that the government says has been a
12334 consistent practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see
12335 the harm
—passionately get them to see the harm. For if they
12336 don't see that, then we haven't any chance of winning.
</quote>
12338 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12340 He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but
12341 he didn't understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the
12342 right thing
—not because of politics but because it was right. As a law
12343 professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court
12344 does the right thing
—not because of politics but because it is right. As
12345 I listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood
12346 his point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough.
12347 Let the politicians learn to see that it was also good.
12350 <emphasis role='strong'
>The night before
</emphasis> the argument, a
12351 line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The case
12352 had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free
12353 culture. Hundreds stood in line
12355 <!-- PAGE BREAK 245 -->
12356 for the chance to see the proceedings. Scores spent the night on the
12357 Supreme Court steps so that they would be assured a seat.
12360 Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can
12361 ask for seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for
12362 my parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get
12363 a seat in a special section reserved for them. And senators and
12365 have a special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of
12366 course, the press has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on
12367 the Court. As we entered that morning, there was no place that was
12368 not taken. This was an argument about intellectual property law, yet
12369 the halls were filled. As I walked in to take my seat at the front of the
12370 Court, I saw my parents sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table,
12371 I saw Jack Valenti sitting in the special section ordinarily reserved for
12372 family of the Justices.
12375 When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began
12376 where I intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's
12377 power. This was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether
12378 those enumerated powers had any limit.
12380 <indexterm><primary>O'Connor, Sandra Day
</primary></indexterm>
12382 Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening.
12383 The history was bothering her.
12387 justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often
12388 through the years, and if you are right, don't we run the risk of
12389 upsetting previous extensions of time? I mean, this seems to be a
12390 practice that began with the very first act.
12394 She was quite willing to concede
<quote>that this flies directly in the face
12395 of what the framers had in mind.
</quote> But my response again and again
12396 was to emphasize limits on Congress's power.
12400 mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in
12401 mind, then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their
12402 <!-- PAGE BREAK 246 -->
12403 words that gives effect to what they had in mind, and the answer
12408 There were two points in this argument when I should have seen
12409 where the Court was going. The first was a question by Justice
12410 Kennedy, who observed,
12414 justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that
12415 the '
76 act, too, should have been declared void, and that we
12416 might leave it alone because of the disruption, is that for all these
12417 years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts.
12418 I just don't see any empirical evidence for that.
12422 Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a
12428 mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all.
12429 Nothing in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical
12430 assertion about impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a
12431 structural limit necessary to assure that what would be an effectively
12432 perpetual term not be permitted under the copyright laws.
12435 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12437 That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right
12438 answer was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any
12439 number of briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And
12440 here was the place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a
12441 softball; my answer was a swing and a miss.
12444 The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been
12445 crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> ruling,
12446 and we hoped that he would see this case as its second cousin.
12449 It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all
12450 sympathetic. To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked:
12452 <!-- PAGE BREAK 247 -->
12456 chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the
12457 right to copy verbatim other people's books, don't you?
12460 mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that
12461 should be in the public domain and would be in the public
12463 but for a statute that cannot be justified under ordinary First
12464 Amendment analysis or under a proper reading of the limits built
12465 into the Copyright Clause.
12468 <indexterm><primary>Olson, Theodore B.
</primary></indexterm>
12470 Things went better for us when the government gave its argument;
12471 for now the Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia
12472 asked Solicitor General Olson,
12476 justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12477 time would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely
12478 the argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited
12479 time which is extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited
12484 When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal.
12485 Olson's flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed
12486 to the academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if
12487 this were the first case ever to consider limits on Congress's
12488 Copyright and Patent Clause power. Ever the professor and not the
12489 advocate, I closed by pointing out the long history of the Court
12490 imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of the Copyright and
12491 Patent Clause
— indeed, the very first case striking a law of
12492 Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon the
12493 Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the
12497 <emphasis role='strong'
>As I left
</emphasis> the court that day, I
12498 knew there were a hundred points I wished I could remake. There were a
12499 hundred questions I wished I had
12501 <!-- PAGE BREAK 248 -->
12502 answered differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me
12506 The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit?
12507 Over and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was
12508 precisely the answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not
12509 imagine how the Court could understand that the government believed
12510 Congress's power was unlimited under the terms of the Copyright
12511 Clause, and sustain the government's argument. The solicitor general
12512 had made my argument for me. No matter how often I tried, I could not
12513 understand how the Court could find that Congress's power under the
12514 Commerce Clause was limited, but under the Copyright Clause,
12515 unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe that we may
12516 have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court
—in particular,
12517 the Conservatives
—would feel itself constrained by the rule of
12518 law that it had established elsewhere.
12521 <emphasis role='strong'
>The morning
</emphasis> of January
15,
2003, I
12522 was five minutes late to the office and missed the
7:
00 A.M. call from
12523 the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the message, I could tell in an
12524 instant that she had bad news to report.The Supreme Court had affirmed
12525 the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven justices had voted in the
12526 majority. There were two dissents.
12529 A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the
12530 phone off the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat
12531 down to see where I had been wrong in my reasoning.
12534 My
<emphasis>reasoning
</emphasis>. Here was a case that pitted all the
12535 money in the world against
<emphasis>reasoning
</emphasis>. And here
12536 was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, looking for
12540 I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would
12541 distinguish the principle in this case from the principle in
12542 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. The argument was nowhere to be found. The case was not even
12543 cited. The argument that was the core argument of our case did not
12544 even appear in the Court's opinion.
12546 <indexterm><primary>Ginsburg, Ruth Bader
</primary></indexterm>
12549 <!-- PAGE BREAK 249 -->
12550 Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument.
12551 Consistent with her view that Congress's power was not limited
12552 generally, she had found Congress's power not limited here.
12555 Her opinion was perfectly reasonable
—for her, and for Justice
12556 Souter. Neither believes in
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle>. It would be too much to expect them
12557 to write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine
12558 they had worked so hard to defeat.
12561 But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I
12562 was reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile
12563 limited powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the
12564 Progress Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could
12565 reconcile the two simply
<emphasis>by not addressing the
12566 argument
</emphasis>. There was no inconsistency because they would not
12567 talk about the two together. There was therefore no principle that
12568 followed from the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> case: In that context, Congress's power would
12569 be limited, but in this context it would not.
12572 Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values
12573 they would respect? By what right did they
—the silent
12574 five
—get to select the part of the Constitution they would
12575 enforce based on the values they thought important? We were right back
12576 to the argument that I said I hated at the start: I had failed to
12577 convince them that the issue here was important, and I had failed to
12578 recognize that however much I might hate a system in which the Court
12579 gets to pick the constitutional values that it will respect, that is
12580 the system we have.
12582 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12584 Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's
12585 opinion was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition
12586 of intellectual property law should not support this unjustified
12587 extension of terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that
12588 had governed in the context of patents (so had we). But the rest of
12589 the Court discounted the parallel
—without explaining how the
12590 very same words in the Progress Clause could come to mean totally
12591 different things depending upon whether the words were about patents
12592 or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's charge go unanswered.
12594 <indexterm><primary>Breyer, Stephen
</primary></indexterm>
12596 <!-- PAGE BREAK 250 -->
12597 Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever
12598 written, was external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of
12599 copyrights has become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had
12600 said that under the current term, a copyright gave an author
99.8
12601 percent of the value of a perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong,
12602 that the actual number was
99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either
12603 way, the point was clear: If the Constitution said a term had to be
12604 <quote>limited,
</quote> and the existing term was so long as to be effectively
12605 unlimited, then it was unconstitutional.
12608 These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But
12609 because neither believed in the
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> case, neither was willing to push
12610 it as a reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without
12611 anyone having addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge
12612 Sentelle. It was
<citetitle>Hamlet
</citetitle> without the Prince.
12615 <emphasis role='strong'
>Defeat brings depression
</emphasis>. They say
12616 it is a sign of health when depression gives way to anger. My anger
12617 came quickly, but it didn't cure the depression. This anger was of two
12620 <indexterm><primary>originalism
</primary></indexterm>
12622 It was first anger with the five
<quote>Conservatives.
</quote> It would have been
12623 one thing for them to have explained why the principle of
<citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> didn't
12624 apply in this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing
12625 argument, I don't believe, having read it made by others, and having
12626 tried to make it myself. But it at least would have been an act of
12627 integrity. These justices in particular have repeatedly said that the
12628 proper mode of interpreting the Constitution is
<quote>originalism
</quote>—to
12629 first understand the framers' text, interpreted in their context, in
12630 light of the structure of the Constitution. That method had produced
12631 <citetitle>Lopez
</citetitle> and many other
<quote>originalist
</quote> rulings. Where was their
12632 <quote>originalism
</quote> now?
12635 Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain
12636 what the framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they
12637 did; they joined an opinion that never once tried to explain how the
12638 structure of that clause would affect the interpretation of Congress's
12640 <!-- PAGE BREAK 251 -->
12641 power. And they joined an opinion that didn't even try to explain why
12642 this grant of power could be unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause
12643 would be limited. In short, they had joined an opinion that did not
12644 apply to, and was inconsistent with, their own method for interpreting
12645 the Constitution. This opinion may well have yielded a result that
12646 they liked. It did not produce a reason that was consistent with their
12650 My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with
12652 For I had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of
12655 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12657 Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for
12658 idealism about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular.
12659 Most have a much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this
12660 case would be won based on whether I could convince the Justices that
12661 the framers' values were important, I fought the idea, because I
12662 didn't want to believe that that is how this Court decides. I insisted
12663 on arguing this case as if it were a simple application of a set of
12664 principles. I had an argument that followed in logic. I didn't need
12665 to waste my time showing it should also follow in popularity.
12668 As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I
12669 can see a hundred places where the answers could have taken the
12670 conversation in different directions, where the truth about the harm
12671 that this unchecked power will cause could have been made clear to
12672 this Court. Justice Kennedy in good faith wanted to be shown. I,
12673 idiotically, corrected his question. Justice Souter in good faith
12674 wanted to be shown the First Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher,
12675 reframed the question to make the logical point. I had shown them how
12676 they could strike this law of Congress if they wanted to. There were a
12677 hundred places where I could have helped them want to, yet my
12678 stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have stood before
12679 hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion in that
12680 effort to persuade; but I
12681 <!-- PAGE BREAK 252 -->
12682 refused to stand before this audience and try to persuade with the
12683 passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis on which a court
12684 should decide the issue.
12686 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12687 <indexterm><primary>Fried, Charles
</primary></indexterm>
12689 Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it
12690 have been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or
12694 My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court
12695 was not ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It
12696 would take a great deal more to show our society why our framers were
12697 right. And when we do that, we will be able to show that Court.
12700 Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in
12701 doing anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have
12702 little reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had
12703 stepped down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could
12706 <indexterm><primary>Jaszi, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
12708 And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in
12709 January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading
12710 intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this
12711 case was a mistake.
<quote>The Court is not ready,
</quote> Peter Jaszi said; this
12712 issue should not be raised until it is.
12715 After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and
12716 publicly, that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have
12717 been persuaded, then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that
12718 here again Peter was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in
12719 a way that would do some good or they were not ready to hear this case
12720 in a way that would do some good. Either way, the decision to bring
12721 this case
—a decision I had made four years before
—was wrong.
12724 <emphasis role='strong'
>While the reaction
</emphasis> to the Sonny
12725 Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the
12726 Court's decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to
12727 say that extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won
12728 that battle over ideas. Where
12730 <!-- PAGE BREAK 253 -->
12731 the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had been
12732 skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good
12733 thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision
12734 was attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and
12735 harmful law.
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle> wrote in its editorial,
12739 In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are
12740 seeing the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of
12741 copyright perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment,
12742 one that should not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on
12743 the entire creative output of humanity is one of the reasons we live
12744 in a time of such fruitful creative ferment.
12748 The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of
12749 hilarious images
—of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from
12750 my view of the case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced in figure
12751 <xref xrefstyle=
"template:%n" linkend=
"fig-18"/>. The
<quote>powerful
12752 and wealthy
</quote> line is a bit unfair. But the punch in the face
12753 felt exactly like that.
12754 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben
</primary></indexterm>
12756 <figure id=
"fig-18" float=
"1">
12758 <graphic fileref=
"images/tom-the-dancing-bug.png" align=
"center" width=
"100%"></graphic>
12759 <indexterm><primary>Bolling, Ruben
</primary></indexterm>
12762 The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the
12763 quote from
<citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>. That
<quote>grand experiment
</quote> we call the
12764 <quote>public domain
</quote> is over? When I can make light of it, I think,
<quote>Honey,
12765 I shrunk the Constitution.
</quote> But I can rarely make light of it. We had
12766 in our Constitution a commitment to free culture. In the case that I
12767 fathered, the Supreme Court effectively renounced that commitment. A
12768 better lawyer would have made them see differently.
12770 <!-- PAGE BREAK 254 -->
12772 <chapter label=
"14" id=
"eldred-ii">
12773 <title>Eldred II
</title>
12775 <emphasis role='strong'
>The day
</emphasis>
12776 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was decided, fate would have it that I
12777 was to travel to Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in
12778 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> was denied
—meaning the case was
12779 really finally over
—fate would have it that I was giving a
12780 speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a particularly
12781 long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city from
12782 Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and
12783 wrote an op-ed piece.
12785 <indexterm><primary>Ayer, Don
</primary></indexterm>
12787 It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San
12788 Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head
12789 the same advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is
12790 important. And alternating with that command was the question of
12791 Justice Kennedy:
<quote>For all these years the act has impeded progress in
12792 science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical evidence for
12793 that.
</quote> And so, having failed in the argument of constitutional principle,
12794 finally, I turned to an argument of politics.
12797 <citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle> published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple
12798 fix: Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner
12799 <!-- PAGE BREAK 256 -->
12800 would be required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid
12801 the fee, he got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not,
12802 the work passed into the public domain.
12805 We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name.
12806 Eric Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as
12807 he said early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name.
12810 Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this
12811 is either the
<quote>Public Domain Enhancement Act
</quote> or the
<quote>Copyright
12812 Term Deregulation Act.
</quote> Either way, the essence of the idea is clear
12813 and obvious: Remove copyright where it is doing nothing except
12814 blocking access and the spread of knowledge. Leave it for as long as
12815 Congress allows for those works where its worth is at least $
1. But for
12816 everything else, let the content go.
12818 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
12820 The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed
12821 it in an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters
12822 expressing support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity,
12823 people can see the copyright system makes no sense. As a good
12824 Republican might say, here government regulation is simply getting in
12825 the way of innovation and creativity. And as a good Democrat might
12826 say, here the government is blocking access and the spread of
12827 knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, there is no real difference
12828 between Democrats and Republicans on this issue. Anyone can recognize
12829 the stupid harm of the present system.
12832 Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration
12833 requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system
12834 for people who want to license content is that there is no obvious
12835 place to look for the current copyright owners. Since registration is
12836 not required, since marking content is not required, since no
12837 formality at all is required, it is often impossibly hard to locate
12838 copyright owners to ask permission to use or license their work. This
12839 system would lower these costs, by establishing at least one registry
12840 where copyright owners could be identified.
12842 <indexterm><primary>Berlin Act (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12843 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12845 <!-- PAGE BREAK 257 -->
12846 As I described in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
12847 linkend=
"property-i"/>, formalities in copyright law were
12848 removed in
1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning
12849 any formal requirement before a copyright is granted.
<footnote><para>
12851 <indexterm><primary>German copyright law
</primary></indexterm>
12852 Until the
1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright
12853 legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with
12854 formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of
12855 the author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the
1908 act,
12856 every text of the Convention has provided that
<quote>the enjoyment and the
12857 exercise
</quote> of rights guaranteed by the Convention
<quote>shall not be subject
12858 to any formality.
</quote> The prohibition against formalities is presently
12859 embodied in Article
5(
2) of the Paris Text of the Berne
12860 Convention. Many countries continue to impose some form of deposit or
12861 registration requirement, albeit not as a condition of
12862 copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of
12863 works in national repositories, principally the National Museum.
12864 Copies of books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in
12865 the British Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar
12866 of Authors where the author's true name can be filed in the case of
12867 anonymous or pseudonymous works. Paul Goldstein,
<citetitle>International
12868 Intellectual Property Law, Cases and Materials
</citetitle> (New York: Foundation
12869 Press,
2001),
153–54.
</para></footnote>
12870 The Europeans are said to view copyright as a
<quote>natural right.
</quote> Natural
12871 rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the Anglo-American
12872 tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if their
12873 rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly
12874 respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my
12875 creativity, not upon the special favor of the government.
12878 That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is
12879 absurd copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because
12880 a world without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread
12881 <quote>Walt Disney creativity
</quote> is destroyed when there is no simple way to
12882 know what's protected and what's not.
12884 <indexterm><primary>Berne Convention (
1908)
</primary></indexterm>
12886 The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in
12887 Berlin in
1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne
12888 Convention in
1908, to require copyright terms of life plus fifty
12889 years, as well as the abolition of copyright formalities. The
12890 formalities were hated because the stories of inadvertent loss were
12891 increasingly common. It was as if a Charles Dickens character ran all
12892 copyright offices, and the failure to dot an
<citetitle>i
</citetitle> or cross a
12893 <citetitle>t
</citetitle> resulted in the loss of widows' only income.
12896 These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the
12897 formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law
12898 should always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no
12899 reason copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning
12900 formalities totally, the response in Berlin should have been to
12901 embrace a more equitable system of registration.
12904 Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration
12905 in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was
12906 also a hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save
12907 the starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory
12909 imposed upon creators.
12912 In addition to the practical complaint of authors in
1908, there was
12913 a moral claim as well. There was no reason that creative property
12915 <!-- PAGE BREAK 258 -->
12916 should be a second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a
12917 table, his rights over the table don't depend upon filing a form with
12918 the government. He has a property right over the table
<quote>naturally,
</quote>
12919 and he can assert that right against anyone who would steal the table,
12920 whether or not he has informed the government of his ownership of the
12924 This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the
12925 argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative
12926 property being second-class property. The argument in favor of
12927 formalities turns upon the special problems that creative property
12928 presents. The law of formalities responds to the special physics of
12929 creative property, to assure that it can be efficiently and fairly
12933 No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just
12934 because you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land
12935 is to be effective. And few would think a car is second-class property
12936 just because you must register the car with the state and tag it with
12937 a license. In both of those cases, everyone sees that there is an
12938 important reason to secure registration
—both because it makes
12939 the markets more efficient and because it better secures the rights of
12940 the owner. Without a registration system for land, landowners would
12941 perpetually have to guard their property. With registration, they can
12942 simply point the police to a deed. Without a registration system for
12943 cars, auto theft would be much easier. With a registration system, the
12944 thief has a high burden to sell a stolen car. A slight burden is
12945 placed on the property owner, but those burdens produce a much better
12946 system of protection for property generally.
12949 It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in
12950 copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that
12951 makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative
12952 property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion
12953 places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular
12954 owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property
12955 with confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is
12956 the author and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in
12958 <!-- PAGE BREAK 259 -->
12959 a world without formalities. Complex, expensive,
12960 <emphasis>lawyer
</emphasis> transactions take their place.
12961 <indexterm><primary>Lovett, Lyle
</primary></indexterm>
12964 This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono
12965 Act that we tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it
12966 didn't
<quote>get.
</quote> Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no
12967 way easily to build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright
12968 terms were, as Justice Story said they would be,
<quote>short,
</quote> then this
12969 wouldn't matter much. For fourteen years, under the framers' system, a
12970 work would be presumptively controlled. After fourteen years, it would
12971 be presumptively uncontrolled.
12974 But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the
12975 inability to know what is protected and what is not protected becomes
12976 a huge and obvious burden on the creative process. If the only way a
12977 library can offer an Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a
12978 lawyer to clear the rights to every image and sound, then the
12979 copyright system is burdening creativity in a way that has never been
12980 seen before
<emphasis>because there are no formalities
</emphasis>.
12983 The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If
12984 it is worth $
1 to you, then register your work and you can get the
12985 longer term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how
12986 to get your permission if they want to use your work. And you will get
12987 the benefit of an extended copyright term.
12990 If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended
12991 term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your
12992 monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public
12993 domain where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a
12994 movie based on it. It should become free if it is not worth $
1 to you.
12997 Some worry about the burden on authors. Won't the burden of
12998 registering the work mean that the $
1 is really misleading? Isn't the
12999 hassle worth more than $
1? Isn't that the real problem with
13003 It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I
13004 completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no
13005 doubt because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap
13007 <!-- PAGE BREAK 260 -->
13008 registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must
13009 address the real problem of
<emphasis>governments
</emphasis> standing
13010 at the core of any system of formalities. In this book, I offer such a
13011 solution. That solution essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For
13012 now, assume it was Amazon that ran the registration system. Assume it
13013 was one-click registration. The Eldred Act would propose a simple,
13014 one-click registration fifty years after a work was published. Based
13015 upon historical data, that system would move up to
98 percent of
13016 commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a commercial life,
13017 into the public domain within fifty years. What do you think?
13019 <indexterm><primary>Forbes, Steve
</primary></indexterm>
13021 <emphasis role='strong'
>When Steve Forbes
</emphasis> endorsed the
13022 idea, some in Washington began to pay attention. Many people contacted
13023 me pointing to representatives who might be willing to introduce the
13024 Eldred Act. And I had a few who directly suggested that they might be
13025 willing to take the first step.
13027 <indexterm><primary>Lofgren, Zoe
</primary></indexterm>
13029 One representative, Zoe Lofgren of California, went so far as to get
13030 the bill drafted. The draft solved any problem with international
13031 law. It imposed the simplest requirement upon copyright owners
13032 possible. In May
2003, it looked as if the bill would be
13033 introduced. On May
16, I posted on the Eldred Act blog,
<quote>we are
13034 close.
</quote> There was a general reaction in the blog community that
13035 something good might happen here.
13038 But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and
13039 the MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give
13040 the view of the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti
13041 informed the congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred
13042 Act. The reasons are embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their
13043 thinness shows something clear about what this debate is really about.
13046 The MPAA argued first that Congress had
<quote>firmly rejected the central
13047 concept in the proposed bill
</quote>—that copyrights be renewed. That
13048 was true, but irrelevant, as Congress's
<quote>firm rejection
</quote> had occurred
13049 <!-- PAGE BREAK 261 -->
13050 long before the Internet made subsequent uses much more likely.
13051 Second, they argued that the proposal would harm poor copyright
13052 owners
—apparently those who could not afford the $
1 fee. Third,
13053 they argued that Congress had determined that extending a copyright
13054 term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in the case of the small
13055 percentage of work covered by copyright law that is still commercially
13056 valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal would not cut
13057 off the extended term unless the $
1 fee was not paid. Fourth, the MPAA
13058 argued that the bill would impose
<quote>enormous
</quote> costs, since a
13059 registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are
13060 certainly less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright
13061 whose owner is not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the
13062 copyright to a story underlying a film were to pass into the public
13063 domain. But what risk is that? If it is in the public domain, then the
13064 film is a valid derivative use.
13067 Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to
13068 do this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are
13069 thousands of copyright owners who don't even know they have a
13070 copyright to give. Whether they are free to give away their copyright
13071 or not
—a controversial claim in any case
—unless they know
13072 about a copyright, they're not likely to.
13075 <emphasis role='strong'
>At the beginning
</emphasis> of this book, I
13076 told two stories about the law reacting to changes in technology. In
13077 the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, common sense was
13078 delayed. The difference between the two stories was the power of the
13079 opposition
—the power of the side that fought to defend the
13080 status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old
13081 interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to
13082 protect themselves against this new competitive threat.
13085 I used these two cases as a way to frame the war that this book has
13086 been about. For here, too, a new technology is forcing the law to react.
13087 And here, too, we should ask, is the law following or resisting common
13088 sense? If common sense supports the law, what explains this common
13093 <!-- PAGE BREAK 262 -->
13094 When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the
13095 copyright owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and
13096 harmful, and the law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is
13097 p2p sharing, it is easy to understand why the law backs the owners
13098 still: Much of this sharing is wrong, even if much is harmless. When
13099 the issue is copyright terms for the Mickey Mouses of the world, it is
13100 possible still to understand why the law favors Hollywood: Most people
13101 don't recognize the reasons for limiting copyright terms; it is thus
13102 still possible to see good faith within the resistance.
13104 <indexterm><primary>Kelly, Kevin
</primary></indexterm>
13106 But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred
13107 Act, then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked
13108 selfinterest driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary
13109 range of content that is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with
13110 any copyright owner's desire to exercise continued control over his
13111 content. It would simply liberate what Kevin Kelly calls the
<quote>Dark
13112 Content
</quote> that fills archives around the world. So when the warriors
13113 oppose a change like this, we should ask one simple question:
13116 What does this industry really want?
13119 With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So
13120 the effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about
13121 protecting
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> content. The effort to block the
13122 Eldred Act is an effort to assure that nothing more passes into the
13123 public domain. It is another step to assure that the public domain
13124 will never compete, that there will be no use of content that is not
13125 commercially controlled, and that there will be no commercial use of
13126 content that doesn't require
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> permission
13130 The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side
13131 is. The most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as
13132 its aim not the protection of
<quote>property
</quote> but the rejection of a
13133 tradition. Their aim is not simply to protect what is
13134 theirs.
<emphasis>Their aim is to assure that all there is is what is
13138 It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not
13139 hard to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public
13141 <!-- PAGE BREAK 263 -->
13142 domain tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA
13143 feared the competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public
13144 domain connected to a public that now has the means to create with it
13145 and to share its own creation.
13147 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
13148 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
13150 What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is
13151 as if the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the
13152 Causbys and demands that their remote and useless property rights be
13153 respected, so that these remote and forgotten copyright holders might
13154 block the progress of others.
13157 All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the
13158 <quote>property
</quote> in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so
13159 long as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of
13160 the Internet. The consequence will be an increasing
<quote>permission
13161 society.
</quote> The past can be cultivated only if you can identify the
13162 owner and gain permission to build upon his work. The future will be
13163 controlled by this dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past.
13165 <!-- PAGE BREAK 264 -->
13168 <chapter label=
"" id=
"c-conclusion">
13169 <title>CONCLUSION
</title>
13170 <indexterm id='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>Africa, medications for HIV patients in
</primary></indexterm>
13171 <indexterm id='idxaidsmedications' class='startofrange'
><primary>AIDS medications
</primary></indexterm>
13172 <indexterm id='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='startofrange'
><primary>antiretroviral drugs
</primary></indexterm>
13173 <indexterm id='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='startofrange'
><primary>developing countries, foreign patent costs in
</primary></indexterm>
13174 <indexterm id='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='startofrange'
><primary>drugs
</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical
</secondary></indexterm>
13175 <indexterm id='idxhivaidstherapies' class='startofrange'
><primary>HIV/AIDS therapies
</primary></indexterm>
13177 <emphasis role='strong'
>There are more
</emphasis> than
35 million
13178 people with the AIDS virus worldwide. Twenty-five million of them live
13179 in sub-Saharan Africa. Seventeen million have already died. Seventeen
13180 million Africans is proportional percentage-wise to seven million
13181 Americans. More importantly, it is seventeen million Africans.
13184 There is no cure for AIDS, but there are drugs to slow its
13185 progression. These antiretroviral therapies are still experimental,
13186 but they have already had a dramatic effect. In the United States,
13187 AIDS patients who regularly take a cocktail of these drugs increase
13188 their life expectancy by ten to twenty years. For some, the drugs make
13189 the disease almost invisible.
13192 These drugs are expensive. When they were first introduced in the
13193 United States, they cost between $
10,
000 and $
15,
000 per person per
13194 year. Today, some cost $
25,
000 per year. At these prices, of course, no
13195 African nation can afford the drugs for the vast majority of its
13197 $
15,
000 is thirty times the per capita gross national product of
13198 Zimbabwe. At these prices, the drugs are totally unavailable.
<footnote><para>
13199 <!-- f1. --> Commission on Intellectual Property Rights,
<quote>Final Report: Integrating
13200 Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy
</quote> (London,
2002),
13202 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
55</ulink>. According to a World Health Organization press
13204 issued
9 July
2002, only
230,
000 of the
6 million who need drugs in
13205 the developing world receive them
—and half of them are in Brazil.
13208 <indexterm id='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='startofrange'
><primary>patents
</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals
</secondary></indexterm>
13209 <indexterm id='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='startofrange'
><primary>pharmaceutical patents
</primary></indexterm>
13211 <!-- PAGE BREAK 265 -->
13212 These prices are not high because the ingredients of the drugs are
13213 expensive. These prices are high because the drugs are protected by
13214 patents. The drug companies that produced these life-saving mixes
13215 enjoy at least a twenty-year monopoly for their inventions. They use
13216 that monopoly power to extract the most they can from the market. That
13217 power is in turn used to keep the prices high.
13220 There are many who are skeptical of patents, especially drug
13221 patents. I am not. Indeed, of all the areas of research that might be
13222 supported by patents, drug research is, in my view, the clearest case
13223 where patents are needed. The patent gives the drug company some
13224 assurance that if it is successful in inventing a new drug to treat a
13225 disease, it will be able to earn back its investment and more. This is
13226 socially an extremely valuable incentive. I am the last person who
13227 would argue that the law should abolish it, at least without other
13231 But it is one thing to support patents, even drug patents. It is
13232 another thing to determine how best to deal with a crisis. And as
13233 African leaders began to recognize the devastation that AIDS was
13234 bringing, they started looking for ways to import HIV treatments at
13235 costs significantly below the market price.
13237 <indexterm id='idxinternationallaw2' class='startofrange'
><primary>international law
</primary></indexterm>
13238 <indexterm id='idxparallelimportation' class='startofrange'
><primary>parallel importation
</primary></indexterm>
13239 <indexterm id='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='startofrange'
><primary>South Africa, Republic of, pharmaceutical imports by
</primary></indexterm>
13241 In
1997, South Africa tried one tack. It passed a law to allow the
13242 importation of patented medicines that had been produced or sold in
13243 another nation's market with the consent of the patent owner. For
13244 example, if the drug was sold in India, it could be imported into
13245 Africa from India. This is called
<quote>parallel importation,
</quote> and it is
13246 generally permitted under international trade law and is specifically
13247 permitted within the European Union.
<footnote>
13250 See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite,
<citetitle>Information Feudalism: Who
13251 Owns the Knowledge Economy?
</citetitle> (New York: The New Press,
2003),
37.
13252 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John
</primary></indexterm>
13253 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13256 <indexterm><primary>United States Trade Representative (USTR)
</primary></indexterm>
13258 However, the United States government opposed the bill. Indeed, more
13259 than opposed. As the International Intellectual Property Association
13260 characterized it,
<quote>The U.S. government pressured South Africa
…
13261 not to permit compulsory licensing or parallel
13262 imports.
</quote><footnote><para>
13264 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI),
<citetitle>Patent
13265 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13266 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13267 Organization
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.,
2000),
14, available at
13268 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
56</ulink>. For a
13269 firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see Hearing
13270 Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human
13271 Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep.,
1st sess.,
13272 Ser. No.
106-
126 (
22 July
1999),
150–57 (statement of James
13275 Through the Office of the United States Trade Representative, the
13276 government asked South Africa to change the law
—and to add
13277 pressure to that request, in
1998, the USTR listed South Africa for
13278 possible trade sanctions.
13279 <!-- PAGE BREAK 266 -->
13280 That same year, more than forty pharmaceutical companies began
13281 proceedings in the South African courts to challenge the government's
13282 actions. The United States was then joined by other governments from
13283 the EU. Their claim, and the claim of the pharmaceutical companies,
13284 was that South Africa was violating its obligations under
13285 international law by discriminating against a particular kind of
13286 patent
— pharmaceutical patents. The demand of these governments,
13287 with the United States in the lead, was that South Africa respect
13288 these patents as it respects any other patent, regardless of any
13289 effect on the treatment of AIDS within South Africa.
<footnote><para>
13291 International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI),
<citetitle>Patent
13292 Protection and Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan
13293 Africa, a Report Prepared for the World Intellectual Property
13294 Organization
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.,
2000),
15.
</para></footnote>
13296 <indexterm startref='idxparallelimportation' class='endofrange'
/>
13298 We should place the intervention by the United States in context. No
13299 doubt patents are not the most important reason that Africans don't
13300 have access to drugs. Poverty and the total absence of an effective
13301 health care infrastructure matter more. But whether patents are the
13302 most important reason or not, the price of drugs has an effect on
13303 their demand, and patents affect price. And so, whether massive or
13304 marginal, there was an effect from our government's intervention to
13305 stop the flow of medications into Africa.
13308 By stopping the flow of HIV treatment into Africa, the United
13309 States government was not saving drugs for United States citizens.
13310 This is not like wheat (if they eat it, we can't); instead, the flow that the
13311 United States intervened to stop was, in effect, a flow of knowledge:
13312 information about how to take chemicals that exist within Africa, and
13313 turn those chemicals into drugs that would save
15 to
30 million lives.
13316 Nor was the intervention by the United States going to protect the
13317 profits of United States drug companies
—at least, not substantially. It
13318 was not as if these countries were in the position to buy the drugs for
13319 the prices the drug companies were charging. Again, the Africans are
13320 wildly too poor to afford these drugs at the offered prices. Stopping the
13321 parallel import of these drugs would not substantially increase the sales
13325 Instead, the argument in favor of restricting this flow of
13326 information, which was needed to save the lives of millions, was an
13328 <!-- PAGE BREAK 267 -->
13329 about the sanctity of property.
<footnote><para>
13331 See Sabin Russell,
<quote>New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's
13332 Needs at Odds with Firms' Profit Motive,
</quote> <citetitle>San Francisco Chronicle
</citetitle>,
24
13333 May
1999, A1, available at
13334 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
57</ulink>
13335 (
<quote>compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire
13336 system of intellectual property protection
</quote>); Robert Weissman,
<quote>AIDS
13337 and Developing Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential
13338 Medicines,
</quote> <citetitle>Foreign Policy in Focus
</citetitle> 4:
23 (August
1999), available at
13339 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
58</ulink>
13340 (describing U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson,
<quote>TRIPS, Pharmaceutical
13341 Patents, and the HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between
13342 Intellectual Property Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis,
</quote> <citetitle>Widener Law
13343 Symposium Journal
</citetitle> (Spring
2001):
175.
13344 <!-- PAGE BREAK 333 -->
13346 It was because
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> would be violated that these
13347 drugs should not flow into Africa. It was a principle about the
13348 importance of
<quote>intellectual property
</quote> that led these government actors
13349 to intervene against the South African response to AIDS.
13351 <indexterm startref='idxsouthafricarepublicofpharmaceuticalimportsby' class='endofrange'
/>
13353 Now just step back for a moment. There will be a time thirty years
13354 from now when our children look back at us and ask, how could we have
13355 let this happen? How could we allow a policy to be pursued whose
13356 direct cost would be to speed the death of
15 to
30 million Africans,
13357 and whose only real benefit would be to uphold the
<quote>sanctity
</quote> of an
13358 idea? What possible justification could there ever be for a policy
13359 that results in so many deaths? What exactly is the insanity that
13360 would allow so many to die for such an abstraction?
13362 <indexterm id='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='startofrange'
><primary>corporations
</primary><secondary>in pharmaceutical industry
</secondary></indexterm>
13364 Some blame the drug companies. I don't. They are corporations.
13365 Their managers are ordered by law to make money for the corporation.
13366 They push a certain patent policy not because of ideals, but because it is
13367 the policy that makes them the most money. And it only makes them the
13368 most money because of a certain corruption within our political system
—
13369 a corruption the drug companies are certainly not responsible for.
13372 The corruption is our own politicians' failure of integrity. For the
13373 drug companies would love
—they say, and I believe them
—to
13374 sell their drugs as cheaply as they can to countries in Africa and
13375 elsewhere. There are issues they'd have to resolve to make sure the
13376 drugs didn't get back into the United States, but those are mere
13377 problems of technology. They could be overcome.
13379 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary><secondary>of drug patents
</secondary></indexterm>
13381 A different problem, however, could not be overcome. This is the
13382 fear of the grandstanding politician who would call the presidents of
13383 the drug companies before a Senate or House hearing, and ask,
<quote>How
13384 is it you can sell this HIV drug in Africa for only $
1 a pill, but the same
13385 drug would cost an American $
1,
500?
</quote> Because there is no
<quote>sound
13386 bite
</quote> answer to that question, its effect would be to induce regulation
13387 of prices in America. The drug companies thus avoid this spiral by
13388 avoiding the first step. They reinforce the idea that property should be
13389 <!-- PAGE BREAK 268 -->
13390 sacred. They adopt a rational strategy in an irrational context, with the
13391 unintended consequence that perhaps millions die. And that rational
13392 strategy thus becomes framed in terms of this ideal
—the sanctity of an
13393 idea called
<quote>intellectual property.
</quote>
13395 <indexterm startref='idxafricamedicationsforhivpatientsin' class='endofrange'
/>
13396 <indexterm startref='idxaidsmedications' class='endofrange'
/>
13397 <indexterm startref='idxantiretroviraldrugs' class='endofrange'
/>
13398 <indexterm startref='idxdevelopingcountriesforeignpatentcostsin2' class='endofrange'
/>
13399 <indexterm startref='idxdrugspharmaceutical' class='endofrange'
/>
13400 <indexterm startref='idxhivaidstherapies' class='endofrange'
/>
13401 <indexterm startref='idxcorporationsinpharmaceuticalindustry' class='endofrange'
/>
13403 So when the common sense of your child confronts you, what will
13404 you say? When the common sense of a generation finally revolts
13405 against what we have done, how will we justify what we have done?
13406 What is the argument?
13409 A sensible patent policy could endorse and strongly support the patent
13410 system without having to reach everyone everywhere in exactly the same
13411 way. Just as a sensible copyright policy could endorse and strongly
13412 support a copyright system without having to regulate the spread of
13413 culture perfectly and forever, a sensible patent policy could endorse
13414 and strongly support a patent system without having to block the
13415 spread of drugs to a country not rich enough to afford market prices
13416 in any case. A sensible policy, in other words, could be a balanced
13417 policy. For most of our history, both copyright and patent policies
13418 were balanced in just this sense.
13420 <indexterm startref='idxpatentsonpharmaceuticals' class='endofrange'
/>
13421 <indexterm startref='idxpharmaceuticalpatents' class='endofrange'
/>
13422 <indexterm startref='idxinternationallaw2' class='endofrange'
/>
13424 But we as a culture have lost this sense of balance. We have lost the
13425 critical eye that helps us see the difference between truth and
13426 extremism. A certain property fundamentalism, having no connection to
13427 our tradition, now reigns in this culture
—bizarrely, and with
13428 consequences more grave to the spread of ideas and culture than almost
13429 any other single policy decision that we as a democracy will make.
13431 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsofdrugpatents' class='endofrange'
/>
13433 <emphasis role='strong'
>A simple idea
</emphasis> blinds us, and under
13434 the cover of darkness, much happens that most of us would reject if
13435 any of us looked. So uncritically do we accept the idea of property in
13436 ideas that we don't even notice how monstrous it is to deny ideas to a
13437 people who are dying without them. So uncritically do we accept the
13438 idea of property in culture that we don't even question when the
13439 control of that property removes our
13440 <!-- PAGE BREAK 269 -->
13441 ability, as a people, to develop our culture democratically. Blindness
13442 becomes our common sense. And the challenge for anyone who would
13443 reclaim the right to cultivate our culture is to find a way to make
13444 this common sense open its eyes.
13447 So far, common sense sleeps. There is no revolt. Common sense
13448 does not yet see what there could be to revolt about. The extremism
13449 that now dominates this debate fits with ideas that seem natural, and
13450 that fit is reinforced by the RCAs of our day. They wage a frantic war
13451 to fight
<quote>piracy,
</quote> and devastate a culture for creativity. They defend
13452 the idea of
<quote>creative property,
</quote> while transforming real creators into
13453 modern-day sharecroppers. They are insulted by the idea that rights
13454 should be balanced, even though each of the major players in this
13455 content war was itself a beneficiary of a more balanced ideal. The
13456 hypocrisy reeks. Yet in a city like Washington, hypocrisy is not even
13457 noticed. Powerful lobbies, complex issues, and MTV attention spans
13458 produce the
<quote>perfect storm
</quote> for free culture.
13460 <indexterm><primary>academic journals
</primary></indexterm>
13461 <indexterm><primary>biomedical research
</primary></indexterm>
13462 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of
</secondary></indexterm>
13463 <indexterm><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
13464 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
13465 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)
</primary></indexterm>
13466 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)
</primary></indexterm>
13467 <indexterm><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>public projects in
</secondary></indexterm>
13468 <indexterm><primary>single nucleotied polymorphisms (SNPs)
</primary></indexterm>
13469 <indexterm><primary>Wellcome Trust
</primary></indexterm>
13470 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='startofrange'
><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)
</primary></indexterm>
13471 <indexterm><primary>World Wide Web
</primary></indexterm>
13472 <indexterm><primary>Global Positioning System
</primary></indexterm>
13473 <indexterm><primary>Reagan, Ronald
</primary></indexterm>
13474 <indexterm id='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='startofrange'
><primary>biomedical research
</primary></indexterm>
13476 <emphasis role='strong'
>In August
2003</emphasis>, a fight broke out
13477 in the United States about a decision by the World Intellectual
13478 Property Organization to cancel a meeting.
<footnote><para>
13479 <!-- f6. --> Jonathan Krim,
<quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
13480 August
2003, E1, available at
13481 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
59</ulink>; William New,
<quote>Global Group's
13482 Shift on `Open Source' Meeting Spurs Stir,
</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13483 Daily
</citetitle>,
19 August
2003, available at
13484 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
60</ulink>; William New,
<quote>U.S. Official
13485 Opposes `Open Source' Talks at WIPO,
</quote> <citetitle>National Journal's Technology
13486 Daily
</citetitle>,
19 August
2003, available at
13487 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
61</ulink>.
13489 At the request of a wide range of interests, WIPO had decided to hold
13490 a meeting to discuss
<quote>open and collaborative projects to create public
13491 goods.
</quote> These are projects that have been successful in producing
13492 public goods without relying exclusively upon a proprietary use of
13493 intellectual property. Examples include the Internet and the World
13494 Wide Web, both of which were developed on the basis of protocols in
13495 the public domain. It included an emerging trend to support open
13496 academic journals, including the Public Library of Science project
13497 that I describe in chapter
13498 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"c-afterword"/>. It
13499 included a project to develop single nucleotide polymorphisms (SNPs),
13500 which are thought to have great significance in biomedical
13501 research. (That nonprofit project comprised a consortium of the
13502 Wellcome Trust and pharmaceutical and technological companies,
13503 including Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca,
13504 <!-- PAGE BREAK 270 -->
13505 Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, Hoffmann-La Roche,
13506 Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, and Searle.) It
13507 included the Global Positioning System, which Ronald Reagan set free
13508 in the early
1980s. And it included
<quote>open source and free software.
</quote>
13510 <indexterm startref='idxbiomedicalresearch' class='endofrange'
/>
13512 The aim of the meeting was to consider this wide range of projects
13513 from one common perspective: that none of these projects relied upon
13514 intellectual property extremism. Instead, in all of them, intellectual
13515 property was balanced by agreements to keep access open or to impose
13516 limitations on the way in which proprietary claims might be used.
13518 <indexterm id='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='startofrange'
><primary>Lessig, Lawrence
</primary><secondary>in international debate on intellectual property
</secondary></indexterm>
13520 From the perspective of this book, then, the conference was ideal.
<footnote><para>
13521 <!-- f7. --> I should disclose that I was one of the people who asked WIPO for the
13524 The projects within its scope included both commercial and
13525 noncommercial work. They primarily involved science, but from many
13526 perspectives. And WIPO was an ideal venue for this discussion, since
13527 WIPO is the preeminent international body dealing with intellectual
13530 <indexterm id='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='startofrange'
><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)
</primary></indexterm>
13532 Indeed, I was once publicly scolded for not recognizing this fact
13533 about WIPO. In February
2003, I delivered a keynote address to a
13534 preparatory conference for the World Summit on the Information Society
13535 (WSIS). At a press conference before the address, I was asked what I
13536 would say. I responded that I would be talking a little about the
13537 importance of balance in intellectual property for the development of
13538 an information society. The moderator for the event then promptly
13539 interrupted to inform me and the assembled reporters that no question
13540 about intellectual property would be discussed by WSIS, since those
13541 questions were the exclusive domain of WIPO. In the talk that I had
13542 prepared, I had actually made the issue of intellectual property
13543 relatively minor. But after this astonishing statement, I made
13544 intellectual property the sole focus of my talk. There was no way to
13545 talk about an
<quote>Information Society
</quote> unless one also talked about the
13546 range of information and culture that would be free. My talk did not
13547 make my immoderate moderator very happy. And she was no doubt correct
13548 that the scope of intellectual property protections was ordinarily the
13550 <!-- PAGE BREAK 271 -->
13551 WIPO. But in my view, there couldn't be too much of a conversation
13552 about how much intellectual property is needed, since in my view, the
13553 very idea of balance in intellectual property had been lost.
13556 So whether or not WSIS can discuss balance in intellectual property, I
13557 had thought it was taken for granted that WIPO could and should. And
13558 thus the meeting about
<quote>open and collaborative projects to create
13559 public goods
</quote> seemed perfectly appropriate within the WIPO agenda.
13561 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof' class='endofrange'
/>
13562 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo' class='endofrange'
/>
13563 <indexterm startref='idxworldsummitontheinformationsocietywsis' class='endofrange'
/>
13564 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='startofrange'
><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)
</primary></indexterm>
13565 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation
</primary></indexterm>
13566 <indexterm id='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='startofrange'
><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>on free software
</secondary></indexterm>
13568 But there is one project within that list that is highly
13569 controversial, at least among lobbyists. That project is
<quote>open source
13570 and free software.
</quote> Microsoft in particular is wary of discussion of
13571 the subject. From its perspective, a conference to discuss open source
13572 and free software would be like a conference to discuss Apple's
13573 operating system. Both open source and free software compete with
13574 Microsoft's software. And internationally, many governments have begun
13575 to explore requirements that they use open source or free software,
13576 rather than
<quote>proprietary software,
</quote> for their own internal uses.
13578 <indexterm><primary><quote>copyleft
</quote> licenses
</primary></indexterm>
13579 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
13580 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
13581 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
13583 I don't mean to enter that debate here. It is important only to
13584 make clear that the distinction is not between commercial and
13585 noncommercial software. There are many important companies that depend
13586 fundamentally upon open source and free software, IBM being the most
13587 prominent. IBM is increasingly shifting its focus to the GNU/Linux
13588 operating system, the most famous bit of
<quote>free software
</quote>—and IBM
13589 is emphatically a commercial entity. Thus, to support
<quote>open source and
13590 free software
</quote> is not to oppose commercial entities. It is, instead,
13591 to support a mode of software development that is different from
13592 Microsoft's.
<footnote><para>
13594 Microsoft's position about free and open source software is more
13595 sophisticated. As it has repeatedly asserted, it has no problem with
13596 <quote>open source
</quote> software or software in the public domain. Microsoft's
13597 principal opposition is to
<quote>free software
</quote> licensed under a
<quote>copyleft
</quote>
13598 license, meaning a license that requires the licensee to adopt the
13599 same terms on any derivative work. See Bradford L. Smith,
<quote>The Future
13600 of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide,
</quote> <citetitle>Government Policy
13601 Toward Open Source Software
</citetitle> (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint
13602 Center for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for
13603 Public Policy Research,
2002),
69, available at
13604 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
62</ulink>. See also
13605 Craig Mundie, Microsoft senior vice president,
<citetitle>The Commercial Software
13606 Model
</citetitle>, discussion at New York University Stern School of Business (
3
13607 May
2001), available at
13608 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
63</ulink>.
13611 <indexterm startref='idxlessiglawrenceininternationaldebateonintellectualproperty' class='endofrange'
/>
13612 <indexterm><primary>General Public License (GPL)
</primary></indexterm>
13613 <indexterm><primary>GPL (General Public License)
</primary></indexterm>
13615 More important for our purposes, to support
<quote>open source and free
13616 software
</quote> is not to oppose copyright.
<quote>Open source and free software
</quote>
13617 is not software in the public domain. Instead, like Microsoft's
13618 software, the copyright owners of free and open source software insist
13619 quite strongly that the terms of their software license be respected
13621 <!-- PAGE BREAK 272 -->
13622 adopters of free and open source software. The terms of that license
13623 are no doubt different from the terms of a proprietary software
13624 license. Free software licensed under the General Public License
13625 (GPL), for example, requires that the source code for the software be
13626 made available by anyone who modifies and redistributes the
13627 software. But that requirement is effective only if copyright governs
13628 software. If copyright did not govern software, then free software
13629 could not impose the same kind of requirements on its adopters. It
13630 thus depends upon copyright law just as Microsoft does.
13632 <indexterm id='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>intellectual property rights
</primary><secondary>international organization on issues of
</secondary></indexterm>
13633 <indexterm id='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='startofrange'
><primary>World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO)
</primary></indexterm>
13634 <indexterm id='idxkrimjonathan' class='startofrange'
><primary>Krim, Jonathan
</primary></indexterm>
13635 <indexterm><primary>Microsoft
</primary><secondary>WIPO meeting opposed by
</secondary></indexterm>
13637 It is therefore understandable that as a proprietary software
13638 developer, Microsoft would oppose this WIPO meeting, and
13639 understandable that it would use its lobbyists to get the United
13640 States government to oppose it, as well. And indeed, that is just what
13641 was reported to have happened. According to Jonathan Krim of the
13642 <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>, Microsoft's lobbyists succeeded in getting the United
13643 States government to veto the meeting.
<footnote><para>
13645 Krim,
<quote>The Quiet War over Open-Source,
</quote> available at
<ulink
13646 url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
64</ulink>.
13648 And without U.S. backing, the meeting was canceled.
13651 I don't blame Microsoft for doing what it can to advance its own
13652 interests, consistent with the law. And lobbying governments is
13653 plainly consistent with the law. There was nothing surprising about
13654 its lobbying here, and nothing terribly surprising about the most
13655 powerful software producer in the United States having succeeded in
13656 its lobbying efforts.
13658 <indexterm startref='idxmicrosoftonfreesoftware' class='endofrange'
/>
13659 <indexterm><primary>Boland, Lois
</primary></indexterm>
13661 What was surprising was the United States government's reason for
13662 opposing the meeting. Again, as reported by Krim, Lois Boland, acting
13663 director of international relations for the U.S. Patent and Trademark
13664 Office, explained that
<quote>open-source software runs counter to the
13665 mission of WIPO, which is to promote intellectual-property rights.
</quote>
13666 She is quoted as saying,
<quote>To hold a meeting which has as its purpose
13667 to disclaim or waive such rights seems to us to be contrary to the
13668 goals of WIPO.
</quote>
13670 <indexterm startref='idxkrimjonathan' class='endofrange'
/>
13672 These statements are astonishing on a number of levels.
13674 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss' class='endofrange'
/>
13675 <!-- PAGE BREAK 273 -->
13677 First, they are just flat wrong. As I described, most open source and
13678 free software relies fundamentally upon the intellectual property
13679 right called
<quote>copyright
</quote>. Without it, restrictions imposed by those
13680 licenses wouldn't work. Thus, to say it
<quote>runs counter
</quote> to the mission
13681 of promoting intellectual property rights reveals an extraordinary gap
13682 in understanding
—the sort of mistake that is excusable in a
13683 first-year law student, but an embarrassment from a high government
13684 official dealing with intellectual property issues.
13686 <indexterm><primary>World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS)
</primary></indexterm>
13687 <indexterm><primary>drugs
</primary><secondary>pharmaceutical
</secondary></indexterm>
13688 <indexterm><primary>generic drugs
</primary></indexterm>
13689 <indexterm><primary>patents
</primary><secondary>on pharmaceuticals
</secondary></indexterm>
13691 Second, who ever said that WIPO's exclusive aim was to
<quote>promote
</quote>
13692 intellectual property maximally? As I had been scolded at the
13693 preparatory conference of WSIS, WIPO is to consider not only how best
13694 to protect intellectual property, but also what the best balance of
13695 intellectual property is. As every economist and lawyer knows, the
13696 hard question in intellectual property law is to find that
13697 balance. But that there should be limits is, I had thought,
13698 uncontested. One wants to ask Ms. Boland, are generic drugs (drugs
13699 based on drugs whose patent has expired) contrary to the WIPO mission?
13700 Does the public domain weaken intellectual property? Would it have
13701 been better if the protocols of the Internet had been patented?
13703 <indexterm><primary>Gates, Bill
</primary></indexterm>
13705 Third, even if one believed that the purpose of WIPO was to maximize
13706 intellectual property rights, in our tradition, intellectual property
13707 rights are held by individuals and corporations. They get to decide
13708 what to do with those rights because, again, they are
13709 <emphasis>their
</emphasis> rights. If they want to
<quote>waive
</quote> or
13710 <quote>disclaim
</quote> their rights, that is, within our tradition, totally
13711 appropriate. When Bill Gates gives away more than $
20 billion to do
13712 good in the world, that is not inconsistent with the objectives of the
13713 property system. That is, on the contrary, just what a property system
13714 is supposed to be about: giving individuals the right to decide what
13715 to do with
<emphasis>their
</emphasis> property.
13717 <indexterm id='idxboland' class='startofrange'
><primary>Boland, Lois
</primary></indexterm>
13719 When Ms. Boland says that there is something wrong with a meeting
13720 <quote>which has as its purpose to disclaim or waive such rights,
</quote> she's
13721 saying that WIPO has an interest in interfering with the choices of
13722 <!-- PAGE BREAK 274 -->
13723 the individuals who own intellectual property rights. That somehow,
13724 WIPO's objective should be to stop an individual from
<quote>waiving
</quote> or
13725 <quote>disclaiming
</quote> an intellectual property right. That the interest of
13726 WIPO is not just that intellectual property rights be maximized, but
13727 that they also should be exercised in the most extreme and restrictive
13730 <indexterm id='idxfeudalsystem' class='startofrange'
><primary>feudal system
</primary></indexterm>
13731 <indexterm id='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='startofrange'
><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>feudal system of
</secondary></indexterm>
13733 There is a history of just such a property system that is well known
13734 in the Anglo-American tradition. It is called
<quote>feudalism.
</quote> Under
13735 feudalism, not only was property held by a relatively small number of
13736 individuals and entities. And not only were the rights that ran with
13737 that property powerful and extensive. But the feudal system had a
13738 strong interest in assuring that property holders within that system
13739 not weaken feudalism by liberating people or property within their
13740 control to the free market. Feudalism depended upon maximum control
13741 and concentration. It fought any freedom that might interfere with
13744 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13745 <indexterm><primary>Braithwaite, John
</primary></indexterm>
13747 As Peter Drahos and John Braithwaite relate, this is precisely the
13748 choice we are now making about intellectual property.
<footnote><para>
13750 See Drahos with Braithwaite,
<citetitle>Information Feudalism
</citetitle>,
210–20.
13751 <indexterm><primary>Drahos, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
13753 We will have an information society. That much is certain. Our only
13754 choice now is whether that information society will be
13755 <emphasis>free
</emphasis> or
<emphasis>feudal
</emphasis>. The trend is
13758 <indexterm startref='idxfeudalsystem' class='endofrange'
/>
13759 <indexterm startref='idxpropertyrightsfeudalsystemof' class='endofrange'
/>
13761 When this battle broke, I blogged it. A spirited debate within the
13762 comment section ensued. Ms. Boland had a number of supporters who
13763 tried to show why her comments made sense. But there was one comment
13764 that was particularly depressing for me. An anonymous poster wrote,
13767 <indexterm startref='idxintellectualpropertyrightsinternationalorganizationonissuesof2' class='endofrange'
/>
13768 <indexterm startref='idxworldintellectualpropertyorganizationwipo2' class='endofrange'
/>
13770 George, you misunderstand Lessig: He's only talking about the world as
13771 it should be (
<quote>the goal of WIPO, and the goal of any government,
13772 should be to promote the right balance of intellectual property rights,
13773 not simply to promote intellectual property rights
</quote>), not as it is. If
13774 we were talking about the world as it is, then of course Boland didn't
13775 say anything wrong. But in the world
13776 <!-- PAGE BREAK 275 -->
13777 as Lessig would have it, then of course she did. Always pay attention
13778 to the distinction between Lessig's world and ours.
13782 I missed the irony the first time I read it. I read it quickly and
13783 thought the poster was supporting the idea that seeking balance was
13784 what our government should be doing. (Of course, my criticism of Ms.
13785 Boland was not about whether she was seeking balance or not; my
13786 criticism was that her comments betrayed a first-year law student's
13787 mistake. I have no illusion about the extremism of our government,
13788 whether Republican or Democrat. My only illusion apparently is about
13789 whether our government should speak the truth or not.)
13791 <indexterm startref='idxboland' class='endofrange'
/>
13793 Obviously, however, the poster was not supporting that idea. Instead,
13794 the poster was ridiculing the very idea that in the real world, the
13795 <quote>goal
</quote> of a government should be
<quote>to promote the right balance
</quote> of
13796 intellectual property. That was obviously silly to him. And it
13797 obviously betrayed, he believed, my own silly utopianism.
<quote>Typical for
13798 an academic,
</quote> the poster might well have continued.
13801 I understand criticism of academic utopianism. I think utopianism is
13802 silly, too, and I'd be the first to poke fun at the absurdly
13803 unrealistic ideals of academics throughout history (and not just in
13804 our own country's history).
13807 But when it has become silly to suppose that the role of our
13808 government should be to
<quote>seek balance,
</quote> then count me with the silly,
13809 for that means that this has become quite serious indeed. If it should
13810 be obvious to everyone that the government does not seek balance, that
13811 the government is simply the tool of the most powerful lobbyists, that
13812 the idea of holding the government to a different standard is absurd,
13813 that the idea of demanding of the government that it speak truth and
13814 not lies is just na
ïve, then who have we, the most powerful
13815 democracy in the world, become?
13818 It might be crazy to expect a high government official to speak
13819 the truth. It might be crazy to believe that government policy will be
13820 something more than the handmaiden of the most powerful interests.
13821 <!-- PAGE BREAK 276 -->
13822 It might be crazy to argue that we should preserve a tradition that has
13823 been part of our tradition for most of our history
—free culture.
13826 If this is crazy, then let there be more crazies. Soon.
13828 <indexterm><primary>CodePink Women in Peace
</primary></indexterm>
13829 <indexterm><primary>Safire, William
</primary></indexterm>
13830 <indexterm><primary>Turner, Ted
</primary></indexterm>
13832 <emphasis role='strong'
>There are moments
</emphasis> of hope in this
13833 struggle. And moments that surprise. When the FCC was considering
13834 relaxing ownership rules, which would thereby further increase the
13835 concentration in media ownership, an extraordinary bipartisan
13836 coalition formed to fight this change. For perhaps the first time in
13837 history, interests as diverse as the NRA, the ACLU, Moveon.org,
13838 William Safire, Ted Turner, and CodePink Women for Peace organized to
13839 oppose this change in FCC policy. An astonishing
700,
000 letters were
13840 sent to the FCC, demanding more hearings and a different result.
13843 This activism did not stop the FCC, but soon after, a broad coalition
13844 in the Senate voted to reverse the FCC decision. The hostile hearings
13845 leading up to that vote revealed just how powerful this movement had
13846 become. There was no substantial support for the FCC's decision, and
13847 there was broad and sustained support for fighting further
13848 concentration in the media.
13851 But even this movement misses an important piece of the puzzle.
13852 Largeness as such is not bad. Freedom is not threatened just because
13853 some become very rich, or because there are only a handful of big
13854 players. The poor quality of Big Macs or Quarter Pounders does not
13855 mean that you can't get a good hamburger from somewhere else.
13858 The danger in media concentration comes not from the concentration,
13859 but instead from the feudalism that this concentration, tied to the
13860 change in copyright, produces. It is not just that there are a few
13861 powerful companies that control an ever expanding slice of the
13862 media. It is that this concentration can call upon an equally bloated
13863 range of rights
—property rights of a historically extreme
13864 form
—that makes their bigness bad.
13866 <!-- PAGE BREAK 277 -->
13868 It is therefore significant that so many would rally to demand
13869 competition and increased diversity. Still, if the rally is understood
13870 as being about bigness alone, it is not terribly surprising. We
13871 Americans have a long history of fighting
<quote>big,
</quote> wisely or not. That
13872 we could be motivated to fight
<quote>big
</quote> again is not something new.
13875 It would be something new, and something very important, if an equal
13876 number could be rallied to fight the increasing extremism built within
13877 the idea of
<quote>intellectual property.
</quote> Not because balance is alien to
13878 our tradition; indeed, as I've argued, balance is our tradition. But
13879 because the muscle to think critically about the scope of anything
13880 called
<quote>property
</quote> is not well exercised within this tradition anymore.
13883 If we were Achilles, this would be our heel. This would be the place
13886 <indexterm><primary>Dylan, Bob
</primary></indexterm>
13888 <emphasis role='strong'
>As I write
</emphasis> these final words, the
13889 news is filled with stories about the RIAA lawsuits against almost
13890 three hundred individuals.
<footnote><para>
13892 John Borland,
<quote>RIAA Sues
261 File Swappers,
</quote> CNET News.com, September
13894 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
65</ulink>; Paul
13895 R. La Monica,
<quote>Music Industry Sues Swappers,
</quote> CNN/Money,
8 September
13897 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
66</ulink>; Soni
13898 Sangha and Phyllis Furman with Robert Gearty,
<quote>Sued for a Song,
13899 N.Y.C.
12-Yr-Old Among
261 Cited as Sharers,
</quote> <citetitle>New York Daily News
</citetitle>,
9
13900 September
2003,
3; Frank Ahrens,
<quote>RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised
13901 Targets; Single Mother in Calif.,
12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among
13902 Defendants,
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003, E1; Katie Dean,
13903 <quote>Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA,
</quote> <citetitle>Wired News
</citetitle>,
10 September
2003,
13905 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
67</ulink>.
13907 Eminem has just been sued for
<quote>sampling
</quote> someone else's
13908 music.
<footnote><para>
13910 Jon Wiederhorn,
<quote>Eminem Gets Sued
… by a Little Old Lady,
</quote>
13911 mtv.com,
17 September
2003, available at
13912 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
68</ulink>.
13914 The story about Bob Dylan
<quote>stealing
</quote> from a Japanese author has just
13915 finished making the rounds.
<footnote><para>
13917 Kenji Hall, Associated Press,
<quote>Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for
13918 Dylan Songs,
</quote> Kansascity.com,
9 July
2003, available at
13919 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
69</ulink>.
13920 <!-- PAGE BREAK 334 -->
13922 An insider from Hollywood
—who insists he must remain
13923 anonymous
—reports
<quote>an amazing conversation with these studio
13924 guys. They've got extraordinary [old] content that they'd love to use
13925 but can't because they can't begin to clear the rights. They've got
13926 scores of kids who could do amazing things with the content, but it
13927 would take scores of lawyers to clean it first.
</quote> Congressmen are
13928 talking about deputizing computer viruses to bring down computers
13929 thought to violate the law. Universities are threatening expulsion for
13930 kids who use a computer to share content.
13932 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Thomas Lee
</primary></indexterm>
13933 <indexterm><primary>Causby, Tinie
</primary></indexterm>
13934 <indexterm><primary>BBC
</primary></indexterm>
13935 <indexterm><primary>Brazil, free culture in
</primary></indexterm>
13936 <indexterm><primary>Creative Commons
</primary></indexterm>
13937 <indexterm><primary>Gil, Gilberto
</primary></indexterm>
13938 <indexterm><primary>United Kingdom
</primary><secondary>public creative archive in
</secondary></indexterm>
13940 Yet on the other side of the Atlantic, the BBC has just announced
13941 that it will build a
<quote>Creative Archive,
</quote> from which British citizens can
13942 download BBC content, and rip, mix, and burn it.
<footnote><para>
13943 <!-- f14. --> <quote>BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public,
</quote> BBC press release,
13944 24 August
2003, available at
13945 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
70</ulink>.
13947 And in Brazil, the culture minister, Gilberto Gil, himself a folk hero
13948 of Brazilian music, has joined with Creative Commons to release
13949 content and free licenses in that Latin American
13950 country.
<footnote><para>
13952 <quote>Creative Commons and Brazil,
</quote> Creative Commons Weblog,
6 August
2003,
13954 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
71</ulink>.
13956 <!-- PAGE BREAK 278 -->
13957 I've told a dark story. The truth is more mixed. A technology has
13958 given us a new freedom. Slowly, some begin to understand that this
13959 freedom need not mean anarchy. We can carry a free culture into the
13960 twenty-first century, without artists losing and without the potential of
13961 digital technology being destroyed. It will take some thought, and
13962 more importantly, it will take some will to transform the RCAs of our
13963 day into the Causbys.
13966 Common sense must revolt. It must act to free culture. Soon, if this
13967 potential is ever to be realized.
13969 <!-- PAGE BREAK 279 -->
13973 <chapter label=
"" id=
"c-afterword">
13974 <title>AFTERWORD
</title>
13977 <!-- PAGE BREAK 280 -->
13978 <emphasis role='strong'
>At least some
</emphasis> who have read this
13979 far will agree with me that something must be done to change where we
13980 are heading. The balance of this book maps what might be done.
13983 I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now,
13984 and that which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson
13985 that we can draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that
13986 it requires remaking how many people think about the very same issue.
13989 That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a
13990 significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators,
13991 authors, musicians, filmmakers, scientists
—all to tell this
13992 story in their own words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle
13996 Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of
13997 having an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people
13998 think matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands
13999 opposed, but still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I
14000 sketch changes that Congress could make to better secure a free culture.
14002 <!-- PAGE BREAK 281 -->
14004 <section id=
"usnow">
14005 <title>US, NOW
</title>
14007 <emphasis role='strong'
>Common sense
</emphasis> is with the copyright
14008 warriors because the debate so far has been framed at the
14009 extremes
—as a grand either/or: either property or anarchy,
14010 either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is the
14011 choice, then the warriors should win.
14014 The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are
14015 extremes in this debate, but the extremes are not all that there
14016 is. There are those who believe in maximal copyright
—<quote>All Rights
14017 Reserved
</quote>— and those who reject copyright
—<quote>No Rights
14018 Reserved.
</quote> The
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts believe that you should ask
14019 permission before you
<quote>use
</quote> a copyrighted work in any way. The
<quote>No
14020 Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts believe you should be able to do with content
14021 as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or not.
14023 <indexterm id='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>development of
</secondary></indexterm>
14024 <indexterm id='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>initial free character of
</secondary></indexterm>
14026 When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively
14027 tilted in the
<quote>no rights reserved
</quote> direction. Content could be copied
14028 perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus,
14029 regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under
14032 <!-- PAGE BREAK 282 -->
14033 original design of the Internet was
<quote>no rights reserved.
</quote> Content was
14034 <quote>taken
</quote> regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively
14038 This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite
14039 equal) by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this
14040 book. Through legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's
14041 design, copyright holders have been able to change the essential
14042 character of the environment of the original Internet. If the original
14043 architecture made the effective default
<quote>no rights reserved,
</quote> the
14044 future architecture will make the effective default
<quote>all rights
14045 reserved.
</quote> The architecture and law that surround the Internet's
14046 design will increasingly produce an environment where all use of
14047 content requires permission. The
<quote>cut and paste
</quote> world that defines
14048 the Internet today will become a
<quote>get permission to cut and paste
</quote>
14049 world that is a creator's nightmare.
14051 <indexterm startref='idxinternetdevelopmentof2' class='endofrange'
/>
14052 <indexterm startref='idxinternetinitialfreecharacterof' class='endofrange'
/>
14054 What's needed is a way to say something in the middle
—neither
14055 <quote>all rights reserved
</quote> nor
<quote>no rights reserved
</quote> but
<quote>some rights
14056 reserved
</quote>— and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable
14057 creators to free content as they see fit. In other words, we need a
14058 way to restore a set of freedoms that we could just take for granted
14061 <section id=
"examples">
14062 <title>Rebuilding Freedoms Previously Presumed: Examples
</title>
14063 <indexterm id='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='startofrange'
><primary>free culture
</primary><secondary>restoration efforts on previous aspects of
</secondary></indexterm>
14064 <indexterm id='idxbrowsing' class='startofrange'
><primary>browsing
</primary></indexterm>
14065 <indexterm id='idxprivacyrights2' class='startofrange'
><primary>privacy rights
</primary></indexterm>
14067 If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will
14068 recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about
14069 privacy. Before the Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much
14070 about data about our lives that we broadcast to the world. If you
14071 walked into a bookstore and browsed through some of the works of Karl
14072 Marx, you didn't need to worry about explaining your browsing habits
14073 to your neighbors or boss. The
<quote>privacy
</quote> of your browsing habits was
14077 What made it assured?
14079 <!-- PAGE BREAK 283 -->
14081 Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter
14082 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"property-i"/>, your
14083 privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for
14084 gathering data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who
14085 wanted to gather that data. If you were a suspected spy for North
14086 Korea, working for the CIA, no doubt your privacy would not be
14087 assured. But that's because the CIA would (we hope) find it valuable
14088 enough to spend the thousands required to track you. But for most of
14089 us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The highly inefficient
14090 architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly robust amount
14091 of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not by law
14092 (there is no law protecting
<quote>privacy
</quote> in public places), and in many
14093 places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead,
14094 by the costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy.
14096 <indexterm id='idxamazon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Amazon
</primary></indexterm>
14097 <indexterm><primary>cookies, Internet
</primary></indexterm>
14098 <indexterm id='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='startofrange'
><primary>Internet
</primary><secondary>privacy protection on
</secondary></indexterm>
14100 Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular
14101 has become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you
14102 browse the pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked
14103 at. You know this because at the side of the page, there's a list of
14104 <quote>recently viewed
</quote> pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net
14105 and the function of cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the
14106 data than not. The friction has disappeared, and hence any
<quote>privacy
</quote>
14107 protected by the friction disappears, too.
14109 <indexterm><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>privacy rights in use of
</secondary></indexterm>
14111 Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry
14112 about libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that
14113 people should have the
<quote>right
</quote> to browse in a library without the
14114 government knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties,
14115 too), then this change in the technology of monitoring might concern
14116 you. If it becomes simple to gather and sort who does what in
14117 electronic spaces, then the friction-induced privacy of yesterday
14120 <indexterm startref='idxbrowsing' class='endofrange'
/>
14121 <indexterm startref='idxamazon' class='endofrange'
/>
14123 It is this reality that explains the push of many to define
<quote>privacy
</quote>
14124 on the Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what
14125 friction before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what
14126 friction did.
<footnote><para>
14129 See, for example, Marc Rotenberg,
<quote>Fair Information Practices and the
14130 Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get),
</quote> <citetitle>Stanford Technology
14131 Law Review
</citetitle> 1 (
2001): par.
6–18, available at
14133 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
72</ulink>
14134 (describing examples in which technology defines privacy policy). See
14135 also Jeffrey Rosen,
<citetitle>The Naked Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom
14136 in an Anxious Age
</citetitle> (New York: Random House,
2004) (mapping tradeoffs
14137 between technology and privacy).
</para></footnote>
14138 And whether you're in favor of those laws or not, it is the pattern
14139 that is important here. We must take affirmative steps to secure a
14141 <!-- PAGE BREAK 284 -->
14142 kind of freedom that was passively provided before. A change in
14143 technology now forces those who believe in privacy to affirmatively
14144 act where, before, privacy was given by default.
14146 <indexterm startref='idxprivacyrights2' class='endofrange'
/>
14147 <indexterm startref='idxinternetprivacyprotectionon' class='endofrange'
/>
14148 <indexterm><primary>Data General
</primary></indexterm>
14149 <indexterm><primary>IBM
</primary></indexterm>
14150 <indexterm id='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='startofrange'
><primary>free software/open-source software (FS/OSS)
</primary></indexterm>
14152 A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software
14153 movement. When computers with software were first made available
14154 commercially, the software
—both the source code and the
14155 binaries
— was free. You couldn't run a program written for a
14156 Data General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't
14157 care much about controlling their software.
14159 <indexterm id='idxstallmanrichard' class='startofrange'
><primary>Stallman, Richard
</primary></indexterm>
14161 That was the world Richard Stallman was born into, and while he was a
14162 researcher at MIT, he grew to love the community that developed when
14163 one was free to explore and tinker with the software that ran on
14164 machines. Being a smart sort himself, and a talented programmer,
14165 Stallman grew to depend upon the freedom to add to or modify other
14169 In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical
14170 idea. In a math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a
14171 proof that someone offered. If you thought you had a better way to
14172 prove a theorem, you could take what someone else did and change
14173 it. In a classics department, if you believed a colleague's
14174 translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, you were free to
14175 improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you should be
14176 free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This,
14177 too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like
14180 <indexterm id='idxproprietarycode' class='startofrange'
><primary>proprietary code
</primary></indexterm>
14182 No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue
14183 for computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from
14184 one system to another, it became economically attractive (at least in
14185 the view of some) to hide the code of your program. So, too, as
14186 companies started selling peripherals for mainframe systems. If I
14187 could just take your printer driver and copy it, then that would make
14188 it easier for me to sell a printer to the market than it was for you.
14191 Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the
14192 early
1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code.
14193 <!-- PAGE BREAK 285 -->
14194 The world of free software had been erased by a change in the
14195 economics of computing. And as he believed, if he did nothing about
14196 it, then the freedom to change and share software would be
14197 fundamentally weakened.
14199 <indexterm startref='idxproprietarycode' class='endofrange'
/>
14200 <indexterm><primary>Torvalds, Linus
</primary></indexterm>
14202 Therefore, in
1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating
14203 system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That
14204 was the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's
<quote>Linux
</quote>
14205 kernel was added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system.
14206 <indexterm><primary>GNU/Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
14207 <indexterm><primary>Linux operating system
</primary></indexterm>
14210 Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of
14211 software that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free
14212 Software Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless
14213 the source code for that software is made available as well. Thus,
14214 anyone building upon GPL'd software would have to make their buildings
14215 free as well. This would assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of
14216 code would develop that remained free for others to build upon. His
14217 fundamental goal was freedom; innovative creative code was a
14221 Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now
14222 do for privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that
14223 was taken for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses
14224 that bind copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a
14225 space where free software would survive. He was actively protecting
14226 what before had been passively guaranteed.
14228 <indexterm startref='idxfreesoftwareopensourcesoftwarefsoss2' class='endofrange'
/>
14229 <indexterm startref='idxstallmanrichard' class='endofrange'
/>
14230 <indexterm id='idxacademicjournals' class='startofrange'
><primary>academic journals
</primary></indexterm>
14231 <indexterm id='idxscientificjournals' class='startofrange'
><primary>scientific journals
</primary></indexterm>
14233 Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates
14234 with the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and
14235 scientific journals are produced.
14237 <indexterm id='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='startofrange'
><primary>Lexis and Westlaw
</primary></indexterm>
14238 <indexterm id='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>law
</primary><secondary>databases of case reports in
</secondary></indexterm>
14239 <indexterm><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>journals in
</secondary></indexterm>
14240 <indexterm><primary>Supreme Court, U.S.
</primary><secondary>access to opinions of
</secondary></indexterm>
14242 As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that
14243 printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them
14244 to libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute
14245 knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and
14246 libraries and their users are given access to these electronic
14247 journals through password-protected sites. Something similar to this
14248 has been happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw
14249 have had electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers
14250 to their service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not
14251 copyrighted, and anyone is free to go to a library and read it, Lexis
14252 and Westlaw are also free
14253 <!-- PAGE BREAK 286 -->
14254 to charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme
14255 Court opinion through their respective services.
14257 <indexterm><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>access fees for material in
</secondary></indexterm>
14258 <indexterm id='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='startofrange'
><primary>public domain
</primary><secondary>license system for rebuilding of
</secondary></indexterm>
14260 There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to
14261 charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive
14262 for people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge.
14263 The law has agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed
14264 to flourish. And if there's nothing wrong with selling the public
14265 domain, then there could be nothing wrong, in principle, with selling
14266 access to material that is not in the public domain.
14268 <indexterm startref='idxlexisandwestlaw' class='endofrange'
/>
14269 <indexterm startref='idxlawdatabasesofcasereportsin' class='endofrange'
/>
14271 But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data
14272 was through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to
14273 browse this data except by paying for a subscription?
14275 <indexterm id='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='startofrange'
><primary>libraries
</primary><secondary>journals in
</secondary></indexterm>
14277 As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with
14278 scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper
14279 form, libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had
14280 access to the library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer
14281 experts because the library gave them access. Or patients trying to
14282 understand the risks of a certain treatment could research those risks
14283 by reading all available articles about that treatment. This freedom
14284 was therefore a function of the institution of libraries (norms) and
14285 the technology of paper journals (architecture)
—namely, that it
14286 was very hard to control access to a paper journal.
14289 As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding
14290 that libraries not give the general public access to the
14291 journals. This means that the freedoms provided by print journals in
14292 public libraries begin to disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with
14293 software, a changing technology and market shrink a freedom taken for
14296 <indexterm><primary>PLoS (Public Library of Science)
</primary></indexterm>
14297 <indexterm><primary>Public Library of Science (PLoS)
</primary></indexterm>
14299 This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to
14300 restore the freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science
14301 (PLoS), for example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making
14302 scientific research available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors
14303 <!-- PAGE BREAK 287 -->
14304 of scientific work submit that work to the Public Library of Science.
14305 That work is then subject to peer review. If accepted, the work is
14306 then deposited in a public, electronic archive and made permanently
14307 available for free. PLoS also sells a print version of its work, but
14308 the copyright for the print journal does not inhibit the right of
14309 anyone to redistribute the work for free.
14311 <indexterm startref='idxlibrariesjournalsin' class='endofrange'
/>
14313 This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for
14314 granted before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets.
14315 There's no doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional
14316 publishers and their efforts to make money from the exclusive
14317 distribution of content. But competition in our tradition is
14318 presumptively a good
—especially when it helps spread knowledge
14321 <indexterm startref='idxfreeculturerestorationeffortsonpreviousaspectsof' class='endofrange'
/>
14322 <indexterm startref='idxacademicjournals' class='endofrange'
/>
14323 <indexterm startref='idxscientificjournals' class='endofrange'
/>
14325 <section id=
"oneidea">
14326 <title>Rebuilding Free Culture: One Idea
</title>
14327 <indexterm id='idxcreativecommons' class='startofrange'
><primary>Creative Commons
</primary></indexterm>
14329 The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the
14330 increasing control effected through law and technology.
14332 <indexterm><primary>Stanford University
</primary></indexterm>
14334 Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit
14335 corporation established in Massachusetts, but with its home at
14336 Stanford University. Its aim is to build a layer of
14337 <emphasis>reasonable
</emphasis> copyright on top of the extremes that
14338 now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon
14339 other people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the
14340 freedom for others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags,
14341 tied to human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses,
14342 make this possible.
14345 <emphasis>Simple
</emphasis>—which means without a middleman, or
14346 without a lawyer. By developing a free set of licenses that people
14347 can attach to their content, Creative Commons aims to mark a range of
14348 content that can easily, and reliably, be built upon. These tags are
14349 then linked to machine-readable versions of the license that enable
14350 computers automatically to identify content that can easily be
14351 shared. These three expressions together
—a legal license, a
14352 human-readable description, and
14353 <!-- PAGE BREAK 288 -->
14354 machine-readable tags
—constitute a Creative Commons license. A
14355 Creative Commons license constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who
14356 accesses the license, and more importantly, an expression of the ideal
14357 that the person associated with the license believes in something
14358 different than the
<quote>All
</quote> or
<quote>No
</quote> extremes. Content is marked with the
14359 CC mark, which does not mean that copyright is waived, but that
14360 certain freedoms are given.
14363 These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their
14364 precise contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The
14365 creator can choose a license that permits any use, so long as
14366 attribution is given. She can choose a license that permits only
14367 noncommercial use. She can choose a license that permits any use so
14368 long as the same freedoms are given to other uses (
<quote>share and share
14369 alike
</quote>). Or any use so long as no derivative use is made. Or any use
14370 at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so long as full
14371 copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use.
14374 These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of
14375 copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional
14376 fair use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way
14377 that subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a
14378 lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content,
14379 governed by a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build
14380 upon. Voluntary choice of individuals and creators will make this
14381 content available. And that content will in turn enable us to rebuild
14384 <indexterm><primary>Garlick, Mia
</primary></indexterm>
14386 This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And
14387 of course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such
14388 freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from
14389 many is that we are not interested only in talking about a public
14390 domain or in getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our
14391 aim is to build a movement of consumers and producers
14392 <!-- PAGE BREAK 289 -->
14393 of content (
<quote>content conducers,
</quote> as attorney Mia Garlick calls them)
14394 who help build the public domain and, by their work, demonstrate the
14395 importance of the public domain to other creativity.
14397 <indexterm><primary>Jefferson, Thomas
</primary></indexterm>
14399 The aim is not to fight the
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote> sorts. The aim is to
14400 complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture
14401 are produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written
14402 centuries ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have
14403 imagined. The rules may well have made sense against a background of
14404 technologies from centuries ago, but they do not make sense against
14405 the background of digital technologies. New rules
—with different
14406 freedoms, expressed in ways so that humans without lawyers can use
14407 them
—are needed. Creative Commons gives people a way effectively
14408 to begin to build those rules.
14410 <indexterm id='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='startofrange'
><primary>books
</primary><secondary>free on-line releases of
</secondary></indexterm>
14412 Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some
14413 participate to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for
14414 example, is a science fiction author. His first novel,
<citetitle>Down and Out in
14415 the Magic Kingdom
</citetitle>, was released on-line and for free, under a Creative
14416 Commons license, on the same day that it went on sale in bookstores.
14419 Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher
14420 reasoned like this: There are two groups of people out there: (
1)
14421 those who will buy Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet,
14422 and (
2) those who may never hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made
14423 available for free on the Internet. Some part of (
1) will download
14424 Cory's book instead of buying it. Call them bad-(
1)s. Some part of (
2)
14425 will download Cory's book, like it, and then decide to buy it. Call
14426 them (
2)-goods. If there are more (
2)-goods than bad-(
1)s, the
14427 strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line will probably
14428 <emphasis>increase
</emphasis> sales of Cory's book.
14431 Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that
14432 conclusion. The book's first printing was exhausted months before the
14433 publisher had expected. This first novel of a science fiction author
14434 was a total success.
14436 <indexterm><primary>Free for All (Wayner)
</primary></indexterm>
14437 <indexterm><primary>Wayner, Peter
</primary></indexterm>
14439 The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content
14440 was confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner,
14441 <!-- PAGE BREAK 290 -->
14442 who wrote a book about the free software movement titled
<citetitle>Free for All
</citetitle>,
14443 made an electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative
14444 Commons license after the book went out of print. He then monitored
14445 used book store prices for the book. As predicted, as the number of
14446 downloads increased, the used book price for his book increased, as
14449 <indexterm startref='idxbooksfreeonline2' class='endofrange'
/>
14450 <indexterm><primary>Public Enemy
</primary></indexterm>
14451 <indexterm><primary>rap music
</primary></indexterm>
14452 <indexterm><primary>Leaphart, Walter
</primary></indexterm>
14454 These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary
14455 content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the
14456 Commons. There are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other
14457 reasons. Many who use the
<quote>sampling license
</quote> do so because anything
14458 else would be hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are
14459 free, for commercial or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from
14460 the licensed work; they are just not free to make full copies of the
14461 licensed work available to others. This is consistent with their own
14462 art
—they, too, sample from others. Because the
14463 <emphasis>legal
</emphasis> costs of sampling are so high (Walter
14464 Leaphart, manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born
14465 sampling the music of others, has stated that he does not
<quote>allow
</quote>
14466 Public Enemy to sample anymore, because the legal costs are so
14467 high
<footnote><para>
14469 <citetitle>Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real
14470 Culture Wars
</citetitle> (
2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg
14471 Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre production, available at
14472 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
72</ulink>.
14473 </para></footnote>),
14474 these artists release into the creative environment content
14475 that others can build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow.
14478 Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons
14479 license just because they want to express to others the importance of
14480 balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is,
14481 you are effectively saying you believe in the
<quote>All Rights Reserved
</quote>
14482 model. Good for you, but many do not. Many believe that however
14483 appropriate that rule is for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an
14484 appropriate description of how most creators view the rights
14485 associated with their content. The Creative Commons license expresses
14486 this notion of
<quote>Some Rights Reserved,
</quote> and gives many the chance to
14490 In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over
14491 1 million objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next
14492 step is partnerships with middleware content providers to help them
14493 build into their technologies simple ways for users to mark their content
14495 <!-- PAGE BREAK 291 -->
14496 with Creative Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and
14497 celebrate creators who build content based upon content set free.
14500 These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not
14501 mere arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first
14502 step to showing people how important that domain is to creativity and
14503 innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve
14504 this rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary
14505 steps are possible.
14508 Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by
14509 individuals and creators to change the mix of rights that now govern
14510 the creative field. The project does not compete with copyright; it
14511 complements it. Its aim is not to defeat the rights of authors, but to
14512 make it easier for authors and creators to exercise their rights more
14513 flexibly and cheaply. That difference, we believe, will enable
14514 creativity to spread more easily.
14516 <indexterm startref='idxpublicdomainlicensesystemforrebuildingof' class='endofrange'
/>
14517 <indexterm startref='idxcreativecommons' class='endofrange'
/>
14518 <!-- PAGE BREAK 292 -->
14521 <section id=
"themsoon">
14522 <title>THEM, SOON
</title>
14524 <emphasis role='strong'
>We will
</emphasis> not reclaim a free culture
14525 by individual action alone. It will also take important reforms of
14526 laws. We have a long way to go before the politicians will listen to
14527 these ideas and implement these reforms. But that also means that we
14528 have time to build awareness around the changes that we need.
14531 In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general,
14532 and one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each
14533 is a step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way
14537 <section id=
"formalities">
14538 <title>1. More Formalities
</title>
14540 If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land
14541 upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed.
14542 If you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an
14543 airplane ticket, it has your name on it.
14546 <!-- PAGE BREAK 293 -->
14547 These are all formalities associated with property. They are
14548 requirements that we all must bear if we want our property to be
14552 In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a
14553 copyright, regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You
14554 don't have to register. You don't even have to mark your content. The
14555 default is control, and
<quote>formalities
</quote> are banished.
14561 As I suggested in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
14562 linkend=
"property-i"/>, the motivation to abolish formalities was a
14563 good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities
14564 imposed a burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it
14565 was progress when the law relaxed the formal requirements that a
14566 copyright owner must bear to protect and secure his work. Those
14567 formalities were getting in the way.
14570 But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a
14571 burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that
14572 burdens creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns
14573 what, or with whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the
14574 creative work of others. There are no records, there is no system to
14575 trace
— there is no simple way to know how to get permission. Yet
14576 given the massive increase in the scope of copyright's rule, getting
14577 permission is a necessary step for any work that builds upon our
14578 past. And thus, the
<emphasis>lack
</emphasis> of formalities forces
14579 many into silence where they otherwise could speak.
14582 The law should therefore change this requirement
<footnote><para>
14584 The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only.
14585 Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be
14586 adopted by other countries as well.
</para></footnote>—but it
14587 should not change it by going back to the old, broken system. We
14588 should require formalities, but we should establish a system that will
14589 create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities.
14592 The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work,
14593 registering copyrights, and renewing the claim to
14594 copyright. Traditionally, the first of these three was something the
14595 copyright owner did; the second two were something the government
14596 did. But a revised system of formalities would banish the government
14597 from the process, except for the sole purpose of approving standards
14598 developed by others.
14601 <!-- PAGE BREAK 294 -->
14603 <section id=
"registration">
14604 <title>REGISTRATION AND RENEWAL
</title>
14606 Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration
14607 with the Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When
14608 filing that registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most
14609 government agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to
14610 minimize the burden of registration; it also had little incentive to
14611 minimize the fee. And as the Copyright Office is not a main target of
14612 government policymaking, the office has historically been terribly
14613 underfunded. Thus, when people who know something about the process
14614 hear this idea about formalities, their first reaction is
14615 panic
—nothing could be worse than forcing people to deal with
14616 the mess that is the Copyright Office.
14619 Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition
14620 of extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer
14621 think innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed.
14622 Just because there is a public purpose to a government role, it
14623 doesn't follow that the government must actually administer the
14624 role. Instead, we should be creating incentives for private parties to
14625 serve the public, subject to standards that the government sets.
14628 In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet.
14629 There are at least
32 million Web sites registered around the world.
14630 Domain name owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their
14631 registration alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net),
14632 there is a central registry. The actual registrations are, however,
14633 performed by many competing registrars. That competition drives the
14634 cost of registering down, and more importantly, it drives the ease
14635 with which registration occurs up.
14638 We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of
14639 copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central
14640 registry, but it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it
14641 should establish a database, and a set of standards for registrars. It
14642 should approve registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars
14643 would then compete with one another to deliver the cheapest and
14644 simplest systems for registering and renewing copyrights. That
14645 competition would substantially lower the burden of this
14646 formality
—while producing a database
14647 <!-- PAGE BREAK 295 -->
14648 of registrations that would facilitate the licensing of content.
14652 <section id=
"marking">
14653 <title>MARKING
</title>
14655 It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a
14656 creative work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh
14657 punishment for failing to comply with a regulatory rule
—akin to
14658 imposing the death penalty for a parking ticket in the world of
14659 creative rights. Here again, there is no reason that a marking
14660 requirement needs to be enforced in this way. And more importantly,
14661 there is no reason a marking requirement needs to be enforced
14662 uniformly across all media.
14665 The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is
14666 copyrighted and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark
14667 also makes it easy to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to
14671 One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was
14672 that different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't
14673 clear how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A
14674 new marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing
14675 the differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to
14676 evolve as technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special
14677 signal from the failure to mark
—not the loss of the copyright, but the
14678 loss of the right to punish someone for failing to get permission first.
14681 Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work
14682 to be published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that
14683 failure need not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could
14684 instead be that anyone has the right to use this work, until the
14685 copyright owner complains and demonstrates that it is his work and he
14686 doesn't give permission.
<footnote><para>
14688 There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not
14689 solved here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated
14690 system than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates.
14692 The meaning of an unmarked work would therefore be
<quote>use unless someone
14693 complains.
</quote> If someone does complain, then the obligation would be to
14694 stop using the work in any new
14695 <!-- PAGE BREAK 296 -->
14696 work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses.
14697 This would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark
14701 That in turn raises the question about how work should best be
14702 marked. Here again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies
14703 evolve. The best way to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the
14704 Copyright Office's role to that of approving standards for marking
14705 content that have been crafted elsewhere.
14707 <indexterm><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>copyright marking of
</secondary></indexterm>
14709 For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for
14710 marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The
14711 Copyright Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could
14712 be made. The Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it
14713 judged preferable, and it would base that choice
14714 <emphasis>solely
</emphasis> upon the consideration of which method
14715 could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We
14716 would not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on
14717 the government to keep the product of innovation in line with its
14718 other important functions.
14721 Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration
14722 requirements. If photographs were marked by author and year, there
14723 would be little reason not to allow a photographer to reregister, for
14724 example, all photographs taken in a particular year in one quick
14725 step. The aim of the formality is not to burden the creator; the
14726 system itself should be kept as simple as possible.
14729 The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing
14730 system does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to
14731 make things unclear.
14734 If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most
14735 difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed.
14736 It would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it
14737 would be simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular
14738 kind of content; it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew
14739 that assertion at the appropriate time.
14742 <!-- PAGE BREAK 297 -->
14745 <section id=
"shortterms">
14746 <title>2. Shorter Terms
</title>
14748 The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five
14749 years for corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for
14753 In
<citetitle>The Future of Ideas
</citetitle>, I proposed a seventy-five-year term,
14754 granted in five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every
14755 five years. That seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost
14756 <citetitle>Eldred
</citetitle> v.
<citetitle>Ashcroft
</citetitle>, the proposals became even more
14757 radical.
<citetitle>The Economist
</citetitle> endorsed a proposal for a fourteen-year
14758 copyright term.
<footnote><para>
14761 <quote>A Radical Rethink,
</quote> <citetitle>Economist
</citetitle>,
366:
8308 (
25 January
2003):
15,
14763 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
74</ulink>.
14765 Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents.
14768 I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in
14769 copyright's term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there
14770 are four principles that are important to keep in mind about copyright
14773 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
14776 <emphasis>Keep it short:
</emphasis> The term should be as long as
14777 necessary to give incentives to create, but no longer. If it were tied
14778 to very strong protections for authors (so authors were able to
14779 reclaim rights from publishers), rights to the same work (not
14780 derivative works) might be extended further. The key is not to tie the
14781 work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an author.
14785 <emphasis>Keep it simple:
</emphasis> The line between the public
14786 domain and protected content must be kept clear. Lawyers like the
14787 fuzziness of
<quote>fair use,
</quote> and the distinction between
<quote>ideas
</quote> and
14788 <quote>expression.
</quote> That kind of law gives them lots of work. But our
14789 framers had a simpler idea in mind: protected versus unprotected. The
14790 value of short terms is that there is little need to build exceptions
14791 into copyright when the term itself is kept short. A clear and active
14792 <quote>lawyer-free zone
</quote> makes the complexities of
<quote>fair use
</quote> and
14793 <quote>idea/expression
</quote> less necessary to navigate.
14794 <!-- PAGE BREAK 298 -->
14797 <indexterm><primary>veterans' pensions
</primary></indexterm>
14800 <emphasis>Keep it alive:
</emphasis> Copyright should have to be
14801 renewed. Especially if the maximum term is long, the copyright owner
14802 should be required to signal periodically that he wants the protection
14803 continued. This need not be an onerous burden, but there is no reason
14804 this monopoly protection has to be granted for free. On average, it
14805 takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply for a
14806 pension.
<footnote><para>
14808 Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation
14809 and/or Pension, VA Form
21-
526 (OMB Approved No.
2900-
0001),
14811 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
75</ulink>.
14813 If we make veterans suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't
14814 require authors to spend ten minutes every fifty years to file a
14819 <emphasis>Keep it prospective:
</emphasis> Whatever the term of
14820 copyright should be, the clearest lesson that economists teach is that
14821 a term once given should not be extended. It might have been a mistake
14822 in
1923 for the law to offer authors only a fifty-six-year term. I
14823 don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a mistake, then the
14824 consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in
1923 than we
14825 otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today by
14826 increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase
14827 the number of authors who wrote in
1923. Of course, we can increase
14828 the reward that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase
14829 the copyright burden that smothers many works that are today
14830 invisible). But increasing their reward will not increase their
14831 creativity in
1923. What's not done is not done, and there's nothing
14832 we can do about that now.
</para></listitem>
14835 These changes together should produce an
<emphasis>average
</emphasis>
14836 copyright term that is much shorter than the current term. Until
1976,
14837 the average term was just
32.2 years. We should be aiming for the
14841 No doubt the extremists will call these ideas
<quote>radical.
</quote> (After all, I
14842 call them
<quote>extremists.
</quote>) But again, the term I recommended was longer
14843 than the term under Richard Nixon. How
<quote>radical
</quote> can it be to ask for
14844 a more generous copyright law than Richard Nixon presided over?
14847 <!-- PAGE BREAK 299 -->
14850 <section id=
"freefairuse">
14851 <title>3. Free Use Vs. Fair Use
</title>
14852 <indexterm><primary>land ownership, air traffic and
</primary></indexterm>
14853 <indexterm><primary>property rights
</primary><secondary>air traffic vs.
</secondary></indexterm>
14855 As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally
14856 granted property owners the right to control their property from the
14857 ground to the heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property
14858 rights quickly changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional
14859 challenge. It made no sense anymore to grant that much control, given
14860 the emergence of that new technology.
14863 Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors
<quote>exclusive
14864 right
</quote> to
<quote>their writings.
</quote> Congress has given authors an exclusive
14865 right to
<quote>their writings
</quote> plus any derivative writings (made by
14866 others) that are sufficiently close to the author's original
14867 work. Thus, if I write a book, and you base a movie on that book, I
14868 have the power to deny you the right to release that movie, even
14869 though that movie is not
<quote>my writing.
</quote>
14871 <indexterm><primary>Kaplan, Benjamin
</primary></indexterm>
14873 Congress granted the beginnings of this right in
1870, when it
14874 expanded the exclusive right of copyright to include a right to
14875 control translations and dramatizations of a work.
<footnote><para>
14877 Benjamin Kaplan,
<citetitle>An Unhurried View of Copyright
</citetitle> (New York: Columbia
14878 University Press,
1967),
32.
14880 The courts have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation
14881 ever since. This expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's
14882 greatest judges, Judge Benjamin Kaplan.
14886 So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a
14887 large range of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense
14888 the oddity of accepting such an enlargement of copyright while
14889 yet intoning the abracadabra of idea and expression.
<footnote><para>
14890 <!-- f6. --> Ibid.,
56.
14895 I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and
14896 the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make
14897 sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that
14898 a copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant.
14899 Consider each limitation in turn.
14902 <emphasis>Term:
</emphasis> If Congress wants to grant a derivative
14903 right, then that right should be for a much shorter term. It makes
14904 sense to protect John
14906 <!-- PAGE BREAK 300 -->
14907 Grisham's right to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least
14908 I'm willing to assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right
14909 to run for the same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative
14910 right could be important in inducing creativity; it is not important long
14911 after the creative work is done.
14912 <indexterm><primary>Grisham, John
</primary></indexterm>
14915 <emphasis>Scope:
</emphasis> Likewise should the scope of derivative
14916 rights be narrowed. Again, there are some cases in which derivative
14917 rights are important. Those should be specified. But the law should
14918 draw clear lines around regulated and unregulated uses of copyrighted
14919 material. When all
<quote>reuse
</quote> of creative material was within the control
14920 of businesses, perhaps it made sense to require lawyers to negotiate
14921 the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers to negotiate the
14922 lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that digital
14923 technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the
14924 machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to
14925 the creative process. Smothers it.
14927 <indexterm><primary>Alben, Alex
</primary></indexterm>
14929 This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the
14930 Clint Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for
14931 foreseeable derivative rights
—turning a book into a movie, or a
14932 poem into a musical score
—it doesn't make sense to require
14933 negotiation for the unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make
14937 In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are
14938 protected, and the presumption should be that other uses are not
14939 protected. This is the reverse of the recommendation of my colleague
14940 Paul Goldstein.
<footnote>
14943 Paul Goldstein,
<citetitle>Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial
14944 Jukebox
</citetitle> (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
2003),
187–216.
14945 <indexterm><primary>Goldstein, Paul
</primary></indexterm>
14947 His view is that the law should be written so that
14948 expanded protections follow expanded uses.
14951 Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal
14952 system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of
14953 the Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the
14954 incentives to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with
14955 a strong copyright, weaken the process of innovation.
14958 The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection
14959 <!-- PAGE BREAK 301 -->
14960 beyond the part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon
14961 certain statutory conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free
14962 a great deal of culture to others to cultivate. And under a statutory
14963 rights regime, that reuse would earn artists more income.
14967 <section id=
"liberatemusic">
14968 <title>4. Liberate the Music
—Again
</title>
14970 The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it
14971 wouldn't be fair to end this book without addressing the issue that
14972 is, to most people, most pressing
—music. There is no other
14973 policy issue that better teaches the lessons of this book than the
14974 battles around the sharing of music.
14977 The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the
14978 Internet's growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more
14979 powerfully than any other single application. It was the Internet's
14980 killer app
—possibly in two senses of that word. It no doubt was
14981 the application that drove demand for bandwidth. It may well be the
14982 application that drives demand for regulations that in the end kill
14983 innovation on the network.
14986 The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in
14987 particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed,
14988 performed, and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving
14989 an exclusive right to a composer to control public performances of his
14990 work, and to a performing artist to control copies of her performance.
14993 File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of
14994 content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course,
14995 that's not all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter
14996 <xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber" linkend=
"piracy"/>, they enable
14997 four different kinds of sharing:
14999 <orderedlist numeration=
"upperalpha">
15002 There are some who are using sharing networks as substitutes
15003 for purchasing CDs.
15007 There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample,
15008 on the way to purchasing CDs.
15011 <!-- PAGE BREAK 302 -->
15013 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15014 content that is no longer sold but is still under copyright or that
15015 would have been too cumbersome to buy off the Net.
15019 There are many who are using file-sharing networks to get access to
15020 content that is not copyrighted or to get access that the copyright
15021 owner plainly endorses.
15024 <indexterm><primary>cassette recording
</primary><secondary>VCRs
</secondary></indexterm>
15025 <indexterm><primary>VCRs
</primary></indexterm>
15027 Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It
15028 must avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The
15029 eagerness with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover,
15030 should depend upon the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net
15031 effect of sharing is actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is
15032 significantly weakened.
15035 As I said in chapter
<xref xrefstyle=
"select: labelnumber"
15036 linkend=
"piracy"/>, the actual harm caused by sharing is
15037 controversial. For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume
15038 the harm is real. I assume, in other words, that type A sharing is
15039 significantly greater than type B, and is the dominant use of sharing
15043 Nonetheless, there is a crucial fact about the current technological
15044 context that we must keep in mind if we are to understand how the law
15048 Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is
15049 addictive today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a
15050 broad range of content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to
15051 a broad range of content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet
15052 is cumbersome and slow
—we in the United States are lucky to have
15053 broadband service at
1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at
15054 that speed both up and down. Although wireless access is growing, most
15055 of us still get access across wires. Most only gain access through a
15056 machine with a keyboard. The idea of the always on, always connected
15057 Internet is mainly just an idea.
15060 But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to
15061 the Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should
15062 not make policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should
15063 <!-- PAGE BREAK 303 -->
15064 make policy on the basis of where the technology is going. The
15065 question should not be, how should the law regulate sharing in this
15066 world? The question should be, what law will we require when the
15067 network becomes the network it is clearly becoming? That network is
15068 one in which every machine with electricity is essentially on the Net;
15069 where everywhere you are
—except maybe the desert or the
15070 Rockies
—you can instantaneously be connected to the
15071 Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone
15072 service, where with the flip of a device, you are connected.
15074 <indexterm><primary>cell phones, music streamed over
</primary></indexterm>
15076 In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that
15077 give you access to content on the fly
—such as Internet radio,
15078 content that is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here,
15079 then, is the critical point: When it is
<emphasis>extremely
</emphasis>
15080 easy to connect to services that give access to content, it will be
15081 <emphasis>easier
</emphasis> to connect to services that give you
15082 access to content than it will be to download and store content
15083 <emphasis>on the many devices you will have for playing
15084 content
</emphasis>. It will be easier, in other words, to subscribe
15085 than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the
15086 download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially
15087 is. Content services will compete with content sharing, even if the
15088 services charge money for the content they give access to. Already
15089 cell-phone services in Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over
15090 cell phones (enhanced with plugs for headphones). The Japanese are
15091 paying for this content even though
<quote>free
</quote> content is available in the
15092 form of MP3s across the Web.
<footnote><para>
15094 See, for example,
<quote>Music Media Watch,
</quote> The J@pan Inc. Newsletter,
3
15095 April
2002, available at
15096 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
76</ulink>.
15101 This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the
15102 present: It is emphatically temporary. The
<quote>problem
</quote> with file
15103 sharing
—to the extent there is a real problem
—is a problem
15104 that will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to
15105 the Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy
15106 makers today to be
<quote>solving
</quote> this problem in light of a technology
15107 that will be gone tomorrow. The question should not be how to
15108 regulate the Internet to eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve
15109 that problem away). The question instead should be how to assure that
15110 artists get paid, during
15112 <!-- PAGE BREAK 304 -->
15113 this transition between twentieth-century models for doing business
15114 and twenty-first-century technologies.
15117 The answer begins with recognizing that there are different
<quote>problems
</quote>
15118 here to solve. Let's start with type D content
—uncopyrighted
15119 content or copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The
15120 <quote>problem
</quote> with this content is to make sure that the technology that
15121 would enable this kind of sharing is not rendered illegal. You can
15122 think of it this way: Pay phones are used to deliver ransom demands,
15123 no doubt. But there are many who need to use pay phones who have
15124 nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to ban pay phones in
15125 order to eliminate kidnapping.
15128 Type C content raises a different
<quote>problem.
</quote> This is content that was,
15129 at one time, published and is no longer available. It may be
15130 unavailable because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the
15131 record label he signed with to carry his work. Or it may be
15132 unavailable because the work is forgotten. Either way, the aim of the
15133 law should be to facilitate the access to this content, ideally in a
15134 way that returns something to the artist.
15136 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>out of print
</secondary></indexterm>
15137 <indexterm><primary>books
</primary><secondary>resales of
</secondary></indexterm>
15139 Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of
15140 print, it may still be available in libraries and used book
15141 stores. But libraries and used book stores don't pay the copyright
15142 owner when someone reads or buys an out-of-print book. That makes
15143 total sense, of course, since any other system would be so burdensome
15144 as to eliminate the possibility of used book stores' existing. But
15145 from the author's perspective, this
<quote>sharing
</quote> of his content without
15146 his being compensated is less than ideal.
15149 The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem
15150 out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of
15151 the music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial
15152 providers would be free, under this rule, to
<quote>share
</quote> that content,
15153 even though the sharing involved making a copy. The copy here would be
15154 incidental to the trade; in a context where commercial publishing has
15155 ended, trading music should be as free as trading books.
15159 <!-- PAGE BREAK 305 -->
15160 Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would
15161 ensure that artists get something from the trade of their work. For
15162 example, if the law set a low statutory rate for the commercial
15163 sharing of content that was not offered for sale by a commercial
15164 publisher, and if that rate were automatically transferred to a trust
15165 for the benefit of the artist, then businesses could develop around
15166 the idea of trading this content, and artists would benefit from this
15170 This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep
15171 works available commercially. Works that are available commercially
15172 would not be subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect
15173 the right to charge whatever they want for content if they kept the
15174 work commercially available. But if they don't keep it available, and
15175 instead, the computer hard disks of fans around the world keep it
15176 alive, then any royalty owed for such copying should be much less than
15177 the amount owed a commercial publisher.
15180 The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is
15181 hard only because the extent of the problem will change over time, as
15182 the technologies for gaining access to content change. The law's
15183 solution should be as flexible as the problem is, understanding that
15184 we are in the middle of a radical transformation in the technology for
15185 delivering and accessing content.
15188 So here's a solution that will at first seem very strange to both sides
15189 in this war, but which upon reflection, I suggest, should make some sense.
15192 Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic
15193 claim of the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet)
15194 has harmed a set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to
15195 be protected, then the content industry should be compensated for that
15196 harm. Just as the technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions
15197 of Americans, or the technology of asbestos caused grave illness to
15198 thousands of miners, so, too, has the technology of digital networks
15199 harmed the interests of the content industry.
15202 <!-- PAGE BREAK 306 -->
15203 I love the Internet, and so I don't like likening it to tobacco or
15204 asbestos. But the analogy is a fair one from the perspective of the
15205 law. And it suggests a fair response: Rather than seeking to destroy
15206 the Internet, or the p2p technologies that are currently harming
15207 content providers on the Internet, we should find a relatively simple
15208 way to compensate those who are harmed.
15210 <indexterm id='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='startofrange'
><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)
</primary></indexterm>
15212 The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been
15213 floated by Harvard law professor William Fisher.
<footnote>
15216 <indexterm id='idxartistspayments3' class='startofrange'
><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
15217 William Fisher,
<citetitle>Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities
</citetitle> (last
15218 revised:
10 October
2000), available at
15219 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
77</ulink>; William
15220 Fisher,
<citetitle>Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the Future of
15221 Entertainment
</citetitle> (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
15222 2004), ch.
6, available at
15223 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
78</ulink>. Professor
15224 Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt noncommercial
15225 sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish compensation
15226 to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel,
<quote>Impose a
15227 Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing,
</quote> available at
15228 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
79</ulink>. For other proposals, see Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>Who's Holding Back
15229 Broadband?
</quote> <citetitle>Washington Post
</citetitle>,
8 January
2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on
15230 behalf of Sharman Networks, A Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr.,
15231 Chairman of the Senate Foreign Relations Committee,
26 February
2002,
15233 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
80</ulink>; Serguei Osokine,
<citetitle>A Quick Case for Intellectual Property
15234 Use Fee (IPUF)
</citetitle>,
3 March
2002, available at
15235 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
81</ulink>; Jefferson Graham,
15236 <quote>Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly,
</quote> <citetitle>USA Today
</citetitle>,
13 May
15238 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
82</ulink>; Steven M. Cherry,
<quote>Getting Copyright Right,
</quote>
15239 IEEE Spectrum Online,
1 July
2002, available at
15240 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
83</ulink>; Declan
15241 McCullagh,
<quote>Verizon's Copyright Campaign,
</quote> CNET News.com,
27 August
15243 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
84</ulink>.
15244 Fisher's proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for
15245 DAT. Unlike Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly
15246 proportionally, though more popular artists would get more than the less
15247 popular. As is typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current
15248 debate by about a decade. See
15249 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
85</ulink>.
15250 <indexterm><primary>Fisher, William
</primary></indexterm>
15251 <indexterm><primary>Netanel, Neil Weinstock
</primary></indexterm>
15252 <indexterm><primary>Promises to Keep (Fisher)
</primary></indexterm>
15253 <indexterm startref='idxartistspayments3' class='endofrange'
/>
15255 Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the
15256 Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission
15257 would (
1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how
15258 easy it is to evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive
15259 to evade them). Once the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would
15260 develop (
2) systems to monitor how many items of each content were
15261 distributed. On the basis of those numbers, then (
3) artists would be
15262 compensated. The compensation would be paid for by (
4) an appropriate
15266 Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million
15267 questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book,
15268 <citetitle>Promises to Keep
</citetitle>. The modification that I would make is relatively
15269 simple: Fisher imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright
15270 system. I imagine it complementing the existing system. The aim of
15271 the proposal would be to facilitate compensation to the extent that
15272 harm could be shown. This compensation would be temporary, aimed at
15273 facilitating a transition between regimes. And it would require
15274 renewal after a period of years. If it continues to make sense to
15275 facilitate free exchange of content, supported through a taxation
15276 system, then it can be continued. If this form of protection is no
15277 longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old system of
15278 controlling access.
15280 <indexterm startref='idxpromisestokeepfisher' class='endofrange'
/>
15281 <indexterm><primary>artists
</primary><secondary>recording industry payments to
</secondary></indexterm>
15283 Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim
15284 is not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that
15285 the system supports the widest range of
<quote>semiotic democracy
</quote>
15286 possible. But the aims of semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the
15287 other changes I described were accomplished
—in particular, the
15288 limits on derivative
15290 <!-- PAGE BREAK 307 -->
15291 uses. A system that simply charges for access would not greatly burden
15292 semiotic democracy if there were few limitations on what one was
15293 allowed to do with the content itself.
15295 <indexterm><primary>Apple Corporation
</primary></indexterm>
15296 <indexterm><primary>MusicStore
</primary></indexterm>
15297 <indexterm><primary>Real Networks
</primary></indexterm>
15298 <indexterm><primary>CDs
</primary><secondary>prices of
</secondary></indexterm>
15300 No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of
15301 <quote>harm
</quote> to an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation
15302 would be outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This
15303 background system to compensate would also not need to interfere with
15304 innovative proposals such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted
15305 when Apple launched the MusicStore, it could beat
<quote>free
</quote> by being
15306 easier than free is. This has proven correct: Apple has sold millions
15307 of songs at even the very high price of
99 cents a song. (At
99 cents,
15308 the cost is the equivalent of a per-song CD price, though the labels
15309 have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's move was countered by
15310 Real Networks, offering music at just
79 cents a song. And no doubt
15311 there will be a great deal of competition to offer and sell music
15314 <indexterm><primary>cable television
</primary></indexterm>
15315 <indexterm><primary>television
</primary><secondary>cable vs. broadcast
</secondary></indexterm>
15316 <indexterm><primary>Asia, commercial piracy in
</primary></indexterm>
15317 <indexterm><primary>piracy
</primary><secondary>in Asia
</secondary></indexterm>
15318 <indexterm><primary>film industry
</primary><secondary>luxury theatres vs. video piracy in
</secondary></indexterm>
15320 This competition has already occurred against the background of
<quote>free
</quote>
15321 music from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known
15322 for thirty years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than
15323 that, there is nothing impossible at all about
<quote>competing with free.
</quote>
15324 Indeed, if anything, the competition spurs the competitors to offer
15325 new and better products. This is precisely what the competitive market
15326 was to be about. Thus in Singapore, though piracy is rampant, movie
15327 theaters are often luxurious
—with
<quote>first class
</quote> seats, and meals
15328 served while you watch a movie
—as they struggle and succeed in
15329 finding ways to compete with
<quote>free.
</quote>
15332 This regime of competition, with a backstop to assure that artists
15333 don't lose, would facilitate a great deal of innovation in the
15334 delivery of content. That competition would continue to shrink type A
15335 sharing. It would inspire an extraordinary range of new
15336 innovators
—ones who would have a right to the content, and would
15337 no longer fear the uncertain and barbarically severe punishments of
15341 In summary, then, my proposal is this:
15345 <!-- PAGE BREAK 308 -->
15346 The Internet is in transition. We should not be regulating a
15347 technology in transition. We should instead be regulating to minimize
15348 the harm to interests affected by this technological change, while
15349 enabling, and encouraging, the most efficient technology we can
15353 We can minimize that harm while maximizing the benefit to innovation
15356 <orderedlist numeration=
"arabic">
15359 guaranteeing the right to engage in type D sharing;
15363 permitting noncommercial type C sharing without liability,
15364 and commercial type C sharing at a low and fixed rate set by
15369 while in this transition, taxing and compensating for type A
15370 sharing, to the extent actual harm is demonstrated.
15374 But what if
<quote>piracy
</quote> doesn't disappear? What if there is a competitive
15375 market providing content at a low cost, but a significant number of
15376 consumers continue to
<quote>take
</quote> content for nothing? Should the law do
15380 Yes, it should. But, again, what it should do depends upon how the
15381 facts develop. These changes may not eliminate type A sharing. But the
15382 real issue is not whether it eliminates sharing in the abstract. The
15383 real issue is its effect on the market. Is it better (a) to have a
15384 technology that is
95 percent secure and produces a market of size
<citetitle>x
</citetitle>,
15385 or (b) to have a technology that is
50 percent secure but produces a
15386 market of five times
<citetitle>x
</citetitle>? Less secure might produce more unauthorized
15387 sharing, but it is likely to also produce a much bigger market in
15388 authorized sharing. The most important thing is to assure artists'
15389 compensation without breaking the Internet. Once that's assured, then
15390 it may well be appropriate to find ways to track down the petty
15394 But we're a long way away from whittling the problem down to this
15395 subset of type A sharers. And our focus until we're there should not
15396 be on finding ways to break the Internet. Our focus until we're there
15398 <!-- PAGE BREAK 309 -->
15399 should be on how to make sure the artists are paid, while protecting
15400 the space for innovation and creativity that the Internet is.
15404 <section id=
"firelawyers">
15405 <title>5. Fire Lots of Lawyers
</title>
15407 I'm a lawyer. I make lawyers for a living. I believe in the law. I believe
15408 in the law of copyright. Indeed, I have devoted my life to working in
15409 law, not because there are big bucks at the end but because there are
15410 ideals at the end that I would love to live.
15413 Yet much of this book has been a criticism of lawyers, or the role
15414 lawyers have played in this debate. The law speaks to ideals, but it
15415 is my view that our profession has become too attuned to the
15416 client. And in a world where the rich clients have one strong view,
15417 the unwillingness of the profession to question or counter that one
15418 strong view queers the law.
15420 <indexterm><primary>Nimmer, Melville
</primary></indexterm>
15421 <indexterm><primary>Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA) (
1998)
</primary><secondary>Supreme Court challenge of
</secondary></indexterm>
15423 The evidence of this bending is compelling. I'm attacked as a
15424 <quote>radical
</quote> by many within the profession, yet the positions that I am
15425 advocating are precisely the positions of some of the most moderate
15426 and significant figures in the history of this branch of the
15427 law. Many, for example, thought crazy the challenge that we brought to
15428 the Copyright Term Extension Act. Yet just thirty years ago, the
15429 dominant scholar and practitioner in the field of copyright, Melville
15430 Nimmer, thought it obvious.
<footnote><para>
15432 Lawrence Lessig,
<quote>Copyright's First Amendment
</quote> (Melville B. Nimmer
15433 Memorial Lecture),
<citetitle>UCLA Law Review
</citetitle> 48 (
2001):
1057,
1069–70.
15438 However, my criticism of the role that lawyers have played in this
15439 debate is not just about a professional bias. It is more importantly
15440 about our failure to actually reckon the costs of the law.
15443 Economists are supposed to be good at reckoning costs and benefits.
15444 But more often than not, economists, with no clue about how the legal
15445 system actually functions, simply assume that the transaction costs of
15446 the legal system are slight.
<footnote><para>
15448 A good example is the work of Professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz is
15449 to be commended for his careful review of data about infringement,
15450 leading him to question his own publicly stated
15451 position
—twice. He initially predicted that downloading would
15452 substantially harm the industry. He then revised his view in light of
15453 the data, and he has since revised his view again. Compare Stan
15454 J. Liebowitz,
<citetitle>Rethinking the Network Economy: The True Forces That
15455 Drive the Digital Marketplace
</citetitle> (New York: Amacom,
2002), (reviewing his
15456 original view but expressing skepticism) with Stan J. Liebowitz,
15457 <quote>Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?
</quote> working paper, June
2003,
15459 <ulink url=
"http://free-culture.cc/notes/">link #
86</ulink>.
15460 Liebowitz's careful analysis is extremely valuable in estimating the
15461 effect of file-sharing technology. In my view, however, he
15462 underestimates the costs of the legal system. See, for example,
15463 <citetitle>Rethinking
</citetitle>,
174–76.
15464 <indexterm><primary>Liebowitz, Stan
</primary></indexterm>
15466 They see a system that has been around for hundreds of years, and they
15467 assume it works the way their elementary school civics class taught
15471 <!-- PAGE BREAK 310 -->
15472 But the legal system doesn't work. Or more accurately, it doesn't work
15473 for anyone except those with the most resources. Not because the
15474 system is corrupt. I don't think our legal system (at the federal
15475 level, at least) is at all corrupt. I mean simply because the costs of
15476 our legal system are so astonishingly high that justice can
15477 practically never be done.
15480 These costs distort free culture in many ways. A lawyer's time is
15481 billed at the largest firms at more than $
400 per hour. How much time
15482 should such a lawyer spend reading cases carefully, or researching
15483 obscure strands of authority? The answer is the increasing reality:
15484 very little. The law depended upon the careful articulation and
15485 development of doctrine, but the careful articulation and development
15486 of legal doctrine depends upon careful work. Yet that careful work
15487 costs too much, except in the most high-profile and costly cases.
15490 The costliness and clumsiness and randomness of this system mock
15491 our tradition. And lawyers, as well as academics, should consider it
15492 their duty to change the way the law works
—or better, to change the
15493 law so that it works. It is wrong that the system works well only for the
15494 top
1 percent of the clients. It could be made radically more efficient,
15495 and inexpensive, and hence radically more just.
15498 But until that reform is complete, we as a society should keep the law
15499 away from areas that we know it will only harm. And that is precisely
15500 what the law will too often do if too much of our culture is left to
15503 <indexterm><primary>Brezhnev, Leonid
</primary></indexterm>
15505 Think about the amazing things your kid could do or make with digital
15506 technology
—the film, the music, the Web page, the blog. Or think
15507 about the amazing things your community could facilitate with digital
15508 technology
—a wiki, a barn raising, activism to change something.
15509 Think about all those creative things, and then imagine cold molasses
15510 poured onto the machines. This is what any regime that requires
15511 permission produces. Again, this is the reality of Brezhnev's Russia.
15514 The law should regulate in certain areas of culture
—but it should
15515 regulate culture only where that regulation does good. Yet lawyers
15517 <!-- PAGE BREAK 311-->
15518 rarely test their power, or the power they promote, against this
15519 simple pragmatic question:
<quote>Will it do good?
</quote> When challenged about
15520 the expanding reach of the law, the lawyer answers,
<quote>Why not?
</quote>
15523 We should ask,
<quote>Why?
</quote> Show me why your regulation of culture is
15524 needed. Show me how it does good. And until you can show me both,
15525 keep your lawyers away.
15527 <!-- PAGE BREAK 312 -->
15531 <chapter label=
"" id=
"c-notes">
15532 <title>NOTES
</title>
15534 Throughout this text, there are references to links on the World Wide
15535 Web. As anyone who has tried to use the Web knows, these links can be
15536 highly unstable. I have tried to remedy the instability by redirecting
15537 readers to the original source through the Web site associated with
15538 this book. For each link below, you can go to
15539 http://free-culture.cc/notes and locate the original source by
15540 clicking on the number after the # sign. If the original link remains
15541 alive, you will be redirected to that link. If the original link has
15542 disappeared, you will be redirected to an appropriate reference for
15546 <!-- insert endnotes here -->
15547 <?latex \theendnotes
?>
15549 <!--PAGE BREAK 336-->
15552 <chapter label=
"" id=
"c-acknowledgments">
15553 <title>ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
</title>
15555 This book is the product of a long and as yet unsuccessful struggle that
15556 began when I read of Eric Eldred's war to keep books free. Eldred's
15557 work helped launch a movement, the free culture movement, and it is
15558 to him that this book is dedicated.
15560 <indexterm><primary>Rose, Mark
</primary></indexterm>
15562 I received guidance in various places from friends and academics,
15563 including Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner,
15564 Mark Rose, and Kathleen Sullivan. And I received correction and
15565 guidance from many amazing students at Stanford Law School and
15566 Stanford University. They included Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James
15567 P. Fellers, Christopher Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman,
15568 Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, Brian Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng, and
15569 Erica Platt. I am particularly grateful to Catherine Crump and Harry
15570 Surden, who helped direct their research, and to Laura Lynch, who
15571 brilliantly managed the army that they assembled, and provided her own
15572 critical eye on much of this.
15575 Yuko Noguchi helped me to understand the laws of Japan as well as
15576 its culture. I am thankful to her, and to the many in Japan who helped
15577 me prepare this book: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto Misaki,
15578 Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata, and Yoshihiro
15579 <!--PAGE BREAK 337-->
15580 Yonezawa. I am thankful as well as to Professor Nobuhiro Nakayama,
15581 and the Tokyo University Business Law Center, for giving me the
15582 chance to spend time in Japan, and to Tadashi Shiraishi and Kiyokazu
15583 Yamagami for their generous help while I was there.
15586 These are the traditional sorts of help that academics regularly draw
15587 upon. But in addition to them, the Internet has made it possible to
15588 receive advice and correction from many whom I have never even
15589 met. Among those who have responded with extremely helpful advice to
15590 requests on my blog about the book are Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli, David
15591 Gerstein, and Peter DiMauro, as well as a long list of those who had
15592 specific ideas about ways to develop my argument. They included
15593 Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob Devine,
15594 Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger,
15595 Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt,
15596 K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan
15597 McMullen, Fred Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir
15598 Safdar, Saul Schleimer, Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker,
15599 Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt
15600 Wasserman, Miljenko Williams,
<quote>Wink,
</quote> Roger Wood,
<quote>Ximmbo da Jazz,
</quote>
15601 and Richard Yanco. (I apologize if I have missed anyone; with
15602 computers come glitches, and a crash of my e-mail system meant I lost
15603 a bunch of great replies.)
15606 Richard Stallman and Michael Carroll each read the whole book in
15607 draft, and each provided extremely helpful correction and advice.
15608 Michael helped me to see more clearly the significance of the
15609 regulation of derivitive works. And Richard corrected an
15610 embarrassingly large number of errors. While my work is in part
15611 inspired by Stallman's, he does not agree with me in important places
15612 throughout this book.
15615 Finally, and forever, I am thankful to Bettina, who has always
15616 insisted that there would be unending happiness away from these
15617 battles, and who has always been right. This slow learner is, as ever,
15618 grateful for her perpetual patience and love.
15620 <!--PAGE BREAK 338-->
15625 <?latex {\footnotesize
?>
15626 <?latex {\centering
?>
15628 Free culture: How big media uses technology and the law to lock down
15629 culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig.
15632 Copyright
© Lawrence Lessig. Some rights reserved.
15635 This version of
<citetitle>Free Culture
</citetitle> is licensed under
15636 a Creative Commons license. This license permits non-commercial use of
15637 this work, so long as attribution is given. For more information
15638 about the license visit
15639 <ulink url=
"http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/">http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/
1.0/
</ulink>
15642 This digital book was published by Petter Reinholdtsen in
2015. The
15643 original hardcover paper book was published in
2004 by The Penguin
15647 Excerpt from an editorial titled
<quote>The Coming of Copyright
15648 Perpetuity,
</quote> <citetitle>The New York Times
</citetitle>, January
15649 16,
2003. Copyright
© 2003 by The New York Times Co. Reprinted
15654 <xref xrefstyle=
"template:%n" linkend=
"fig-1711-vcr-handgun-cartoonfig"/> by
15655 Paul Conrad, copyright Tribune Media Services, Inc. All rights
15656 reserved. Reprinted with permission.
15660 <xref xrefstyle=
"template:%n" linkend=
"fig-1761-pattern-modern-media-ownership"/>
15661 courtesy of the office of FCC Commissioner, Michael J. Copps.
15669 Classifications: (Dewey)
15676 (US Lib. of Congress) KF2979.L47
2004
15680 <?latex } %\centering
?>
15683 Typeset using the Crimson Text font and dblatex. The dblatex author
15684 provided valuable help in formatting the print version of this book.
15688 The source of this version of the book is written using DocBook
15689 notation and the other formats are derived from the DocBook source.
15690 The DocBook source is based on a DocBook XML version created by Hans
15691 Schou, and extended by Petter Reinholdtsen with formatting and index
15692 references. The source files for this book are available from
15693 <ulink url=
"https://github.com/petterreinholdtsen/free-culture-lessig"/>.
15701 <informaltable id=
"isbn">
15702 <tgroup cols=
"2" align=
"left">
15705 <entry>ISBN
</entry>
15706 <entry>Format / MIME-type
</entry>
15711 <entry>978-
82-
92812-XX-Y
</entry>
15712 <entry>text/plain
</entry>
15715 <entry>978-
82-
92812-XX-Y
</entry>
15716 <entry>application/pdf
</entry>
15719 <entry>978-
82-
92812-XX-Y
</entry>
15720 <entry>text/html
</entry>
15723 <entry>978-
82-
92812-XX-Y
</entry>
15724 <entry>application/epub+zip
</entry>
15727 <entry>978-
82-
92812-XX-Y
</entry>
15728 <entry>application/docbook+xml
</entry>
15731 <entry>978-
82-
92812-XX-Y
</entry>
15732 <entry>application/x-mobipocket-ebook
</entry>
15738 <?latex } %\tiny
?>