From: Petter Reinholdtsen Date: Thu, 26 Jul 2012 22:18:13 +0000 (+0200) Subject: Update to current version. X-Git-Tag: edition-2015-10-10~2101 X-Git-Url: https://pere.pagekite.me/gitweb/text-free-culture-lessig.git/commitdiff_plain/42338009daba7b063906ff46f63397743583da74?hp=7c92cd4dbe3c2eb17c31920eee909c315ed517e6 Update to current version. --- diff --git a/archive/freeculture.nb.epub b/archive/freeculture.nb.epub index 16094bc..cd82c8f 100644 Binary files a/archive/freeculture.nb.epub and b/archive/freeculture.nb.epub differ diff --git a/archive/freeculture.nb.html b/archive/freeculture.nb.html new file mode 100644 index 0000000..b0d346b --- /dev/null +++ b/archive/freeculture.nb.html @@ -0,0 +1,11254 @@ +Fri kultur

Fri kultur

Hvordan store mediaaktører bruker teknologi og loven til å låse ned kulturen +og kontrollere kreativiteten

Lawrence Lessig

Versjon 2004-02-10

+Denne versjonen av Fri Kultur er lisensert med en Creative Commons-lisens. +Denne lisensen tillater ikke-kommersiell utnyttelse av verket, hvis +opphavsinnehaveren er navngitt. For mer informasjon om lisensen, klikk på +ikonet over eller besøk http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/1.0/ +

2004-03-25

Om forfatteren

+Lawrense Lessig (http://www.lessig.org), professor i +juss og en John A. Wilson Distinguished Faculty Scholar ved Stanford Law +School, er stifteren av Stanford Center for Internet and Society og +styreleder i Creative Commons (http://creativecommons.org). +Forfatteren har gitt ut av The Future of Ideas (Random House, 2001) og Code: +And other Laws of Cyberspace (Basic Books, 1999), og er medlem av styrene i +Public Library of Science, the Electronic Frontier Foundation, og Public +Knowledge. Han har vunnet Free Software Foundation's Award for the +Advancement of Free Software, to ganger vært oppført i BusinessWeek's "e.biz +25," og omtalt som en av Scientific American's "50 visjonærer". Etter +utdanning ved University of Pennsylvania, Cambridge University, og Yale Law +School, assisterte Lessig dommer Richard Posner ved U.S. Seventh Circuit +Court of Appeals. +


Dedikasjon

+Til Eric Eldred — hvis arbeid først trakk meg til denne saken, og for +hvem saken fortsetter. +

+

Figur 1. Creative Commons, noen rettigheter reservert

Creative Commons, noen rettigheter reservert


+

tabelloversikt

2.1. Tabell
3.1.
3.2.
3.3.
3.4.

Kolofon

+Du kan kjøpe en kopi av denne boken ved å klikke på en av lenkene nedenfor: +

+Andre bøker av Lawrence Lessig +

+The Future of Ideas: The Fate of the Commons in a Connected World +

+Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace +

+The Penguin Press +

+New York +

+Fri Kultur +

+Hvordan store mediaaktører bruker teknologi og loven til å låse ned kulturen +og kontrollere kreativiteten +

+Lawrence Lessig +

+The Penguin Press +

+a member of Penguin Group (USA) Inc. 375 Hudson Street New York, New York +

+Opphavsrett © Lawrence Lessig, +

+Alle rettigheter reservert +

+Excerpt from an editorial titled "The Coming of Copyright Perpetuity," The +New York Times, January 16, 2003. Copyright © 2003 by The New York +Times Co. Reprinted with permission. +

+Cartoon by Paul Conrad on page 159. Copyright Tribune Media Services, Inc. +

+All rights reserved. Reprinted with permission. +

+Diagram on page 164 courtesy of the office of FCC Commissioner, Michael +J. Copps. +

+Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data +

+Lessig, Lawrence. Free culture : how big media uses technology and the law +to lock down culture and control creativity / Lawrence Lessig. +

+p. cm. +

+Includes index. +

+ISBN 1-59420-006-8 (hardcover) +

+1. Intellectual property—United States. 2. Mass media—United +States. +

+3. Technological innovations—United States. 4. Art—United +States. I. Title. +

+KF2979.L47 +

+343.7309'9—dc22 +

+This book is printed on acid-free paper. +

+Printed in the United States of America +

+1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 +

+Designed by Marysarah Quinn +

+Oversatt til bokmål av Petter Reinholdtsen og Anders Hagen Jarmund. +

+Without limiting the rights under copyright reserved above, no part of this +publication may be reproduced, stored in or introduced into a retrieval +system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means (electronic, mechanical, +photocopying, recording or otherwise), without the prior written permission +of both the copyright owner and the above publisher of this book. The +scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book via the Internet or via +any other means without the permission of the publisher is illegal and +punishable by law. Please purchase only authorized electronic editions and +do not participate in or encourage electronic piracy of copyrighted +materials. Your support of the author's rights is appreciated. +

Forord

+David Pogue, en glimrende skribent og forfatter av utallige tekniske +datarelaterte tekster, skrev dette på slutten av hans gjennomgang av min +første bok, Code: And Other Laws of Cyberspace: +

+I motsetning til faktiske lover, så har ikke internett-programvare +kapasiteten til å straffe. Den påvirker ikke folk som ikke er online (og +kun en veldig liten minoritet av verdens befolkning er online). Og hvis du +ikke liker systemet på internett, så kan du alltid slå av +modemet.[1] +

+Pogue var skeptisk til argumentet som er kjernen av boken — at +programvaren, eller "koden", fungerte som en slags lov — og foreslo i +sin anmeldelse den lykkelig tanken at hvis livet i cyberspace gikk dårlig, +så kan vi alltid som med en trylleformel slå over en bryter og komme hjem +igjen. Slå av modemet, koble fra datamaskinen, og eventuelle problemer som +finnes der ville ikke "påvirke" oss mer. +

+ +Pogue kan ha hatt rett i 1999 — jeg er skeptisk, men det kan +hende. Men selv om han hadde rett da, så er ikke argumentet gyldig nå. Fri +Kultur er om problemene internett forårsaker selv etter at modemet er slått +av. Den er et argument om hvordan slagene som nå brer om seg i livet +on-line har fundamentalt påvirket "folk som er ikke pålogget." Det finnes +ingen bryter som kan isolere oss fra internettets effekt. +

+Men i motsetning til i boken Code, er argumentet her ikke så mye om +internett i seg selv. Istedet er det om konsekvensen av internett for en del +av vår tradisjon som er mye mer grunnleggende, og uansett hvor hardt dette +er for en geek-wanna-be å innrømme, mye viktigere. +

+Den tradisjonen er måten vår kultur blir laget på. Som jeg vil forklare i +sidene som følger, kommer vi fra en tradisjon av "fri kultur"—ikke +"fri" som i "fri bar" (for å låne et uttrykk fra stifteren av fri +programvarebevegelsen[2]), men "fri" som i +"talefrihet", "fritt marked", "frihandel", "fri konkurranse", "fri vilje" og +"frie valg". En fri kultur støtter og beskytter skapere og oppfinnere. +Dette gjør den direkte ved å tildele immaterielle rettigheter. Men det gjør +den indirekte ved å begrense rekkevidden for disse rettighetene, for å +garantere at neste generasjon skapere og oppfinnere er så fri som mulig fra +kontroll fra fortiden. En fri kultur er ikke en kultur uten eierskap, like +lite som et fritt marked er et marked der alt er gratis. Det motsatte av +fri kultur er "tillatelseskultur"—en kultur der skapere kun kan skape +med tillatelse fra de mektige, eller fra skaperne fra fortiden. +

+Hvis vi forsto denne endringen, så tror jeg vi ville stå imot den. Ikke +"vi" på venstresiden eller "dere" på høyresiden, men vi som ikke har +investert i den bestemt kulturindustrien som har definert det tjuende +århundre. Enten du er på venstre eller høyresiden, hvis du i denne forstand +ikke har interesser, vil historien jeg forteller her gi deg problemer. For +endringene jeg beskriver påvirker verdier som begge sider av vår politiske +kultur anser som grunnleggende. +

+Vi så et glimt av dette tverrpolitiske raseri på forsommeren i 2003. Da FCC +vurderte endringer i reglene for medieeierskap som ville slakke på +begrensningene rundt mediakonsentrasjon, sendte en ekstraordinær koalisjon +mer enn 700 000 brev til FCC for å motsette seg endringen. Mens William +Safire beskrev å marsjere "ubehagelig sammen med CodePink Women for Peace +and the National Rifle Association, mellom liberale Olympia Snowe og +konservative Ted Stevens", formulerte han kanskje det enkleste uttrykket +for hva som var på spill: konsentrasjonen av makt. Så spurte han: + +

+Høres dette ikke-konservativt ut? Ikke for meg. Denne konsentrasjonen av +makt—politisk, selskapsmessig, pressemessig, kulturelt—bør være +bannlyst av konservative. Spredningen av makt gjennom lokal kontroll, og +derigjennom oppmuntre til individuell deltagelse, er essensen i føderalismen +og det største uttrykk for demokrati.[3] +

+Denne idéen er et element i argumentet til Fri Kultur, selv om min fokus +ikke bare er på konsentrasjonen av makt som følger av konsentrasjonen i +eierskap, men mer viktig, og fordi det er mindre synlig, på konsentrasjonen +av makt som er resultat av en radikal endring i det effektive virkeområdet +til loven. Loven er i endring, og endringen forandrer på hvordan vår kultur +blir skapt. Den endringen bør bekymre deg—Uansett om du bryr deg om +internett eller ikke, og uansett om du er til venstre for Safires eller til +høyre. Inspirasjonen til tittelen og mye av argumentet i denne boken kommer +fra arbeidet til Richard Stallman og Free Software Foundation. Faktisk, da +jeg leste Stallmans egne tekster på nytt, spesielt essyene i Free Software, +Free Society, innser jeg at alle de teoretiske innsiktene jeg utvikler her +er innsikter som Stallman beskrev for tiår siden. Man kan dermed godt +argumentere for at dette verket kun er et avledet verk. +

+ +Jeg godtar kritikken, hvis det faktisk er kritikk. Arbeidet til en advokat +er alltid avledede verker, og jeg mener ikke å gjøre noe mer i denne boken +enn å minne en kultur om en tradisjon som alltid har vært deres egen. Som +Stallman forsvarer jeg denne tradisjonen på grunnlag av verdier. Som +Stallman tror jeg dette er verdiene til frihet. Og som Stallman, tror jeg +dette er verdier fra vår fortid som må forsvares i vår fremtid. En fri +kultur har vært vår fortid, men vil bare være vår fremtid hvis vi endrer +retningen vi følger akkurat nå. På samme måte som Stallmans argumenter for +fri programvare, treffer argumenter for en fri kultur på forvirring som er +vanskelig å unngå, og enda vanskeligere å forstå. En fri kultur er ikke en +kultur uten eierskap. Det er ikke en kultur der kunstnere ikke får +betalt. En kultur uten eierskap eller en der skaperne ikke kan få betalt, er +anarki, ikke frihet. Anarki er ikke hva jeg fremmer her. +

+I stedet er den frie kulturen som jeg forsvarer i denne boken en balanse +mellom anarki og kontroll. En fri kultur, i likhet med et fritt marked, er +fylt med eierskap. Den er fylt med regler for eierskap og kontrakter som +blir håndhevet av staten. Men på samme måte som det frie markedet blir +pervertert hvis dets eierskap blir føydalt, så kan en fri kultur bli ødelagt +av ekstremisme i eierskapsrettighetene som definerer den. Det er dette jeg +frykter om vår kultur i dag. Det er som motpol til denne ekstremismen at +denne boken er skrevet. +



[1] +David Pogue, "Don't Just Chat, Do Something," New York Times, 30. januar +2000 +

[2] +Richard M. Stallman, Fri programvare, Frie samfunn 57 (Joshua Gay, +red. 2002). +

[3] William Safire, "The Great Media Gulp," New York Times, 22. mai 2003. + +

Kapittel 1. Introduksjon

+17. desember 1903, på en vindfylt strand i Nord-Carolina i såvidt under +hundre sekunder, demonstrerte Wright-brødrene at et selvdrevet fartøy tyngre +enn luft kunne fly. Øyeblikket var elektrisk, og dens betydning ble alment +forstått. Nesten umiddelbart, eksploderte interessen for denne nye +teknologien som muliggjorde bemannet luftfart og en hærskare av oppfinnere +begynte å bygge videre på den. +

+Da Wright-brødrene fant opp flymaskinen, hevdet loven i USA at en grunneier +ble antatt å eie ikke bare overflaten på området sitt, men også alt landet +under bakken, helt ned til senterpunktet i jorda, og alt volumet over +bakken, "i ubestemt grad, oppover".[4] I +mange år undret lærde over hvordan en best skulle tolke idéen om at +eiendomsretten gikk helt til himmelen. Betød dette at du eide stjernene? +Kunne en dømme gjess for at de regelmessig og med vilje tok seg inn på annen +manns eiendom? +

+Så kom flymaskiner, og for første gang hadde dette prinsippet i lovverket i +USA—dypt nede i grunnlaget for vår tradisjon og akseptert av de +viktigste juridiske tenkerne i vår fortid—en betydning. Hvis min +eiendom rekker til himmelen, hva skjer når United flyr over mitt område? +Har jeg rett til å nekte dem å bruke min eiendom? Har jeg mulighet til å +inngå en eksklusiv avtale med Delta Airlines? Kan vi gjennomføre en auksjon +for å finne ut hvor mye disse rettighetene er verdt? +

+I 1945 ble disse spørsmålene en føderal sak. Da bøndene Thomas Lee og Tinie +Causby i Nord Carolina begynte å miste kyllinger på grunn av lavtflygende +militære fly (vettskremte kyllinger fløy tilsynelatende i låveveggene og +døde), saksøkte Causbyene regjeringen for å trenge seg inn på deres +eiendom. Flyene rørte selvfølgelig aldri overflaten på Causbys' eiendom. Men +hvis det stemte som Blackstone, Kent, og Cola hadde sagt, at deres eiendom +strakk seg "i ubestemt grad, oppover," så hadde regjeringen trengt seg inn +på deres eiendom, og Causbys ønsket å sette en stopper for dette. +

+Høyesterett gikk med på å ta opp Causbys sak. Kongressen hadde vedtatt at +luftfartsveiene var tilgjengelig for alle, men hvis ens eiendom virkelig +rakk til himmelen, da kunne muligens kongressens vedtak ha vært i strid med +grunnlovens forbud mot å "ta" eiendom uten kompensasjon. Retten erkjente at +"det er gammel doktrine etter sedvane at en eiendom rakk til utkanten av +universet.", men dommer Douglas hadde ikke tålmodighet for forhistoriske +doktriner. I et enkelt avsnitt, ble hundrevis av år med +eiendomslovgivningen strøket. Som han skrev på vegne av retten, +

+[Denne] doktrinen har ingen plass i den moderne verden. Luften er en +offentlig motorvei, slik kongressen har erklært. Hvis det ikke var +tilfelle, ville hver eneste transkontinentale flyrute utsette operatørene +for utallige søksmål om inntrenging på annen manns eiendom. Idéen er i +strid med sunn fornuft. Å anerkjenne slike private krav til luftrommet +ville blokkere disse motorveiene, seriøst forstyrre muligheten til kontroll +og utvikling av dem i fellesskapets interesse og overføre til privat +eierskap det som kun fellesskapet har et rimelig krav til.[5] +

+"Idéen er i strid med sunn fornuft." +

+ +Det er hvordan loven vanligvis fungerer. Ikke ofte like brått eller +utålmodig, men til slutt er dette hvordan loven fungerer. Det var ikke +stilen til Douglas å utbrodere. Andre dommere ville ha skrevet mange flere +sider før de nådde sin konklusjon, men for Douglas holdt det med en enkel +linje: "Idéen er i strid med sunn fornuft.". Men uansett om det tar flere +sider eller kun noen få ord, så er det en genial egenskap med et +lovpraksis-system, slik som vårt er, at loven tilpasser seg til aktuelle +teknologiene. Og mens den tilpasser seg, så endres den. Idéer som var +solide som fjell i en tidsalder knuses i en annen. +

+Eller, det er hvordan ting skjer når det ikke er noen mektige på andre siden +av endringen. Causbyene var bare bønder. Og selv om det uten tvil var +mange som dem som var lei av den økende trafikken i luften (og en håper ikke +for mange kyllinger flakset seg inn i vegger), ville Causbyene i verden +finne det svært hardt å samles for å stoppe idéen, og teknologien, som +Wright-brødrene hadde ført til verden. Wright-brødrene spyttet flymaskiner +inn i den teknologiske meme-dammen. Idéen spredte seg deretter som et virus +i en kyllingfarm. Causbyene i verden fant seg selv omringet av "det synes +rimelig" gitt teknologien som Wright-brødrene hadde produsert. De kunne stå +på sine gårder, med døde kyllinger i hendene, og heve knyttneven mot disse +nye teknologiene så mye de ville. De kunne ringe sine representanter eller +til og med saksøke. Men når alt kom til alt, ville kraften i det som virket +"åpenbart" for alle andre—makten til "sunn fornuft"—ville vinne +frem. Deres "personlige interesser" ville ikke få lov til å nedkjempe en +åpenbar fordel for fellesskapet. +

+Edwin Howard Armstrong er en av USAs glemte oppfinnergenier. Han dukket opp +på oppfinnerscenen etter titaner som Thomas Edison og Alexander Graham +Bell. Alle hans bidrag på området radioteknologi gjør han til kanskje den +viktigste av alle enkeltoppfinnere i de første femti årene av radio. Han +var bedre utdannet enn Michael Faraday, som var bokbinderlærling da han +oppdaget elektrisk induksjon i 1831. Men han hadde like god intuisjon om +hvordan radioverden virket, og ved minst tre anledninger, fant Armstrong opp +svært viktig teknologier som brakte vår forståelse av radio et hopp videre. + +

+Dagen etter julaften i 1933, ble fire patenter utstedt til Armstrong for +hans mest signifikante oppfinnelse—FM-radio. Inntil da hadde +forbrukerradioer vært amplitude-modulert (AM) radio. Tidens teoretikere +hadde sagt at frekvens-modulert (FM) radio. De hadde rett når det gjelder +et smalt bånd av spektrumet. Men Armstrong oppdaget at frekvens-modulert +radio i et vidt bånd i spektrumet leverte en forbløffende gjengivelse av +lyd, med mye mindre senderstyrke og støy. +

+Den 5. november 1935 demonstrerte han teknologien på et møte hos institutt +for radioingeniører ved Empire State-bygningen i New York City. Han vred +radiosøkeren over en rekke AM-stasjoner, inntil radioen låste seg mot en +kringkasting som han hadde satt opp 27 kilometer unna. Radioen ble helt +stille, som om den var død, og så, med en klarhet ingen andre i rommet noen +gang hadde hørt fra et elektrisk apparat, produserte det lyden av en +opplesers stemme: "Dette er amatørstasjon W2AG ved Yonkers, New York, som +opererer på frekvensmodulering ved to og en halv meter." +

+Publikum hørte noe ingen hadde trodd var mulig: +

+Et glass vann ble fylt opp foran mikrofonen i Yonkers, og det hørtes ut som +et plass som ble fylt opp. . . . Et papir ble krøllet og revet opp, og det +hørtes ut som papir og ikke som en sprakende skogbrann. . . . Sousa-marsjer +ble spilt av fra plater og en pianosolo og et gitarnummer ble +utført. . . . Musikken ble presentert med en livaktighet som sjeldent om +noen gang før hadde vært hørt fra en radio-"musikk-boks".[6] +

+ +Som vår egen sunn fornuft forteller oss, hadde Armstrong oppdaget en mye +bedre radioteknologi. Men på tidspunktet for hans oppfinnelse, jobbet +Armstrong for RCA. RCA var den dominerende aktøren i det da dominerende +AM-radiomarkedet. I 1935 var det tusen radiostasjoner over hele USA, men +stasjonene i de store byene var alle eid av en liten håndfull selskaper. + +

+Presidenten i RCA, David Sarnoff, en venn av Armstrong, var ivrig etter å få +Armstrong til å oppdage en måte å fjerne støyen fra AM-radio. Så Sarnoff var +ganske spent da Armstrong fortalte ham at han hadde en enhet som fjernet +støy fra "radio.". Men da Armstrong demonstrerte sin oppfinnelse, var ikke +Sarnoff fornøyd. +

+Jeg trodde Armstrong ville finne opp et slags filter for å fjerne skurring +fra AM-radioen vår. Jeg trodde ikke han skulle starte en revolusjon — +starte en hel forbannet ny industri i konkurranse med RCA.[7] +

+Armstrongs oppfinnelse truet RCAs AM-herredømme, så selskapet lanserte en +kampanje for å knuse FM-radio. Mens FM kan ha vært en overlegen teknologi, +var Sarnoff en overlegen taktiker. En forfatter beskrev det slik, + +

+Kreftene til fordel for FM, i hovedsak ingeniørfaglige, kunne ikke overvinne +tyngden til strategien utviklet av avdelingene for salg, patenter og juss +for å undertrykke denne trusselen til selskapets posisjon. For FM utgjorde, +hvis det fikk utvikle seg uten begrensninger . . . en komplett endring i +maktforholdene rundt radio . . . og muligens fjerningen av det nøye +begrensede AM-systemet som var grunnlaget for RCA stigning til +makt.[8] +

+RCA holdt først teknologien innomhus, og insistere på at det var nødvendig +med ytterligere tester. Da Armstrong, etter to år med testing, ble +utålmodig, begynte RCA å bruke sin makt hos myndighetene til holde tilbake +den generelle spredningen av FM-radio. I 1936, ansatte RCA den tidligere +lederen av FCC og ga ham oppgaven med å sikre at FCC tilordnet +radiospekteret på en måte som ville kastrere FM—hovedsakelig ved å +flytte FM-radio til et annet band i spekteret. I første omgang lyktes ikke +disse forsøkene. Men mens Armstrong og nasjonen var distrahert av andre +verdenskrig, begynte RCAs arbeid å bære frukter. Like etter at krigen var +over, annonserte FCC et sett med avgjørelser som ville ha en klar effekt: +FM-radio ville bli forkrøplet.Lawrence lessing beskrevet det slik, +

+Serien med slag mot kroppen som FM-radio mottok rett etter krigen, i en +serie med avgjørelser manipulert gjennom FCC av de store radiointeressene, +var nesten utrolige i deres kraft og underfundighet.[9] +

+For å gjøre plass i spektrumet for RCAs nyeste satsingsområde, televisjon, +skulle FM-radioens brukere flyttes til et helt nytt band i spektrumet. +Sendestyrken til FM-radioene ble også redusert, og gjorde at FM ikke lenger +kunne brukes for å sende programmer fra en del av landet til en annen. +(Denne endringen ble sterkt støttet av AT&T, på grunn av at fjerningen +av FM-videresendingsstasjoner ville bety at radiostasjonene ville bli nødt +til å kjøpe kablede linker fra AT&T.) Spredningen av FM-radio var +dermed kvalt, i hvert fall midlertidig. +

+Armstrong sto imot RCAs innsats. Som svar motsto RCA Armstrongs patenter. +Etter å ha bakt FM-teknologi inn i den nye standarden for TV, erklærte RCS +patentene ugyldige—uten grunn og nesten femten år etter at de ble +utstedet. De nektet dermed å betale ham for bruken av patentene. I seks år +kjempet Armstrong en dyr søksmålskrig for å forsvare patentene sine. Til +slutt, samtidig som patentene utløp, tilbød RCA et forlik så lavt at det +ikke engang dekket Armstrongs advokatregning. Beseiret, knust og nå blakk, +skrev Armstrong i 1954 en kort beskjed til sin kone, før han gikk ut av et +vindu i trettende etasje og falt i døden. +

+ +Dette er slik loven virker noen ganger. Ikke ofte like tragisk, og sjelden +med heltemodig drama, men noen ganger er det slik det virker. Fra starten +har myndigheter og myndighetsorganer blitt tatt til fange. Det er mer +sannsynlig at de blir fanget når en mektig interesse er truet av enten en +juridisk eller teknologisk endring. Denne mektige interessen utøver for +ofte sin innflytelse hos myndighetene til å få myndighetene til å beskytte +den. Retorikken for denne beskyttelsen er naturligvis alltid med fokus på +fellesskapets beste. Realiteten er noe annet. Idéer som kan være solide +som fjell i en tidsalder, men som overlatt til seg selv, vil falle sammen i +en annen, er videreført gjennom denne subtile korrupsjonen i vår politiske +prosess. RCA hadde hva Causby-ene ikke hadde: Makten til å undertrykke +effekten av en teknologisk endring. +

+Det er ingen enkeltoppfinner av Internet. Ei heller er det en god dato som +kan brukes til å markere når det ble født. Likevel har internettet i løpet +av svært kort tid blitt en del av vanlige amerikaneres liv. I følge the Pew +Internet and American Life-prosjektet, har 58 prosent av amerikanerne hatt +tilgang til internettet i 2002, opp fra 49 prosent to år +tidligere.[10] Det tallet kan uten +problemer passere to tredjedeler av nasjonen ved utgangen av 2004. +

+Etter hvert som internett er blitt integrert inn i det vanlige liv har ting +blitt endret. Noen av disse endringene er teknisk—internettet har +gjort kommunikasjon raskere, det har redusert kostnaden med å samle inn +data, og så videre. Disse tekniske endringene er ikke fokus for denne +boken. De er viktige. De er ikke godt forstått. Men de er den type ting +som ganske enkelt ville blir borte hvis vi alle bare slo av internettet. De +påvirker ikke folk som ikke bruker internettet, eller i det miste påvirker +det ikke dem direkte. De er et godt tema for en bok om internettet. Men +dette er ikke en bok om internettet. +

+I stedet er denne boken om effekten av internettet ut over internettet i seg +selv. En effekt på hvordan kultur blir skapt. Min påstand er at +internettet har ført til en viktig og ukjent endring i denne prosessen. +Denne endringen vil forandre en tradisjon som er like gammel som republikken +selv. De fleste, hvis de la merke til denne endringen, ville avvise den. +Men de fleste legger ikke engang merke til denne endringen som internettet +har introdusert. +

+ +Vi kan få en følelse av denne endringen ved å skille mellom kommersiell og +ikke-kommersiell kultur, ved å knytte lovens reguleringer til hver av dem. +Med "kommersiell kultur" mener jeg den delen av vår kultur som er produsert +og solgt eller produsert for å bli solgt. Med "ikke-kommersiell kultur" +mener jeg alt det andre. Da gamle menn satt rundt i parker eller på +gatehjørner og fortalte historier som unger og andre lyttet til, så var det +ikke-kommersiell kultur. Da Noah Webster publiserte sin "Reader", eller +Joel Barlow sin poesi, så var det kommersiell kultur. +

+Fra historisk tid, og for omtrent hele vår tradisjon, har ikke-kommersiell +kultur i hovedsak ikke vært regulert. Selvfølgelig, hvis din historie var +utuktig, eller hvis dine sanger forstyrret freden, kunne loven gripe inn. +Men loven var aldri direkte interessert i skapingen eller spredningen av +denne form for kultur, og lot denne kulturen være "fri". Den vanlige måten +som vanlige individer delte og formet deres kultur—historiefortelling, +formidling av scener fra teater eller TV, delta i fan-klubber, deling av +musikk, laging av kassetter—ble ikke styrt av lovverket. +

+Fokuset på loven var kommersiell kreativitet. I starten forsiktig, etter +hvert betraktelig, beskytter loven insentivet til skaperne ved å tildele dem +en eksklusiv rett til deres kreative verker, slik at de kan selge disse +eksklusive rettighetene på en kommersiell markedsplass.[11] Dette er også, naturligvis, en viktig del av +kreativitet og kultur, og det har blitt en viktigere og viktigere del i +USA. Men det var på ingen måte dominerende i vår tradisjon. Det var i +stedet bare en del, en kontrollert del, balansert mot det frie. +

+Denne grove inndelingen mellom den frie og den kontrollerte har nå blitt +fjernet.[12] Internettet har satt scenen +for denne fjerningen, og pressen frem av store medieaktører har loven nå +påvirket det. For første gang i vår tradisjon, har de vanlige måtene som +individer skaper og deler kultur havnet innen rekekvidde for reguleringene +til loven, som har blitt utvidet til å dra inn i sitt kontrollområde den +enorme mengden kultur og kreativitet som den aldri tidligere har nådd over. +Teknologien som tok vare på den historiske balansen—mellom bruken av +den delen av kulturen vår som var fri og bruken av vår kultur som krevde +tillatelse—har blitt borte. Konsekvensen er at vi er mindre og mindre +en fri kultur, og mer og mer en tillatelseskultur. +

+Denne endringen blir rettferdiggjort som nødvendig for å beskytte +kommersiell kreativitet. Og ganske riktig, proteksjonisme er nøyaktig det +som motiverer endringen. Men proteksjonismen som rettferdiggjør endringene +som jeg skal beskrive lenger ned er ikke den begrensede og balanserte typen +som har definert loven tidligere. Dette er ikke en proteksjonisme for å +beskytte artister. Det er i stedet en proteksjonisme for å beskytte +bestemte forretningsformer. Selskaper som er truet av potensialet til +internettet for å endre måten både kommersiell og ikke-kommersiell kultur +blir skapt og delt, har samlet seg for å få lovgiverne til å bruke loven for +å beskytte selskapene. Dette er historien om RCA og Armstrong, og det er +drømmen til Causbyene. +

+For internettet har sluppet løs en ekstraordinær mulighet for mange til å +delta i prosessen med å bygge og kultivere en kultur som rekker lagt utenfor +lokale grenselinjer. Den makten har endret markedsplassen for å lage og +kultivere kultur generelt, og den endringen truer i neste omgang etablerte +innholdsindustrier. Internettet er dermed for industriene som bygget og +distribuerte innhold i det tjuende århundret hva FM-radio var for AM-radio, +eller hva traileren var for jernbaneindustrien i det nittende århundret: +begynnelsen på slutten, eller i hvert fall en markant endring. Digitale +teknologier, knyttet til internettet, kunne produsere et mye mer +konkurransedyktig og levende marked for å bygge og kultivere kultur. Dette +markedet kunne inneholde en mye videre og mer variert utvalg av skapere. +Disse skaperne kunne produsere og distribuere et mye mer levende utvalg av +kreativitet. Og avhengig av noen få viktige faktorer, så kunne disse +skaperne tjenere mer i snitt fra dette systemet enn skaperne gjør i +dag—så lenge RCA-ene av i dag ikke bruker loven til å beskytte dem +selv mot denne konkurransen. +

+Likevel, som jeg argumenterer for i sidene som følger, er dette nøyaktig det +som skjer i vår kultur i dag. Dette som er dagens ekvivalenter til tidlig +tjuende århundres radio og nittende århundres jernbaner bruker deres makt +til å få loven til å beskytte dem mot dette nye, mer effektive, mer levende +teknologi for å bygge kultur. De lykkes i deres plan om å gjøre om +internettet før internettet gjør om på dem. +

+Det ser ikke slik ut for mange. Kamphandlingene over opphavsrett og +internettet er fjernt for de fleste. For de få som følger dem, virker de i +hovedsak å handle om et enklere sett med spørsmål—hvorvidt +"piratvirksomhet" vil bli akseptert, og hvorvidt "eiendomsretten" vil bli +beskyttet. "Krigen" som har blitt erklært mot teknologiene til +internettet—det presidenten for Motion Picture Association of America +(MPAA) Jack Valenti kaller sin "egen terroristkrig"[13]—har blitt rammet inn som en kamp om å følge +loven og respektere eiendomsretten. For å vite hvilken side vi bør ta i +denne krigen, de fleste tenker at vi kun trenger å bestemme om hvorvidt vi +er for eiendomsrett eller mot den. +

+Hvis dette virkelig var alternativene, så ville jeg være enig med Jack +Valenti og innholdsindustrien. Jeg tror også på eiendomsretten, og spesielt +på viktigheten av hva Mr. Valenti så pent kaller "kreativ eiendomsrett". +Jeg tror at "piratvirksomhet" er galt, og at loven, riktig innstilt, bør +straffe "piratvirksomhet", både på og utenfor internettet. +

+Men disse enkle trosoppfatninger maskerer et mye mer grunnleggende spørsmål +og en mye mer dramatisk endring. Min frykt er at med mindre vi begynner å +legge merke til denne endringen, så vil krigen for å befri verden fra +internettets "pirater" også fjerne verdier fra vår kultur som har vært +integrert til vår tradisjon helt fra starten. +

+Disse verdiene bygget en tradisjon som, for i hvert fall de første 180 årene +av vår republikk, garanterte skaperne rettigheten til å bygge fritt på deres +fortid, og beskyttet skaperne og innovatørene fra både statlig og privat +kontroll. Det første grunnlovstillegget beskyttet skaperne fra statlig +kontroll. Og som professor Neil Netanel kraftfylt argumenterer,[14] opphavsrettslov, skikkelig balansert, beskyttet +skaperne mot privat kontroll. Vår tradisjon var dermed hverken Sovjet eller +tradisjonen til velgjørere. I stedet skar det ut en bred manøvreringsrom +hvor skapere kunne kultivere og utvide vår kultur. +

+Likevel har lovens respons til internettet, når det knyttes sammen til +endringer i teknologien i internettet selv, ført til massiv økting av den +effektive reguleringen av kreativitet i USA. For å bygge på eller kritisere +kulturen rundt oss må en spørre, som Oliver Twist, om tillatelse først. +Tillatelse er, naturligvis, ofte innvilget—men det er ikke ofte +innvilget til den kritiske eller den uavhengige. Vi har bygget en slags +kulturell adel. De innen dette adelskapet har et enkelt liv, mens de på +utsiden har det ikke. Men det er adelskap i alle former som er fremmed for +vår tradisjon. +

+Historien som følger er om denne krigen. Er det ikke om "betydningen av +teknologi" i vanlig liv. Jeg tror ikke på guder, hverken digitale eller +andre typer. Det er heller ikke et forsøk på å demonisere noen individer +eller gruppe, jeg tro heller ikke i en djevel, selskapsmessig eller på annen +måte. Det er ikke en moralsk historie. Ei heller er det et rop om hellig +krig mot en industri. +

+Det er i stedet et forsøk på å forstå en håpløst ødeleggende krig som er +inspirert av teknologiene til internettet, men som rekker lang utenfor dens +kode. Og ved å forstå denne kampen er den en innsats for å finne veien til +fred. Det er ingen god grunn for å fortsette dagens batalje rundt +internett-teknologiene. Det vil være til stor skade for vår tradisjon og +kultur hvis den får lov til å fortsette ukontrollert. Vi må forstå kilden +til denne krigen. Vi må finne en løsning snart. +

+Lik Causbyenes kamp er denne krigen, delvis, om "eiendomsrett". Eiendommen i +denne krigen er ikke like håndfast som den til Causbyene, og ingen uskyldige +kyllinger har så langt mistet livet. Likevel er idéene rundt denne +"eiendomsretten" like åpenbare for de fleste som Causbyenes krav om +ukrenkeligheten til deres bondegård var for dem. De fleste av oss tar for +gitt de uvanlig mektige krav som eierne av "immaterielle rettigheter" nå +hevder. De fleste av oss, som Causbyene, behandler disse kravene som +åpenbare. Og dermed protesterer vi, som Causbyene,, når ny teknologi griper +inn i denne eiendomsretten. Det er så klart for oss som det var fro dem at +de nye teknologiene til internettet "tar seg til rette" mot legitime krav +til "eiendomsrett". Det er like klart for oss som det var for dem at loven +skulle ta affære for å stoppe denne inntrengingen i annen manns eiendom. +

+ +Og dermed, når nerder og teknologer forsvarer sin tids Armstrong og +Wright-brødenes teknologi, får de lite sympati fra de fleste av oss. Sunn +fornuft gjør ikke opprør. I motsetning til saken til de uheldige Causbyene, +er sunn fornuft på samme side som eiendomseierne i denne krigen. I +motsetning til hos de heldige Wright-brødrene, har internettet ikke +inspirert en revolusjon til fordel for seg. +

+Mitt håp er å skyve denne sunne fornuften videre. Jeg har blitt stadig mer +overrasket over kraften til denne idéen om immaterielle rettigheter og, mer +viktig, dets evne til å slå av kritisk tanke hos lovmakere og innbyggere. +Det har aldri før i vår historie vært så mye av vår "kultur" som har vært +"eid" enn det er nå. Og likevel har aldri før konsentrasjonen av makt til å +kontrollere bruken av kulturen vært mer akseptert uten spørsmål enn det er +nå. +

+Gåten er, hvorfor det? Er det fordi vi fått en innsikt i sannheten om +verdien og betydningen av absolutt eierskap over idéer og kultur? Er det +fordi vi har oppdaget at vår tradisjon med å avvise slike absolutte krav var +feil? +

+Eller er det på grunn av at idéer om absolutt eierskap over idéer og kultur +gir fordeler til RCA-ene i vår tid, og passer med vår ureflekterte +intuisjon? +

+Er denne radikale endringen vekk fra vår tradisjon om fri kultur en +forekomst av USA som korrigerer en feil fra sin fortid, slik vi gjorde det +etter en blodig krig mot slaveri, og slik vi sakte gjør det mot +forskjellsbehandling? Eller er denne radikale endringen vekk fra vår +tradisjon med fri kultur nok et eksempel på at vårt politiske system er +fanget av noen få mektige særinteresser? +

+Fører sunn fornuft til det ekstreme i dette spørsmålet på grunn av at sunn +fornuft faktisk tror på dette ekstreme? Eller står sunn fornuft i stillhet +i møtet med dette ekstreme fordi, som med Armstrong versus RCA, at den mer +mektige siden har sikret seg at det har et mye mer mektig synspunkt? +

+ +Jeg forsøker ikke å være mystisk. Mine egne synspunkter er klare. Jeg mener +det var riktig for sunn fornuft å gjøre opprør mot ekstremismen til +Causbyene. Jeg mener det ville være riktig for sunn fornuft å gjøre opprør +mot de ekstreme krav som gjøres i dag på vegne av "immaterielle +rettigheter". Det som loven krever i dag er mer å mer like dumt som om +lensmannen skulle arrestere en flymaskin for å trenge inn på annen manns +eiendom. Men konsekvensene av den nye dumskapen vil bli mye mer +dyptgripende. + +

+Basketaket som pågår akkurat nå senterer seg rundt to idéer: +"piratvirksomhet" og "eiendom". Mitt mål med denne bokens neste to deler er +å utforske disse to idéene. +

+Metoden min er ikke den vanlige metoden for en akademiker. Jeg ønsker ikke +å pløye deg inn i et komplisert argument, steinsatt med referanser til +obskure franske teoretikere—uansett hvor naturlig det har blitt for +den rare sorten vi akademikere har blitt. Jeg vil i stedet begynne hver del +med en samling historier som etablerer en sammenheng der disse +tilsynelatende enkle idéene kan bli fullt ut forstått. +

+De to delene setter opp kjernen i påstanden til denne boken: at mens +internettet faktisk har produsert noe fantastisk og nytt, bidrar våre +myndigheter, presset av store medieaktører for å møte dette "noe nytt" til å +ødelegge noe som er svært gammelt. I stedet for å forstå endringene som +internettet kan gjøre mulig, og i stedet for å ta den tiden som trengs for å +la "sunn fornuft" finne ut hvordan best svare på utfordringen, så lar vi de +som er mest truet av endringene bruke sin makt til å endre loven—og +viktigere, å bruke sin makt til å endre noe fundamentalt om hvordan vi +alltid har fungert. +

+Jeg tror vi tillater dette, ikke fordi det er riktig, og heller ikke fordi +de fleste av oss tror på disse endringene. Vi tillater det på grunn av at +de interessene som er mest truet er blant de mest mektige aktørene i vår +deprimerende kompromitterte prosess for å utforme lover. Denne boken er +historien om nok en konsekvens for denne type korrupsjon—en konsekvens +for de fleste av oss forblir ukjent med. +



[4] +St. George Tucker, Blackstone's Commentaries 3 (South Hackensack, N.J.: +Rothman Reprints, 1969), 18. +

[5] +USA mot Causby, U.S. 328 (1946): 256, 261. Domstolen fant at det kunne være +å "ta" hvis regjeringens bruk av sitt land reelt sett hadde ødelagt verdien +av eiendomen til Causby. Dette eksemplet ble foreslått for meg i Keith +Aokis flotte stykke, "(intellectual) Property and Sovereignty: Notes Toward +a cultural Geography of Authorship", Stanford Law Review 48 (1996): 1293, +1333. Se også Paul Goldstein, Real Property (Mineola, N.Y.: Foundation Press +(1984)), 1112–13. +

[6] +Lawrence Lessing, Man of High Fidelity:: Edwin Howard Armstrong +(Philadelphia: J. B. Lipincott Company, 1956), 209. +

[7] Se "Saints: The Heroes and Geniuses of the Electronic Era," første +elektroniske kirke i USA, hos www.webstationone.com/fecha, tilgjengelig fra +link #1. +

[8] Lessing, 226. +

[9] +Lessing, 256. +

[10] +Amanda Lenhart, "The Ever-Shifting Internet Population: A New Look at +Internet Access and the Digital Divide," Pew Internet and American Life +Project, 15. april 2003: 6, tilgjengelig fra link #2. +

[11] +Dette er ikke det eneste formålet med opphavsrett, men det er helt klart +hovedformålet med opphavsretten slik den er etablert i føderal grunnlov. +Opphavsrettslovene i delstatene beskyttet historisk ikke bare kommersielle +interesse når det gjalt publikasjoner, men også personverninteresser. Ved å +gi forfattere eneretten til å publisere først, ga delstatenes +opphavsrettslovene forfatterne makt til å kontrollere spredningen av fakta +om seg selv. Se Samuel D. Warren og Louis Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy", +Harvard Law Review 4 (1890): 193, 198–200. +

[12] +Se Jessica Litman, Digital Copyright (New York: Prometheus bøker, 2001), +kap. 13. +

[13] +Amy Harmon, "Black Hawk Download: Moving Beyond Music, Pirates Use New Tools +to Turn the Net into an Illicit Video Club," New York Times, 17. januar +2002. +

[14] +Neil W. Netanel, "Copyright and a Democratic Civil Society," Yale Law +Journal 106 (1996): 283. +

Kapittel 2. "Piratvirksomhet"

+Helt siden loven begynte å regulere kreative eierrettigheter, har det vært +en krig mot "piratvirksomhet". De presise konturene av dette konseptet, +"piratvirksomhet", har vært vanskelig å tegne opp, men bildet av +urettferdighet er enkelt å beskrive. Som Lord Mansfield skrev i en sak som +utvidet rekkevidden for engelsk opphavsrettslov til å inkludere noteark, +

+En person kan bruke kopien til å spille den, men han har ingen rett til å +robbe forfatteren for profitten, ved å lage flere kopier og distribuere +etter eget forgodtbefinnende.[15] +

+ +I dag er vi midt inne i en annen "krig" mot "piratvirksomhet". Internettet +har fremprovosert denne krigen. Internettet gjør det mulig å effektivt spre +innhold. Peer-to-peer (p2p) fildeling er blant det mest effektive av de +effektive teknologier internettet muliggjør. Ved å bruke distribuert +intelligens, kan p2p-systemer muliggjøre enkel spredning av innhold på en +måte som ingen forestilte seg for en generasjon siden. + +

+Denne effektiviteten respekterer ikke de tradisjonelle skillene i +opphavsretten. Nettverket skiller ikke mellom deling av +opphavsrettsbeskyttet og ikke opphavsrettsbeskyttet innhold. Dermed har det +vært deling av en enorm mengde opphavsrettsbeskyttet innhold. Denne +delingen har i sin tur ansporet til krigen, på grunn av at eiere av +opphavsretter frykter delingen vil "frata forfatteren overskuddet." +

+Krigerne har snudd seg til domstolene, til lovgiverne, og i stadig større +grad til teknologi for å forsvare sin "eiendom" mot denne +"piratvirksomheten". En generasjon amerikanere, advarer krigerne, blir +oppdratt til å tro at "eiendom" skal være "gratis". Glem tatoveringer, ikke +tenk på kroppspiercing—våre barn blir tyver! +

+Det er ingen tvil om at "piratvirksomhet" er galt, og at pirater bør +straffes. Men før vi roper på bødlene, bør vi sette dette +"piratvirksomhets"-begrepet i en sammenheng. For mens begrepet blir mer og +mer brukt, har det i sin kjerne en ekstraordinær idé som nesten helt sikkert +er feil. +

+Idéen høres omtrent slik ut: +

+Kreativt arbeid har verdi. Når jeg bruker, eller tar, eller bygger på det +kreative arbeidet til andre, så tar jeg noe fra dem som har verdi. Når jeg +tar noe av verdi fra noen andre, bør jeg få tillatelse fra dem. Å ta noe +som har verdi fra andre uten tillatelse er galt. Det er en form for +piratvirksomhet. +

+Dette synet går dypt i de pågående debattene. Det er hva jussprofessor +Rochelle Dreyfuss ved NYU kritiserer som "hvis verdi, så rettighet"-teorien +for kreative eierrettigheter [16]—hvis det finnes verdi, så må noen ha rettigheten til denne +verdien. Det er perspektivet som fikk komponistenes rettighetsorganisasjon, +ASCAP, til å saksøke jentespeiderne for å ikke betale for sangene som +jentene sagt rundt jentespeidernes leirbål.[17] Det fantes "verdi" (sangene), så det måtte ha vært en +"rettighet"—til og med mot jentespeiderne. +

+ +Denne idéen er helt klart en mulig forståelse om hvordan kreative +eierrettigheter bør virke. Det er helt klart et mulig design for et +lovsystem som beskytter kreative eierrettigheter. Men teorien om "hvis +verdi, så rettighet" for kreative eierrettigheter har aldri vært USAs teori +for kreative eierrettigheter. It har aldri stått rot i vårt lovverk. +

+I vår tradisjon har immaterielle rettigheter i stedet vært et instrument. +Det bygger fundamentet for et rikt kreativt samfunn, men er fortsatt servilt +til verdien av kreativitet. Dagens debatt har snudd dette helt rundt. Vi +har blitt så opptatt av å beskytte instrumentet at vi mister verdien av +syne. +

+Kilden til denne forvirringen er et skille som loven ikke lenger bryr seg om +å markere—skillet mellom å gjenpublisere noens verk på den ene siden, +og bygge på og gjøre om verket på den andre. Da opphavsretten kom var det +kun publisering som ble berørt. Opphavsretten i dag regulerer begge. +

+Før teknologiene til internettet dukket opp, betød ikke denne begrepsmessige +sammenblandingen mye. Teknologiene for å publisere var kostbare, som betød +at det meste av publisering var kommersiell. Kommersielle aktører kunne +håndtere byrden pålagt av loven—til og med byrden som den bysantiske +kompleksiteten som opphavsrettsloven har blitt. Det var bare nok en kostnad +ved å drive forretning. +

+But with the birth of the Internet, this natural limit to the reach of the +law has disappeared. The law controls not just the creativity of commercial +creators but effectively that of anyone. Although that expansion would not +matter much if copyright law regulated only "copying," when the law +regulates as broadly and obscurely as it does, the extension matters a +lot. The burden of this law now vastly outweighs any original +benefit—certainly as it affects noncommercial creativity, and +increasingly as it affects commercial creativity as well. Thus, as we'll see +more clearly in the chapters below, the law's role is less and less to +support creativity, and more and more to protect certain industries against +competition. Just at the time digital technology could unleash an +extraordinary range of commercial and noncommercial creativity, the law +burdens this creativity with insanely complex and vague rules and with the +threat of obscenely severe penalties. We may be seeing, as Richard Florida +writes, the "Rise of the Creative Class."[18] Unfortunately, we are also seeing an extraordinary rise of +regulation of this creative class. +

+Disse byrdene gir ingen mening i vår tradisjon. Vi bør begynne med å forstå +den tradisjonen litt mer, og ved å plassere dagens slag om oppførsel med +merkelappen "piratvirksomhet" i sin rette sammenheng. +

Kapittel en: Skaperne

+I 1928 ble en tegnefilmfigur født. En tidlig Mikke Mus debuterte i mai +dette året, i en stille flopp ved navn Plane Crazy. I november, i Colony +teateret i New York City, ble den første vidt distribuerte tegnefilmen med +synkronisert lyd, Steamboat Willy, vist frem med figuren som skulle bli til +Mikke Mus. +

+Film med sykronisert lyd hadde blitt introdusert et år tidligere i filmen +The Jazz Singer. Suksessen fikk Walt Disney til å kopiere teknikken og +mikse lyd med tegnefilm. Ingen visste hvorvidt det ville virke eller ikke, +og om det fungere, hvorvidt publikum villa ha sans for det. Men da Disney +gjorde en test sommeren 1928, var resutlatet entydig. Som Disney beskriver +dette første eksperimentet, +

+ +Et par av guttene mine kunne lese noteark, og en av dem kunne spille +munnspill. Vi stappet dem inn i et rom hvor de ikke kunne se skjermen, og +gjorde det slik at lyden de spilte ble sendt videre til et rom hvor våre +koner og venner var plassert for å se på bildet. + +

+Guttene brukte et note- og lydeffekt-ark. Etter noen dårlige oppstarter, +kom endelig lyd og handlig i gang med et smell. Munnspilleren spilte +melodien, og resten av oss i lydavdelingen slamret på tinnkasseroller og +blåste på slide-fløyte til rytmen. Synkroniseringen var nesten helt riktig. +

+Effekten på vårt lille publikum var intet mindre enn elektrisk. De reagerte +nesten instiktivt til denne union av lyd og bevegelse. Jeg trodde de tullet +med meg. Så de puttet meg i publikum og satte igang på nytt. Det var +grufult, men det var fantastisk. Og det var noe nytt![19] +

+Disneys daværende partner, og en av animasjonsverdenens mest ekstraordinære +talenter, Ub Iwerks, uttalte det sterkere: "Jeg har aldri vært så begeistret +i hele mitt liv. Ingenting annet har noen sinne vært like bra." +

+Disney hadde laget noe helt nyt, basert på noe relativt nytt. Synkronisert +lyd ga liv til en form for kreativitet som sjeldent hadde—unntatt fra +Disneys hender—vært noe annet en fyllstoff for andre filmer. Gjennom +animasjonens tidligere historie var det Disneys oppfinnelse som satte +standarden som andre måtte sloss for å oppfylle. Og ganske ofte var Disneys +store geni, hans gnist av kreativitet, bygget på arbeidet til andre. +

+Dette er kjent stoff. Det du kanskje ikke vet er at 1928 også markerer en +annen viktig overgang. I samme år laget et komedie-geni (i motsetning til +tegnefilm-geni) sin siste uavhengig produserte stumfilm. Dette geniet var +Buster Keaton. Filmen var Steamboat Bill, Jr. +

+Keaton ble født inn i en vauderville-familie i 1895. I stumfilm-æraen hadde +han mestret bruken av bredpenslet fysisk komedie på en måte som tente +ukontrollerbar latter fra hans publikum. Steamboat Bill, Jr. var en klassier +av denne typen, berømt blant film-elskere for sine utrolige stunts. Filmen +var en klassisk Keaton—fantastisk populær og blant de beste i sin +sjanger. +

+Steamboat Bill, Jr. appeared before Disney's cartoon Steamboat Willie. The +coincidence of titles is not coincidental. Steamboat Willie is a direct +cartoon parody of Steamboat Bill,[20] and +both are built upon a common song as a source. It is not just from the +invention of synchronized sound in The Jazz Singer that we get Steamboat +Willie. It is also from Buster Keaton's invention of Steamboat Bill, Jr., +itself inspired by the song "Steamboat Bill," that we get Steamboat Willie, +and then from Steamboat Willie, Mickey Mouse. +

+Denne "låningen" var ikke unik, hverken for Disney eller for industrien. +Disney apet alltid etter full-lengde massemarkedsfilmene rundt +ham.[21] Det samme gjorde mange andre. +Tidlige tegnefilmer er stappfulle av etterapninger—små variasjoner +over suksessfulle temaer, gamle historier fortalt på nytt. Nøkkelen til +suksess var brilliansen i forskjellene. Med Disney var det lyden som ga +gnisten til hans animasjoner. Senere var det kvaliteten på hans arbeide +relativt til de masseproduserte tegnefilmene som han konkurrerte med. +Likevel var disse bidragene bygget på toppen av fundamentet som var lånt. +Disney bygget på arbeidet til andre som kom før han, og skapte noe nytt ut +av noe som bare var litt gammelt. +

+Noen ganger var låningen begrenset, og noen ganger var den betydelig. Tenkt +på eventurene til brødrene Grimm. Hvis du er like ubevisst som jeg var, så +tror du sannsynlighvis at disse fortellingene er glade, søte historier som +passer for ethvert barn ved leggetid. Realiteten er at Grimm-eventyrene er, +for oss, ganske dystre. Det er noen sjeldne og kanskje spesielt ambisiøse +foreldre som ville våge å lese disse blodige moralistiske historiene til +sine barn, ved leggetid eller hvilken som helst annet tidspunkt. +

+ +Disney tok disse historiene og fortalte dem på nytt på en måte som førte dem +inn i en ny tidsalder. Han ga historiene liv, med både karakterer og +lys. Uten å fjerne bitene av frykt og fare helt, gjorde han morsomt det som +var mørkt og satte inn en ekte følelse av medfølelse der det før var +frykt. Og ikke bare med verkene av brødrene Grimm. Faktisk er katalogen +over Disney-arbeid som baserer seg på arbeidet til andre ganske forbløffende +når den blir samlet: Snøhvit (1937), Fantasia (1940), Pinocchio (1940), +Dumbo (1941), Bambi (1942), Song of the South (1946), Askepott (1950), Alice +in Wonderland (1951), Robin Hood (1952), Peter Pan (1953), Lady og +landstrykeren (1955), Mulan (1998), Tornerose (1959), 101 dalmatinere +(1961), Sverdet i steinen (1963), og Jungelboken (1967)—for ikke å +nevne et nylig eksempel som vi bør kanskje glemme raskt, Treasure Planet +(2003). I alle disse tilfellene, har Disney (eller Disney, Inc.) hentet +kreativitet fra kultur rundt ham, blandet med kreativiteten fra sitt eget +ekstraordinære talent, og deretter brent denne blandingen inn i sjelen til +sin kultur. Hente, blande og brenne. +

+This is a kind of creativity. It is a creativity that we should remember and +celebrate. There are some who would say that there is no creativity except +this kind. We don't need to go that far to recognize its importance. We +could call this "Disney creativity," though that would be a bit +misleading. It is, more precisely, "Walt Disney creativity"—a form of +expression and genius that builds upon the culture around us and makes it +something different. +

In 1928, the culture that Disney was free to draw upon was relatively +fresh. The public domain in 1928 was not very old and was therefore quite +vibrant. The average term of copyright was just around thirty +years—for that minority of creative work that was in fact +copyrighted.[22] That means that for thirty +years, on average, the authors or copyright holders of a creative work had +an "exclusive right" to control certain uses of the work. To use this +copyrighted work in limited ways required the permission of the copyright +owner. +

+At the end of a copyright term, a work passes into the public domain. No +permission is then needed to draw upon or use that work. No permission and, +hence, no lawyers. The public domain is a "lawyer-free zone." Thus, most of +the content from the nineteenth century was free for Disney to use and build +upon in 1928. It was free for anyone— whether connected or not, +whether rich or not, whether approved or not—to use and build upon. +

+ +This is the ways things always were—until quite recently. For most of +our history, the public domain was just over the horizon. From until 1978, +the average copyright term was never more than thirty-two years, meaning +that most culture just a generation and a half old was free for anyone to +build upon without the permission of anyone else. Today's equivalent would +be for creative work from the 1960s and 1970s to now be free for the next +Walt Disney to build upon without permission. Yet today, the public domain +is presumptive only for content from before the Great Depression. +

+Of course, Walt Disney had no monopoly on "Walt Disney creativity." Nor does +America. The norm of free culture has, until recently, and except within +totalitarian nations, been broadly exploited and quite universal. +

+Consider, for example, a form of creativity that seems strange to many +Americans but that is inescapable within Japanese culture: manga, or +comics. The Japanese are fanatics about comics. Some 40 percent of +publications are comics, and 30 percent of publication revenue derives from +comics. They are everywhere in Japanese society, at every magazine stand, +carried by a large proportion of commuters on Japan's extraordinary system +of public transportation. +

+Americans tend to look down upon this form of culture. That's an +unattractive characteristic of ours. We're likely to misunderstand much +about manga, because few of us have ever read anything close to the stories +that these "graphic novels" tell. For the Japanese, manga cover every aspect +of social life. For us, comics are "men in tights." And anyway, it's not as +if the New York subways are filled with readers of Joyce or even +Hemingway. People of different cultures distract themselves in different +ways, the Japanese in this interestingly different way. +

+Men mitt formål her er ikke å forstå manga. Det er a beskrive en variant av +manga som fra en avokats perspektiv er ganske merkelig, men som fra en +Disneys perspektiv er ganske godt kjent. +

+ +This is the phenomenon of doujinshi. Doujinshi are also comics, but they are +a kind of copycat comic. A rich ethic governs the creation of doujinshi. It +is not doujinshi if it is just a copy; the artist must make a contribution +to the art he copies, by transforming it either subtly or significantly. A +doujinshi comic can thus take a mainstream comic and develop it +differently—with a different story line. Or the comic can keep the +character in character but change its look slightly. There is no formula for +what makes the doujinshi sufficiently "different." But they must be +different if they are to be considered true doujinshi. Indeed, there are +committees that review doujinshi for inclusion within shows and reject any +copycat comic that is merely a copy. +

+These copycat comics are not a tiny part of the manga market. They are +huge. More than 33,000 "circles" of creators from across Japan produce these +bits of Walt Disney creativity. More than 450,000 Japanese come together +twice a year, in the largest public gathering in the country, to exchange +and sell them. This market exists in parallel to the mainstream commercial +manga market. In some ways, it obviously competes with that market, but +there is no sustained effort by those who control the commercial manga +market to shut the doujinshi market down. It flourishes, despite the +competition and despite the law. +

+The most puzzling feature of the doujinshi market, for those trained in the +law, at least, is that it is allowed to exist at all. Under Japanese +copyright law, which in this respect (on paper) mirrors American copyright +law, the doujinshi market is an illegal one. Doujinshi are plainly +"derivative works." There is no general practice by doujinshi artists of +securing the permission of the manga creators. Instead, the practice is +simply to take and modify the creations of others, as Walt Disney did with +Steamboat Bill, Jr. Under both Japanese and American law, that "taking" +without the permission of the original copyright owner is illegal. It is an +infringement of the original copyright to make a copy or a derivative work +without the original copyright owner's permission. +

+Yet this illegal market exists and indeed flourishes in Japan, and in the +view of many, it is precisely because it exists that Japanese manga +flourish. As American graphic novelist Judd Winick said to me, "The early +days of comics in America are very much like what's going on in Japan +now. . . . American comics were born out of copying each other. . . . That's +how [the artists] learn to draw—by going into comic books and not +tracing them, but looking at them and copying them" and building from +them.[23] +

+American comics now are quite different, Winick explains, in part because of +the legal difficulty of adapting comics the way doujinshi are +allowed. Speaking of Superman, Winick told me, "there are these rules and +you have to stick to them." There are things Superman "cannot" do. "As a +creator, it's frustrating having to stick to some parameters which are fifty +years old." +

+The norm in Japan mitigates this legal difficulty. Some say it is precisely +the benefit accruing to the Japanese manga market that explains the +mitigation. Temple University law professor Salil Mehra, for example, +hypothesizes that the manga market accepts these technical violations +because they spur the manga market to be more wealthy and +productive. Everyone would be worse off if doujinshi were banned, so the law +does not ban doujinshi.[24] +

+The problem with this story, however, as Mehra plainly acknowledges, is that +the mechanism producing this laissez faire response is not clear. It may +well be that the market as a whole is better off if doujinshi are permitted +rather than banned, but that doesn't explain why individual copyright owners +don't sue nonetheless. If the law has no general exception for doujinshi, +and indeed in some cases individual manga artists have sued doujinshi +artists, why is there not a more general pattern of blocking this "free +taking" by the doujinshi culture? +

+I spent four wonderful months in Japan, and I asked this question as often +as I could. Perhaps the best account in the end was offered by a friend from +a major Japanese law firm. "We don't have enough lawyers," he told me one +afternoon. There "just aren't enough resources to prosecute cases like +this." +

+ +This is a theme to which we will return: that regulation by law is a +function of both the words on the books and the costs of making those words +have effect. For now, focus on the obvious question that is begged: Would +Japan be better off with more lawyers? Would manga be richer if doujinshi +artists were regularly prosecuted? Would the Japanese gain something +important if they could end this practice of uncompensated sharing? Does +piracy here hurt the victims of the piracy, or does it help them? Would +lawyers fighting this piracy help their clients or hurt them? Let's pause +for a moment. +

+If you're like I was a decade ago, or like most people are when they first +start thinking about these issues, then just about now you should be puzzled +about something you hadn't thought through before. +

+We live in a world that celebrates "property." I am one of those +celebrants. I believe in the value of property in general, and I also +believe in the value of that weird form of property that lawyers call +"intellectual property."[25] A large, +diverse society cannot survive without property; a large, diverse, and +modern society cannot flourish without intellectual property. +

+But it takes just a second's reflection to realize that there is plenty of +value out there that "property" doesn't capture. I don't mean "money can't +buy you love," but rather, value that is plainly part of a process of +production, including commercial as well as noncommercial production. If +Disney animators had stolen a set of pencils to draw Steamboat Willie, we'd +have no hesitation in condemning that taking as wrong— even though +trivial, even if unnoticed. Yet there was nothing wrong, at least under the +law of the day, with Disney's taking from Buster Keaton or from the Brothers +Grimm. There was nothing wrong with the taking from Keaton because Disney's +use would have been considered "fair." There was nothing wrong with the +taking from the Grimms because the Grimms' work was in the public domain. +

+ +Thus, even though the things that Disney took—or more generally, the +things taken by anyone exercising Walt Disney creativity—are valuable, +our tradition does not treat those takings as wrong. Some things remain free +for the taking within a free culture, and that freedom is good. +

+The same with the doujinshi culture. If a doujinshi artist broke into a +publisher's office and ran off with a thousand copies of his latest +work—or even one copy—without paying, we'd have no hesitation in +saying the artist was wrong. In addition to having trespassed, he would have +stolen something of value. The law bans that stealing in whatever form, +whether large or small. +

+Yet there is an obvious reluctance, even among Japanese lawyers, to say that +the copycat comic artists are "stealing." This form of Walt Disney +creativity is seen as fair and right, even if lawyers in particular find it +hard to say why. +

+It's the same with a thousand examples that appear everywhere once you begin +to look. Scientists build upon the work of other scientists without asking +or paying for the privilege. ("Excuse me, Professor Einstein, but may I have +permission to use your theory of relativity to show that you were wrong +about quantum physics?") Acting companies perform adaptations of the works +of Shakespeare without securing permission from anyone. (Does anyone believe +Shakespeare would be better spread within our culture if there were a +central Shakespeare rights clearinghouse that all productions of Shakespeare +must appeal to first?) And Hollywood goes through cycles with a certain kind +of movie: five asteroid films in the late 1990s; two volcano disaster films +in 1997. +

+ +Creators here and everywhere are always and at all times building upon the +creativity that went before and that surrounds them now. That building is +always and everywhere at least partially done without permission and without +compensating the original creator. No society, free or controlled, has ever +demanded that every use be paid for or that permission for Walt Disney +creativity must always be sought. Instead, every society has left a certain +bit of its culture free for the taking—free societies more fully than +unfree, perhaps, but all societies to some degree. + +

+The hard question is therefore not whether a culture is free. All cultures +are free to some degree. The hard question instead is "How free is this +culture?" How much, and how broadly, is the culture free for others to take +and build upon? Is that freedom limited to party members? To members of the +royal family? To the top ten corporations on the New York Stock Exchange? Or +is that freedom spread broadly? To artists generally, whether affiliated +with the Met or not? To musicians generally, whether white or not? To +filmmakers generally, whether affiliated with a studio or not? +

+Frie kulturer er kulturer som etterlater mye åpent for andre å bygge på. +Ufrie, eller tillatelse-kulturer etterlater mye mindre. Vår var en fri +kultur. Den er på tur til å bli mindre fri. +

Kapittel to: "Kun etter-apere"

+In 1839, Louis Daguerre invented the first practical technology for +producing what we would call "photographs." Appropriately enough, they were +called "daguerreotypes." The process was complicated and expensive, and the +field was thus limited to professionals and a few zealous and wealthy +amateurs. (There was even an American Daguerre Association that helped +regulate the industry, as do all such associations, by keeping competition +down so as to keep prices up.) +

+Yet despite high prices, the demand for daguerreotypes was strong. This +pushed inventors to find simpler and cheaper ways to make "automatic +pictures." William Talbot soon discovered a process for making "negatives." +But because the negatives were glass, and had to be kept wet, the process +still remained expensive and cumbersome. In the 1870s, dry plates were +developed, making it easier to separate the taking of a picture from its +developing. These were still plates of glass, and thus it was still not a +process within reach of most amateurs. +

+ +The technological change that made mass photography possible didn't happen +until 1888, and was the creation of a single man. George Eastman, himself an +amateur photographer, was frustrated by the technology of photographs made +with plates. In a flash of insight (so to speak), Eastman saw that if the +film could be made to be flexible, it could be held on a single +spindle. That roll could then be sent to a developer, driving the costs of +photography down substantially. By lowering the costs, Eastman expected he +could dramatically broaden the population of photographers. +

+Eastman developed flexible, emulsion-coated paper film and placed rolls of +it in small, simple cameras: the Kodak. The device was marketed on the basis +of its simplicity. "You press the button and we do the rest."[26] As he described in The Kodak Primer: +

+The principle of the Kodak system is the separation of the work that any +person whomsoever can do in making a photograph, from the work that only an +expert can do. . . . We furnish anybody, man, woman or child, who has +sufficient intelligence to point a box straight and press a button, with an +instrument which altogether removes from the practice of photography the +necessity for exceptional facilities or, in fact, any special knowledge of +the art. It can be employed without preliminary study, without a darkroom +and without chemicals.[27] +

+For $25, anyone could make pictures. The camera came preloaded with film, +and when it had been used, the camera was returned to an Eastman factory, +where the film was developed. Over time, of course, the cost of the camera +and the ease with which it could be used both improved. Roll film thus +became the basis for the explosive growth of popular photography. Eastman's +camera first went on sale in 1888; one year later, Kodak was printing more +than six thousand negatives a day. From 1888 through 1909, while industrial +production was rising by 4.7 percent, photographic equipment and material +sales increased by percent.[28] Eastman +Kodak's sales during the same period experienced an average annual increase +of over 17 percent.[29] +

+ + +The real significance of Eastman's invention, however, was not economic. It +was social. Professional photography gave individuals a glimpse of places +they would never otherwise see. Amateur photography gave them the ability to +record their own lives in a way they had never been able to do before. As +author Brian Coe notes, "For the first time the snapshot album provided the +man on the street with a permanent record of his family and its +activities. . . . For the first time in history there exists an authentic +visual record of the appearance and activities of the common man made +without [literary] interpretation or bias."[30] +

+In this way, the Kodak camera and film were technologies of expression. The +pencil or paintbrush was also a technology of expression, of course. But it +took years of training before they could be deployed by amateurs in any +useful or effective way. With the Kodak, expression was possible much sooner +and more simply. The barrier to expression was lowered. Snobs would sneer at +its "quality"; professionals would discount it as irrelevant. But watch a +child study how best to frame a picture and you get a sense of the +experience of creativity that the Kodak enabled. Democratic tools gave +ordinary people a way to express themselves more easily than any tools could +have before. +

+What was required for this technology to flourish? Obviously, Eastman's +genius was an important part. But also important was the legal environment +within which Eastman's invention grew. For early in the history of +photography, there was a series of judicial decisions that could well have +changed the course of photography substantially. Courts were asked whether +the photographer, amateur or professional, required permission before he +could capture and print whatever image he wanted. Their answer was +no.[31] +

+ +The arguments in favor of requiring permission will sound surprisingly +familiar. The photographer was "taking" something from the person or +building whose photograph he shot—pirating something of value. Some +even thought he was taking the target's soul. Just as Disney was not free to +take the pencils that his animators used to draw Mickey, so, too, should +these photographers not be free to take images that they thought valuable. +

+On the other side was an argument that should be familiar, as well. Sure, +there may be something of value being used. But citizens should have the +right to capture at least those images that stand in public view. (Louis +Brandeis, who would become a Supreme Court Justice, thought the rule should +be different for images from private spaces.[32]) It may be that this means that the photographer gets something for +nothing. Just as Disney could take inspiration from Steamboat Bill, Jr. or +the Brothers Grimm, the photographer should be free to capture an image +without compensating the source. +

+Fortunately for Mr. Eastman, and for photography in general, these early +decisions went in favor of the pirates. In general, no permission would be +required before an image could be captured and shared with others. Instead, +permission was presumed. Freedom was the default. (The law would eventually +craft an exception for famous people: commercial photographers who snap +pictures of famous people for commercial purposes have more restrictions +than the rest of us. But in the ordinary case, the image can be captured +without clearing the rights to do the capturing.[33]) +

+We can only speculate about how photography would have developed had the law +gone the other way. If the presumption had been against the photographer, +then the photographer would have had to demonstrate permission. Perhaps +Eastman Kodak would have had to demonstrate permission, too, before it +developed the film upon which images were captured. After all, if permission +were not granted, then Eastman Kodak would be benefiting from the "theft" +committed by the photographer. Just as Napster benefited from the copyright +infringements committed by Napster users, Kodak would be benefiting from the +"image-right" infringement of its photographers. We could imagine the law +then requiring that some form of permission be demonstrated before a company +developed pictures. We could imagine a system developing to demonstrate that +permission. +

+ + + +But though we could imagine this system of permission, it would be very hard +to see how photography could have flourished as it did if the requirement +for permission had been built into the rules that govern it. Photography +would have existed. It would have grown in importance over +time. Professionals would have continued to use the technology as they +did—since professionals could have more easily borne the burdens of +the permission system. But the spread of photography to ordinary people +would not have occurred. Nothing like that growth would have been +realized. And certainly, nothing like that growth in a democratic technology +of expression would have been realized. If you drive through San +Francisco's Presidio, you might see two gaudy yellow school buses painted +over with colorful and striking images, and the logo "Just Think!" in place +of the name of a school. But there's little that's "just" cerebral in the +projects that these busses enable. These buses are filled with technologies +that teach kids to tinker with film. Not the film of Eastman. Not even the +film of your VCR. Rather the "film" of digital cameras. Just Think! is a +project that enables kids to make films, as a way to understand and critique +the filmed culture that they find all around them. Each year, these busses +travel to more than thirty schools and enable three hundred to five hundred +children to learn something about media by doing something with media. By +doing, they think. By tinkering, they learn. +

+These buses are not cheap, but the technology they carry is increasingly +so. The cost of a high-quality digital video system has fallen +dramatically. As one analyst puts it, "Five years ago, a good real-time +digital video editing system cost $25,000. Today you can get professional +quality for $595."[34] These buses are +filled with technology that would have cost hundreds of thousands just ten +years ago. And it is now feasible to imagine not just buses like this, but +classrooms across the country where kids are learning more and more of +something teachers call "media literacy." +

+ +"Media literacy," as Dave Yanofsky, the executive director of Just Think!, +puts it, "is the ability . . . to understand, analyze, and deconstruct media +images. Its aim is to make [kids] literate about the way media works, the +way it's constructed, the way it's delivered, and the way people access it." + +

+This may seem like an odd way to think about "literacy." For most people, +literacy is about reading and writing. Faulkner and Hemingway and noticing +split infinitives are the things that "literate" people know about. +

+Maybe. But in a world where children see on average 390 hours of television +commercials per year, or between 20,000 and 45,000 commercials +generally,[35] it is increasingly important +to understand the "grammar" of media. For just as there is a grammar for the +written word, so, too, is there one for media. And just as kids learn how to +write by writing lots of terrible prose, kids learn how to write media by +constructing lots of (at least at first) terrible media. +

+A growing field of academics and activists sees this form of literacy as +crucial to the next generation of culture. For though anyone who has written +understands how difficult writing is—how difficult it is to sequence +the story, to keep a reader's attention, to craft language to be +understandable—few of us have any real sense of how difficult media +is. Or more fundamentally, few of us have a sense of how media works, how it +holds an audience or leads it through a story, how it triggers emotion or +builds suspense. +

+It took filmmaking a generation before it could do these things well. But +even then, the knowledge was in the filming, not in writing about the +film. The skill came from experiencing the making of a film, not from +reading a book about it. One learns to write by writing and then reflecting +upon what one has written. One learns to write with images by making them +and then reflecting upon what one has created. +

+This grammar has changed as media has changed. When it was just film, as +Elizabeth Daley, executive director of the University of Southern +California's Annenberg Center for Communication and dean of the USC School +of Cinema-Television, explained to me, the grammar was about "the placement +of objects, color, . . . rhythm, pacing, and texture."[36] But as computers open up an interactive space where +a story is "played" as well as experienced, that grammar changes. The simple +control of narrative is lost, and so other techniques are necessary. Author +Michael Crichton had mastered the narrative of science fiction. But when he +tried to design a computer game based on one of his works, it was a new +craft he had to learn. How to lead people through a game without their +feeling they have been led was not obvious, even to a wildly successful +author.[37] +

+This skill is precisely the craft a filmmaker learns. As Daley describes, +"people are very surprised about how they are led through a film. [I]t is +perfectly constructed to keep you from seeing it, so you have no idea. If a +filmmaker succeeds you do not know how you were led." If you know you were +led through a film, the film has failed. +

+Yet the push for an expanded literacy—one that goes beyond text to +include audio and visual elements—is not about making better film +directors. The aim is not to improve the profession of filmmaking at all. +Instead, as Daley explained, +

+From my perspective, probably the most important digital divide is not +access to a box. It's the ability to be empowered with the language that +that box works in. Otherwise only a very few people can write with this +language, and all the rest of us are reduced to being read-only. +

+"Read-only." Passive recipients of culture produced elsewhere. Couch +potatoes. Consumers. This is the world of media from the twentieth century. +

+The twenty-first century could be different. This is the crucial point: It +could be both read and write. Or at least reading and better understanding +the craft of writing. Or best, reading and understanding the tools that +enable the writing to lead or mislead. The aim of any literacy, and this +literacy in particular, is to "empower people to choose the appropriate +language for what they need to create or express."[38] It is to enable students "to communicate in the +language of the twenty-first century."[39] +

+As with any language, this language comes more easily to some than to +others. It doesn't necessarily come more easily to those who excel in +written language. Daley and Stephanie Barish, director of the Institute for +Multimedia Literacy at the Annenberg Center, describe one particularly +poignant example of a project they ran in a high school. The high school +was a very poor inner-city Los Angeles school. In all the traditional +measures of success, this school was a failure. But Daley and Barish ran a +program that gave kids an opportunity to use film to express meaning about +something the students know something about—gun violence. +

+The class was held on Friday afternoons, and it created a relatively new +problem for the school. While the challenge in most classes was getting the +kids to come, the challenge in this class was keeping them away. The "kids +were showing up at 6 A.M. and leaving at 5 at night," said Barish. They were +working harder than in any other class to do what education should be +about—learning how to express themselves. +

+Using whatever "free web stuff they could find," and relatively simple tools +to enable the kids to mix "image, sound, and text," Barish said this class +produced a series of projects that showed something about gun violence that +few would otherwise understand. This was an issue close to the lives of +these students. The project "gave them a tool and empowered them to be able +to both understand it and talk about it," Barish explained. That tool +succeeded in creating expression—far more successfully and powerfully +than could have been created using only text. "If you had said to these +students, `you have to do it in text,' they would've just thrown their hands +up and gone and done something else," Barish described, in part, no doubt, +because expressing themselves in text is not something these students can do +well. Yet neither is text a form in which these ideas can be expressed +well. The power of this message depended upon its connection to this form of +expression. +

+ + + +"But isn't education about teaching kids to write?" I asked. In part, of +course, it is. But why are we teaching kids to write? Education, Daley +explained, is about giving students a way of "constructing meaning." To say +that that means just writing is like saying teaching writing is only about +teaching kids how to spell. Text is one part—and increasingly, not the +most powerful part—of constructing meaning. As Daley explained in the +most moving part of our interview, +

+What you want is to give these students ways of constructing meaning. If all +you give them is text, they're not going to do it. Because they can't. You +know, you've got Johnny who can look at a video, he can play a video game, +he can do graffiti all over your walls, he can take your car apart, and he +can do all sorts of other things. He just can't read your text. So Johnny +comes to school and you say, "Johnny, you're illiterate. Nothing you can do +matters." Well, Johnny then has two choices: He can dismiss you or he [can] +dismiss himself. If his ego is healthy at all, he's going to dismiss +you. [But i]nstead, if you say, "Well, with all these things that you can +do, let's talk about this issue. Play for me music that you think reflects +that, or show me images that you think reflect that, or draw for me +something that reflects that." Not by giving a kid a video camera and +. . . saying, "Let's go have fun with the video camera and make a little +movie." But instead, really help you take these elements that you +understand, that are your language, and construct meaning about the +topic. . . . +

+That empowers enormously. And then what happens, of course, is eventually, +as it has happened in all these classes, they bump up against the fact, "I +need to explain this and I really need to write something." And as one of +the teachers told Stephanie, they would rewrite a paragraph 5, 6, 7, 8 +times, till they got it right. +

+ +Because they needed to. There was a reason for doing it. They needed to say +something, as opposed to just jumping through your hoops. They actually +needed to use a language that they didn't speak very well. But they had come +to understand that they had a lot of power with this language." +

+When two planes crashed into the World Trade Center, another into the +Pentagon, and a fourth into a Pennsylvania field, all media around the world +shifted to this news. Every moment of just about every day for that week, +and for weeks after, television in particular, and media generally, retold +the story of the events we had just witnessed. The telling was a retelling, +because we had seen the events that were described. The genius of this awful +act of terrorism was that the delayed second attack was perfectly timed to +assure that the whole world would be watching. +

+These retellings had an increasingly familiar feel. There was music scored +for the intermissions, and fancy graphics that flashed across the +screen. There was a formula to interviews. There was "balance," and +seriousness. This was news choreographed in the way we have increasingly +come to expect it, "news as entertainment," even if the entertainment is +tragedy. +

+But in addition to this produced news about the "tragedy of September 11," +those of us tied to the Internet came to see a very different production as +well. The Internet was filled with accounts of the same events. Yet these +Internet accounts had a very different flavor. Some people constructed photo +pages that captured images from around the world and presented them as slide +shows with text. Some offered open letters. There were sound +recordings. There was anger and frustration. There were attempts to provide +context. There was, in short, an extraordinary worldwide barn raising, in +the sense Mike Godwin uses the term in his book Cyber Rights, around a news +event that had captured the attention of the world. There was ABC and CBS, +but there was also the Internet. +

+ +I don't mean simply to praise the Internet—though I do think the +people who supported this form of speech should be praised. I mean instead +to point to a significance in this form of speech. For like a Kodak, the +Internet enables people to capture images. And like in a movie by a student +on the "Just Think!" bus, the visual images could be mixed with sound or +text. +

+But unlike any technology for simply capturing images, the Internet allows +these creations to be shared with an extraordinary number of people, +practically instantaneously. This is something new in our +tradition—not just that culture can be captured mechanically, and +obviously not just that events are commented upon critically, but that this +mix of captured images, sound, and commentary can be widely spread +practically instantaneously. +

+September 11 was not an aberration. It was a beginning. Around the same +time, a form of communication that has grown dramatically was just beginning +to come into public consciousness: the Web-log, or blog. The blog is a kind +of public diary, and within some cultures, such as in Japan, it functions +very much like a diary. In those cultures, it records private facts in a +public way—it's a kind of electronic Jerry Springer, available +anywhere in the world. +

+But in the United States, blogs have taken on a very different character. +There are some who use the space simply to talk about their private +life. But there are many who use the space to engage in public +discourse. Discussing matters of public import, criticizing others who are +mistaken in their views, criticizing politicians about the decisions they +make, offering solutions to problems we all see: blogs create the sense of a +virtual public meeting, but one in which we don't all hope to be there at +the same time and in which conversations are not necessarily linked. The +best of the blog entries are relatively short; they point directly to words +used by others, criticizing with or adding to them. They are arguably the +most important form of unchoreographed public discourse that we have. +

+ +That's a strong statement. Yet it says as much about our democracy as it +does about blogs. This is the part of America that is most difficult for +those of us who love America to accept: Our democracy has atrophied. Of +course we have elections, and most of the time the courts allow those +elections to count. A relatively small number of people vote in those +elections. The cycle of these elections has become totally professionalized +and routinized. Most of us think this is democracy. +

+But democracy has never just been about elections. Democracy means rule by +the people, but rule means something more than mere elections. In our +tradition, it also means control through reasoned discourse. This was the +idea that captured the imagination of Alexis de Tocqueville, the +nineteenth-century French lawyer who wrote the most important account of +early "Democracy in America." It wasn't popular elections that fascinated +him—it was the jury, an institution that gave ordinary people the +right to choose life or death for other citizens. And most fascinating for +him was that the jury didn't just vote about the outcome they would +impose. They deliberated. Members argued about the "right" result; they +tried to persuade each other of the "right" result, and in criminal cases at +least, they had to agree upon a unanimous result for the process to come to +an end.[40] +

+Yet even this institution flags in American life today. And in its place, +there is no systematic effort to enable citizen deliberation. Some are +pushing to create just such an institution.[41] And in some towns in New England, something close to deliberation +remains. But for most of us for most of the time, there is no time or place +for "democratic deliberation" to occur. +

+More bizarrely, there is generally not even permission for it to occur. We, +the most powerful democracy in the world, have developed a strong norm +against talking about politics. It's fine to talk about politics with people +you agree with. But it is rude to argue about politics with people you +disagree with. Political discourse becomes isolated, and isolated discourse +becomes more extreme.[42] We say what our +friends want to hear, and hear very little beyond what our friends say. +

+ +Enter the blog. The blog's very architecture solves one part of this +problem. People post when they want to post, and people read when they want +to read. The most difficult time is synchronous time. Technologies that +enable asynchronous communication, such as e-mail, increase the opportunity +for communication. Blogs allow for public discourse without the public ever +needing to gather in a single public place. +

+But beyond architecture, blogs also have solved the problem of +norms. There's no norm (yet) in blog space not to talk about politics. +Indeed, the space is filled with political speech, on both the right and the +left. Some of the most popular sites are conservative or libertarian, but +there are many of all political stripes. And even blogs that are not +political cover political issues when the occasion merits. +

+The significance of these blogs is tiny now, though not so tiny. The name +Howard Dean may well have faded from the 2004 presidential race but for +blogs. Yet even if the number of readers is small, the reading is having an +effect. +

+One direct effect is on stories that had a different life cycle in the +mainstream media. The Trent Lott affair is an example. When Lott "misspoke" +at a party for Senator Strom Thurmond, essentially praising Thurmond's +segregationist policies, he calculated correctly that this story would +disappear from the mainstream press within forty-eight hours. It did. But he +didn't calculate its life cycle in blog space. The bloggers kept researching +the story. Over time, more and more instances of the same "misspeaking" +emerged. Finally, the story broke back into the mainstream press. In the +end, Lott was forced to resign as senate majority leader.[43] +

+This different cycle is possible because the same commercial pressures don't +exist with blogs as with other ventures. Television and newspapers are +commercial entities. They must work to keep attention. If they lose +readers, they lose revenue. Like sharks, they must move on. +

+But bloggers don't have a similar constraint. They can obsess, they can +focus, they can get serious. If a particular blogger writes a particularly +interesting story, more and more people link to that story. And as the +number of links to a particular story increases, it rises in the ranks of +stories. People read what is popular; what is popular has been selected by a +very democratic process of peer-generated rankings. +

+ +There's a second way, as well, in which blogs have a different cycle from +the mainstream press. As Dave Winer, one of the fathers of this movement and +a software author for many decades, told me, another difference is the +absence of a financial "conflict of interest." "I think you have to take the +conflict of interest" out of journalism, Winer told me. "An amateur +journalist simply doesn't have a conflict of interest, or the conflict of +interest is so easily disclosed that you know you can sort of get it out of +the way." +

+These conflicts become more important as media becomes more concentrated +(more on this below). A concentrated media can hide more from the public +than an unconcentrated media can—as CNN admitted it did after the Iraq +war because it was afraid of the consequences to its own +employees.[44] It also needs to sustain a +more coherent account. (In the middle of the Iraq war, I read a post on the +Internet from someone who was at that time listening to a satellite uplink +with a reporter in Iraq. The New York headquarters was telling the reporter +over and over that her account of the war was too bleak: She needed to offer +a more optimistic story. When she told New York that wasn't warranted, they +told her that they were writing "the story.") +

Blog space gives amateurs a way to enter the debate—"amateur" not in +the sense of inexperienced, but in the sense of an Olympic athlete, meaning +not paid by anyone to give their reports. It allows for a much broader range +of input into a story, as reporting on the Columbia disaster revealed, when +hundreds from across the southwest United States turned to the Internet to +retell what they had seen.[45] And it +drives readers to read across the range of accounts and "triangulate," as +Winer puts it, the truth. Blogs, Winer says, are "communicating directly +with our constituency, and the middle man is out of it"—with all the +benefits, and costs, that might entail. +

+ +Winer is optimistic about the future of journalism infected with +blogs. "It's going to become an essential skill," Winer predicts, for public +figures and increasingly for private figures as well. It's not clear that +"journalism" is happy about this—some journalists have been told to +curtail their blogging.[46] But it is clear +that we are still in transition. "A lot of what we are doing now is warm-up +exercises," Winer told me. There is a lot that must mature before this +space has its mature effect. And as the inclusion of content in this space +is the least infringing use of the Internet (meaning infringing on +copyright), Winer said, "we will be the last thing that gets shut down." +

+This speech affects democracy. Winer thinks that happens because "you don't +have to work for somebody who controls, [for] a gatekeeper." That is +true. But it affects democracy in another way as well. As more and more +citizens express what they think, and defend it in writing, that will change +the way people understand public issues. It is easy to be wrong and +misguided in your head. It is harder when the product of your mind can be +criticized by others. Of course, it is a rare human who admits that he has +been persuaded that he is wrong. But it is even rarer for a human to ignore +when he has been proven wrong. The writing of ideas, arguments, and +criticism improves democracy. Today there are probably a couple of million +blogs where such writing happens. When there are ten million, there will be +something extraordinary to report. +

+John Seely Brown is the chief scientist of the Xerox Corporation. His work, +as his Web site describes it, is "human learning and . . . the creation of +knowledge ecologies for creating . . . innovation." +

+Brown thus looks at these technologies of digital creativity a bit +differently from the perspectives I've sketched so far. I'm sure he would be +excited about any technology that might improve democracy. But his real +excitement comes from how these technologies affect learning. +

+ +As Brown believes, we learn by tinkering. When "a lot of us grew up," he +explains, that tinkering was done "on motorcycle engines, lawnmower engines, +automobiles, radios, and so on." But digital technologies enable a different +kind of tinkering—with abstract ideas though in concrete form. The +kids at Just Think! not only think about how a commercial portrays a +politician; using digital technology, they can take the commercial apart and +manipulate it, tinker with it to see how it does what it does. Digital +technologies launch a kind of bricolage, or "free collage," as Brown calls +it. Many get to add to or transform the tinkering of many others. +

+The best large-scale example of this kind of tinkering so far is free +software or open-source software (FS/OSS). FS/OSS is software whose source +code is shared. Anyone can download the technology that makes a FS/OSS +program run. And anyone eager to learn how a particular bit of FS/OSS +technology works can tinker with the code. +

+This opportunity creates a "completely new kind of learning platform," as +Brown describes. "As soon as you start doing that, you . . . unleash a free +collage on the community, so that other people can start looking at your +code, tinkering with it, trying it out, seeing if they can improve it." Each +effort is a kind of apprenticeship. "Open source becomes a major +apprenticeship platform." +

+In this process, "the concrete things you tinker with are abstract. They +are code." Kids are "shifting to the ability to tinker in the abstract, and +this tinkering is no longer an isolated activity that you're doing in your +garage. You are tinkering with a community platform. . . . You are +tinkering with other people's stuff. The more you tinker the more you +improve." The more you improve, the more you learn. +

+This same thing happens with content, too. And it happens in the same +collaborative way when that content is part of the Web. As Brown puts it, +"the Web [is] the first medium that truly honors multiple forms of +intelligence." Earlier technologies, such as the typewriter or word +processors, helped amplify text. But the Web amplifies much more than +text. "The Web . . . says if you are musical, if you are artistic, if you +are visual, if you are interested in film . . . [then] there is a lot you +can start to do on this medium. [It] can now amplify and honor these +multiple forms of intelligence." +

+ +Brown is talking about what Elizabeth Daley, Stephanie Barish, and Just +Think! teach: that this tinkering with culture teaches as well as +creates. It develops talents differently, and it builds a different kind of +recognition. +

+Yet the freedom to tinker with these objects is not guaranteed. Indeed, as +we'll see through the course of this book, that freedom is increasingly +highly contested. While there's no doubt that your father had the right to +tinker with the car engine, there's great doubt that your child will have +the right to tinker with the images she finds all around. The law and, +increasingly, technology interfere with a freedom that technology, and +curiosity, would otherwise ensure. +

+These restrictions have become the focus of researchers and scholars. +Professor Ed Felten of Princeton (whom we'll see more of in chapter 10) has +developed a powerful argument in favor of the "right to tinker" as it +applies to computer science and to knowledge in general.[47] But Brown's concern is earlier, or younger, or more +fundamental. It is about the learning that kids can do, or can't do, because +of the law. +

+"This is where education in the twenty-first century is going," Brown +explains. We need to "understand how kids who grow up digital think and want +to learn." +

+"Yet," as Brown continued, and as the balance of this book will evince, "we +are building a legal system that completely suppresses the natural +tendencies of today's digital kids. . . . We're building an architecture +that unleashes 60 percent of the brain [and] a legal system that closes down +that part of the brain." +

+We're building a technology that takes the magic of Kodak, mixes moving +images and sound, and adds a space for commentary and an opportunity to +spread that creativity everywhere. But we're building the law to close down +that technology. +

+"No way to run a culture," as Brewster Kahle, whom we'll meet in chapter 9, +quipped to me in a rare moment of despondence. +

Kapittel tre: Kataloger

+Høsten 2001, ble Jesse Jordan fra Oceanside, New York, innrullert som +førsteårsstudent ved Rensselaer Polytechnic Institute, i Troy, New York. +Hans studieprogram ved RPI var informasjonsteknologi. Selv om han ikke var +en programmerer, bestemte Jesse seg i oktober å begynne å fikle med en +søkemotorteknologi som var tilgjengelig på RPI-nettverket. +

+RPI is one of America's foremost technological research institutions. It +offers degrees in fields ranging from architecture and engineering to +information sciences. More than 65 percent of its five thousand +undergraduates finished in the top 10 percent of their high school +class. The school is thus a perfect mix of talent and experience to imagine +and then build, a generation for the network age. +

+RPI's computer network links students, faculty, and administration to one +another. It also links RPI to the Internet. Not everything available on the +RPI network is available on the Internet. But the network is designed to +enable students to get access to the Internet, as well as more intimate +access to other members of the RPI community. +

+ +Search engines are a measure of a network's intimacy. Google brought the +Internet much closer to all of us by fantastically improving the quality of +search on the network. Specialty search engines can do this even better. The +idea of "intranet" search engines, search engines that search within the +network of a particular institution, is to provide users of that institution +with better access to material from that institution. Businesses do this +all the time, enabling employees to have access to material that people +outside the business can't get. Universities do it as well. +

+These engines are enabled by the network technology itself. Microsoft, for +example, has a network file system that makes it very easy for search +engines tuned to that network to query the system for information about the +publicly (within that network) available content. Jesse's search engine was +built to take advantage of this technology. It used Microsoft's network file +system to build an index of all the files available within the RPI network. +

+Jesse's wasn't the first search engine built for the RPI network. Indeed, +his engine was a simple modification of engines that others had built. His +single most important improvement over those engines was to fix a bug within +the Microsoft file-sharing system that could cause a user's computer to +crash. With the engines that existed before, if you tried to access a file +through a Windows browser that was on a computer that was off-line, your +computer could crash. Jesse modified the system a bit to fix that problem, +by adding a button that a user could click to see if the machine holding the +file was still on-line. +

+Jesse's engine went on-line in late October. Over the following six months, +he continued to tweak it to improve its functionality. By March, the system +was functioning quite well. Jesse had more than one million files in his +directory, including every type of content that might be on users' +computers. +

+ +Thus the index his search engine produced included pictures, which students +could use to put on their own Web sites; copies of notes or research; copies +of information pamphlets; movie clips that students might have created; +university brochures—basically anything that users of the RPI network +made available in a public folder of their computer. +

+But the index also included music files. In fact, one quarter of the files +that Jesse's search engine listed were music files. But that means, of +course, that three quarters were not, and—so that this point is +absolutely clear—Jesse did nothing to induce people to put music files +in their public folders. He did nothing to target the search engine to these +files. He was a kid tinkering with a Google-like technology at a university +where he was studying information science, and hence, tinkering was the +aim. Unlike Google, or Microsoft, for that matter, he made no money from +this tinkering; he was not connected to any business that would make any +money from this experiment. He was a kid tinkering with technology in an +environment where tinkering with technology was precisely what he was +supposed to do. +

+On April 3, 2003, Jesse was contacted by the dean of students at RPI. The +dean informed Jesse that the Recording Industry Association of America, the +RIAA, would be filing a lawsuit against him and three other students whom he +didn't even know, two of them at other universities. A few hours later, +Jesse was served with papers from the suit. As he read these papers and +watched the news reports about them, he was increasingly astonished. +

+"It was absurd," he told me. "I don't think I did anything wrong. . . . I +don't think there's anything wrong with the search engine that I ran or +. . . what I had done to it. I mean, I hadn't modified it in any way that +promoted or enhanced the work of pirates. I just modified the search engine +in a way that would make it easier to use"—again, a search engine, +which Jesse had not himself built, using the Windows filesharing system, +which Jesse had not himself built, to enable members of the RPI community to +get access to content, which Jesse had not himself created or posted, and +the vast majority of which had nothing to do with music. +

+ +But the RIAA branded Jesse a pirate. They claimed he operated a network and +had therefore "willfully" violated copyright laws. They demanded that he pay +them the damages for his wrong. For cases of "willful infringement," the +Copyright Act specifies something lawyers call "statutory damages." These +damages permit a copyright owner to claim $150,000 per infringement. As the +RIAA alleged more than one hundred specific copyright infringements, they +therefore demanded that Jesse pay them at least $15,000,000. +

+Similar lawsuits were brought against three other students: one other +student at RPI, one at Michigan Technical University, and one at +Princeton. Their situations were similar to Jesse's. Though each case was +different in detail, the bottom line in each was exactly the same: huge +demands for "damages" that the RIAA claimed it was entitled to. If you +added up the claims, these four lawsuits were asking courts in the United +States to award the plaintiffs close to $100 billion—six times the +total profit of the film industry in 2001.[48] +

+Jesse called his parents. They were supportive but a bit frightened. An +uncle was a lawyer. He began negotiations with the RIAA. They demanded to +know how much money Jesse had. Jesse had saved $12,000 from summer jobs and +other employment. They demanded $12,000 to dismiss the case. +

+The RIAA wanted Jesse to admit to doing something wrong. He refused. They +wanted him to agree to an injunction that would essentially make it +impossible for him to work in many fields of technology for the rest of his +life. He refused. They made him understand that this process of being sued +was not going to be pleasant. (As Jesse's father recounted to me, the chief +lawyer on the case, Matt Oppenheimer, told Jesse, "You don't want to pay +another visit to a dentist like me.") And throughout, the RIAA insisted it +would not settle the case until it took every penny Jesse had saved. +

+ +Jesse's family was outraged at these claims. They wanted to fight. But +Jesse's uncle worked to educate the family about the nature of the American +legal system. Jesse could fight the RIAA. He might even win. But the cost of +fighting a lawsuit like this, Jesse was told, would be at least $250,000. If +he won, he would not recover that money. If he won, he would have a piece of +paper saying he had won, and a piece of paper saying he and his family were +bankrupt. +

+Så Jesse hadde et mafia-lignende valg: $250,000 og en sjanse til å vinne, +eller $12.000 og et forlik. +

+The recording industry insists this is a matter of law and morality. Let's +put the law aside for a moment and think about the morality. Where is the +morality in a lawsuit like this? What is the virtue in scapegoatism? The +RIAA is an extraordinarily powerful lobby. The president of the RIAA is +reported to make more than $1 million a year. Artists, on the other hand, +are not well paid. The average recording artist makes $45,900.[49] There are plenty of ways for the RIAA to affect and +direct policy. So where is the morality in taking money from a student for +running a search engine?[50] +

+23. juni overførte Jesse alle sine oppsparte midler til advokaten som jobbet +for RIA. Saken mot ham ble trukket. Og med dette, ble unggutten som hadde +fiklet med en datamaskin og blitt saksøkt for 15 millioner dollar en +aktivist: +

+I was definitely not an activist [before]. I never really meant to be an +activist. . . . [But] I've been pushed into this. In no way did I ever +foresee anything like this, but I think it's just completely absurd what the +RIAA has done. +

+Jesse's parents betray a certain pride in their reluctant activist. As his +father told me, Jesse "considers himself very conservative, and so do +I. . . . He's not a tree hugger. . . . I think it's bizarre that they would +pick on him. But he wants to let people know that they're sending the wrong +message. And he wants to correct the record." +

Kapittel fire: "Pirater"

+If "piracy" means using the creative property of others without their +permission—if "if value, then right" is true—then the history of +the content industry is a history of piracy. Every important sector of "big +media" today—film, records, radio, and cable TV—was born of a +kind of piracy so defined. The consistent story is how last generation's +pirates join this generation's country club—until now. +

Film

+ +The film industry of Hollywood was built by fleeing pirates.[51] Creators and directors migrated from the East Coast +to California in the early twentieth century in part to escape controls that +patents granted the inventor of filmmaking, Thomas Edison. These controls +were exercised through a monopoly "trust," the Motion Pictures Patents +Company, and were based on Thomas Edison's creative property—patents. +Edison formed the MPPC to exercise the rights this creative property gave +him, and the MPPC was serious about the control it demanded. +

+As one commentator tells one part of the story, +

+A January 1909 deadline was set for all companies to comply with the +license. By February, unlicensed outlaws, who referred to themselves as +independents protested the trust and carried on business without submitting +to the Edison monopoly. In the summer of 1909 the independent movement was +in full-swing, with producers and theater owners using illegal equipment and +imported film stock to create their own underground market. +

+With the country experiencing a tremendous expansion in the number of +nickelodeons, the Patents Company reacted to the independent movement by +forming a strong-arm subsidiary known as the General Film Company to block +the entry of non-licensed independents. With coercive tactics that have +become legendary, General Film confiscated unlicensed equipment, +discontinued product supply to theaters which showed unlicensed films, and +effectively monopolized distribution with the acquisition of all U.S. film +exchanges, except for the one owned by the independent William Fox who +defied the Trust even after his license was revoked.[52] +

+The Napsters of those days, the "independents," were companies like Fox. And +no less than today, these independents were vigorously resisted. "Shooting +was disrupted by machinery stolen, and `accidents' resulting in loss of +negatives, equipment, buildings and sometimes life and limb frequently +occurred."[53] That led the independents to +flee the East Coast. California was remote enough from Edison's reach that +filmmakers there could pirate his inventions without fear of the law. And +the leaders of Hollywood filmmaking, Fox most prominently, did just that. +

+ +Of course, California grew quickly, and the effective enforcement of federal +law eventually spread west. But because patents grant the patent holder a +truly "limited" monopoly (just seventeen years at that time), by the time +enough federal marshals appeared, the patents had expired. A new industry +had been born, in part from the piracy of Edison's creative property. +

Innspilt musikk

+Plateindustrien ble født av en annen type piratvirksomhet, dog for å forstå +hvordan krever at en setter seg inn i detaljer om hvordan loven regulerer +musikk. +

+At the time that Edison and Henri Fourneaux invented machines for +reproducing music (Edison the phonograph, Fourneaux the player piano), the +law gave composers the exclusive right to control copies of their music and +the exclusive right to control public performances of their music. In other +words, in 1900, if I wanted a copy of Phil Russel's 1899 hit "Happy Mose," +the law said I would have to pay for the right to get a copy of the musical +score, and I would also have to pay for the right to perform it publicly. +

+But what if I wanted to record "Happy Mose," using Edison's phonograph or +Fourneaux's player piano? Here the law stumbled. It was clear enough that I +would have to buy any copy of the musical score that I performed in making +this recording. And it was clear enough that I would have to pay for any +public performance of the work I was recording. But it wasn't totally clear +that I would have to pay for a "public performance" if I recorded the song +in my own house (even today, you don't owe the Beatles anything if you sing +their songs in the shower), or if I recorded the song from memory (copies in +your brain are not—yet— regulated by copyright law). So if I +simply sang the song into a recording device in the privacy of my own home, +it wasn't clear that I owed the composer anything. And more importantly, it +wasn't clear whether I owed the composer anything if I then made copies of +those recordings. Because of this gap in the law, then, I could effectively +pirate someone else's song without paying its composer anything. +

+ +The composers (and publishers) were none too happy about this capacity to +pirate. As South Dakota senator Alfred Kittredge put it, +

+Imagine the injustice of the thing. A composer writes a song or an opera. A +publisher buys at great expense the rights to the same and copyrights +it. Along come the phonographic companies and companies who cut music rolls +and deliberately steal the work of the brain of the composer and publisher +without any regard for [their] rights.[54] +

+The innovators who developed the technology to record other people's works +were "sponging upon the toil, the work, the talent, and genius of American +composers,"[55] and the "music publishing +industry" was thereby "at the complete mercy of this one +pirate."[56] As John Philip Sousa put it, +in as direct a way as possible, "When they make money out of my pieces, I +want a share of it."[57] +

+These arguments have familiar echoes in the wars of our day. So, too, do the +arguments on the other side. The innovators who developed the player piano +argued that "it is perfectly demonstrable that the introduction of automatic +music players has not deprived any composer of anything he had before their +introduction." Rather, the machines increased the sales of sheet +music.[58] In any case, the innovators +argued, the job of Congress was "to consider first the interest of [the +public], whom they represent, and whose servants they are." "All talk about +`theft,'" the general counsel of the American Graphophone Company wrote, "is +the merest claptrap, for there exists no property in ideas musical, literary +or artistic, except as defined by statute."[59] +

+ +The law soon resolved this battle in favor of the composer and the recording +artist. Congress amended the law to make sure that composers would be paid +for the "mechanical reproductions" of their music. But rather than simply +granting the composer complete control over the right to make mechanical +reproductions, Congress gave recording artists a right to record the music, +at a price set by Congress, once the composer allowed it to be recorded +once. This is the part of copyright law that makes cover songs +possible. Once a composer authorizes a recording of his song, others are +free to record the same song, so long as they pay the original composer a +fee set by the law. +

+American law ordinarily calls this a "compulsory license," but I will refer +to it as a "statutory license." A statutory license is a license whose key +terms are set by law. After Congress's amendment of the Copyright Act in +1909, record companies were free to distribute copies of recordings so long +as they paid the composer (or copyright holder) the fee set by the statute. +

+This is an exception within the law of copyright. When John Grisham writes a +novel, a publisher is free to publish that novel only if Grisham gives the +publisher permission. Grisham, in turn, is free to charge whatever he wants +for that permission. The price to publish Grisham is thus set by Grisham, +and copyright law ordinarily says you have no permission to use Grisham's +work except with permission of Grisham. +

+But the law governing recordings gives recording artists less. And thus, in +effect, the law subsidizes the recording industry through a kind of +piracy—by giving recording artists a weaker right than it otherwise +gives creative authors. The Beatles have less control over their creative +work than Grisham does. And the beneficiaries of this less control are the +recording industry and the public. The recording industry gets something of +value for less than it otherwise would pay; the public gets access to a much +wider range of musical creativity. Indeed, Congress was quite explicit about +its reasons for granting this right. Its fear was the monopoly power of +rights holders, and that that power would stifle follow-on +creativity.[60] +

+While the recording industry has been quite coy about this recently, +historically it has been quite a supporter of the statutory license for +records. As a 1967 report from the House Committee on the Judiciary relates, +

+the record producers argued vigorously that the compulsory license system +must be retained. They asserted that the record industry is a +half-billion-dollar business of great economic importance in the United +States and throughout the world; records today are the principal means of +disseminating music, and this creates special problems, since performers +need unhampered access to musical material on nondiscriminatory +terms. Historically, the record producers pointed out, there were no +recording rights before 1909 and the 1909 statute adopted the compulsory +license as a deliberate anti-monopoly condition on the grant of these +rights. They argue that the result has been an outpouring of recorded music, +with the public being given lower prices, improved quality, and a greater +choice.[61] +

+By limiting the rights musicians have, by partially pirating their creative +work, the record producers, and the public, benefit. +

Radio

+Radio was also born of piracy. +

+When a radio station plays a record on the air, that constitutes a "public +performance" of the composer's work.[62] As +I described above, the law gives the composer (or copyright holder) an +exclusive right to public performances of his work. The radio station thus +owes the composer money for that performance. +

+ +But when the radio station plays a record, it is not only performing a copy +of the composer's work. The radio station is also performing a copy of the +recording artist's work. It's one thing to have "Happy Birthday" sung on the +radio by the local children's choir; it's quite another to have it sung by +the Rolling Stones or Lyle Lovett. The recording artist is adding to the +value of the composition performed on the radio station. And if the law +were perfectly consistent, the radio station would have to pay the recording +artist for his work, just as it pays the composer of the music for his +work. + + +

+But it doesn't. Under the law governing radio performances, the radio +station does not have to pay the recording artist. The radio station need +only pay the composer. The radio station thus gets a bit of something for +nothing. It gets to perform the recording artist's work for free, even if it +must pay the composer something for the privilege of playing the song. +

+This difference can be huge. Imagine you compose a piece of music. Imagine +it is your first. You own the exclusive right to authorize public +performances of that music. So if Madonna wants to sing your song in public, +she has to get your permission. +

+Imagine she does sing your song, and imagine she likes it a lot. She then +decides to make a recording of your song, and it becomes a top hit. Under +our law, every time a radio station plays your song, you get some money. But +Madonna gets nothing, save the indirect effect on the sale of her CDs. The +public performance of her recording is not a "protected" right. The radio +station thus gets to pirate the value of Madonna's work without paying her +anything. +

+No doubt, one might argue that, on balance, the recording artists +benefit. On average, the promotion they get is worth more than the +performance rights they give up. Maybe. But even if so, the law ordinarily +gives the creator the right to make this choice. By making the choice for +him or her, the law gives the radio station the right to take something for +nothing. +

Kabel-TV

+ +Cable TV was also born of a kind of piracy. +

+ +When cable entrepreneurs first started wiring communities with cable +television in 1948, most refused to pay broadcasters for the content that +they echoed to their customers. Even when the cable companies started +selling access to television broadcasts, they refused to pay for what they +sold. Cable companies were thus Napsterizing broadcasters' content, but more +egregiously than anything Napster ever did— Napster never charged for +the content it enabled others to give away. +

+Broadcasters and copyright owners were quick to attack this theft. Rosel +Hyde, chairman of the FCC, viewed the practice as a kind of "unfair and +potentially destructive competition."[63] +There may have been a "public interest" in spreading the reach of cable TV, +but as Douglas Anello, general counsel to the National Association of +Broadcasters, asked Senator Quentin Burdick during testimony, "Does public +interest dictate that you use somebody else's property?"[64] As another broadcaster put it, +

+The extraordinary thing about the CATV business is that it is the only +business I know of where the product that is being sold is not paid +for.[65] +

+Again, the demand of the copyright holders seemed reasonable enough: +

+All we are asking for is a very simple thing, that people who now take our +property for nothing pay for it. We are trying to stop piracy and I don't +think there is any lesser word to describe it. I think there are harsher +words which would fit it.[66] +

+Disse var "gratispassasjerer", sa presidenten Charlton Heston i Screen +Actor's Guild, som "tok lønna fra skuespillerne"[67] +

+Men igjen, det er en annen side i debatten. Som assisterende justisminister +Edwin Zimmerman sa det, +

+Our point here is that unlike the problem of whether you have any copyright +protection at all, the problem here is whether copyright holders who are +already compensated, who already have a monopoly, should be permitted to +extend that monopoly. . . . The question here is how much compensation they +should have and how far back they should carry their right to +compensation.[68] +

+Opphavsrettinnehaverne tok kabelselskapene til retten. Høyesterett fant to +ganger at kabelselskaper ikke skyldte opphavsrettinnehaverne noen ting. +

+It took Congress almost thirty years before it resolved the question of +whether cable companies had to pay for the content they "pirated." In the +end, Congress resolved this question in the same way that it resolved the +question about record players and player pianos. Yes, cable companies would +have to pay for the content that they broadcast; but the price they would +have to pay was not set by the copyright owner. The price was set by law, +so that the broadcasters couldn't exercise veto power over the emerging +technologies of cable. Cable companies thus built their empire in part upon +a "piracy" of the value created by broadcasters' content. +

+These separate stories sing a common theme. If "piracy" means using value +from someone else's creative property without permission from that +creator—as it is increasingly described today[69] — then every industry affected by copyright +today is the product and beneficiary of a certain kind of piracy. Film, +records, radio, cable TV. . . . The list is long and could well be +expanded. Every generation welcomes the pirates from the last. Every +generation—until now. +

Kapittel fem: "Piratvirksomhet"

+There is piracy of copyrighted material. Lots of it. This piracy comes in +many forms. The most significant is commercial piracy, the unauthorized +taking of other people's content within a commercial context. Despite the +many justifications that are offered in its defense, this taking is +wrong. No one should condone it, and the law should stop it. +

+ +But as well as copy-shop piracy, there is another kind of "taking" that is +more directly related to the Internet. That taking, too, seems wrong to +many, and it is wrong much of the time. Before we paint this taking +"piracy," however, we should understand its nature a bit more. For the harm +of this taking is significantly more ambiguous than outright copying, and +the law should account for that ambiguity, as it has so often done in the +past. + +

Piracy I

+All across the world, but especially in Asia and Eastern Europe, there are +businesses that do nothing but take others people's copyrighted content, +copy it, and sell it—all without the permission of a copyright +owner. The recording industry estimates that it loses about $4.6 billion +every year to physical piracy[70] (that +works out to one in three CDs sold worldwide). The MPAA estimates that it +loses $3 billion annually worldwide to piracy. +

+This is piracy plain and simple. Nothing in the argument of this book, nor +in the argument that most people make when talking about the subject of this +book, should draw into doubt this simple point: This piracy is wrong. +

+Which is not to say that excuses and justifications couldn't be made for +it. We could, for example, remind ourselves that for the first one hundred +years of the American Republic, America did not honor foreign copyrights. We +were born, in this sense, a pirate nation. It might therefore seem +hypocritical for us to insist so strongly that other developing nations +treat as wrong what we, for the first hundred years of our existence, +treated as right. +

+That excuse isn't terribly strong. Technically, our law did not ban the +taking of foreign works. It explicitly limited itself to American +works. Thus the American publishers who published foreign works without the +permission of foreign authors were not violating any rule. The copy shops +in Asia, by contrast, are violating Asian law. Asian law does protect +foreign copyrights, and the actions of the copy shops violate that law. So +the wrong of piracy that they engage in is not just a moral wrong, but a +legal wrong, and not just an internationally legal wrong, but a locally +legal wrong as well. +

+ +True, these local rules have, in effect, been imposed upon these +countries. No country can be part of the world economy and choose not to +protect copyright internationally. We may have been born a pirate nation, +but we will not allow any other nation to have a similar childhood. +

+If a country is to be treated as a sovereign, however, then its laws are its +laws regardless of their source. The international law under which these +nations live gives them some opportunities to escape the burden of +intellectual property law.[71] In my view, +more developing nations should take advantage of that opportunity, but when +they don't, then their laws should be respected. And under the laws of these +nations, this piracy is wrong. +

+Alternatively, we could try to excuse this piracy by noting that in any +case, it does no harm to the industry. The Chinese who get access to +American CDs at 50 cents a copy are not people who would have bought those +American CDs at $15 a copy. So no one really has any less money than they +otherwise would have had.[72] +

+This is often true (though I have friends who have purchased many thousands +of pirated DVDs who certainly have enough money to pay for the content they +have taken), and it does mitigate to some degree the harm caused by such +taking. Extremists in this debate love to say, "You wouldn't go into Barnes +& Noble and take a book off of the shelf without paying; why should it +be any different with on-line music?" The difference is, of course, that +when you take a book from Barnes & Noble, it has one less book to +sell. By contrast, when you take an MP3 from a computer network, there is +not one less CD that can be sold. The physics of piracy of the intangible +are different from the physics of piracy of the tangible. +

+ +This argument is still very weak. However, although copyright is a property +right of a very special sort, it is a property right. Like all property +rights, the copyright gives the owner the right to decide the terms under +which content is shared. If the copyright owner doesn't want to sell, she +doesn't have to. There are exceptions: important statutory licenses that +apply to copyrighted content regardless of the wish of the copyright +owner. Those licenses give people the right to "take" copyrighted content +whether or not the copyright owner wants to sell. But where the law does not +give people the right to take content, it is wrong to take that content even +if the wrong does no harm. If we have a property system, and that system is +properly balanced to the technology of a time, then it is wrong to take +property without the permission of a property owner. That is exactly what +"property" means. +

+Finally, we could try to excuse this piracy with the argument that the +piracy actually helps the copyright owner. When the Chinese "steal" Windows, +that makes the Chinese dependent on Microsoft. Microsoft loses the value of +the software that was taken. But it gains users who are used to life in the +Microsoft world. Over time, as the nation grows more wealthy, more and more +people will buy software rather than steal it. And hence over time, because +that buying will benefit Microsoft, Microsoft benefits from the piracy. If +instead of pirating Microsoft Windows, the Chinese used the free GNU/Linux +operating system, then these Chinese users would not eventually be buying +Microsoft. Without piracy, then, Microsoft would lose. +

+This argument, too, is somewhat true. The addiction strategy is a good +one. Many businesses practice it. Some thrive because of it. Law students, +for example, are given free access to the two largest legal databases. The +companies marketing both hope the students will become so used to their +service that they will want to use it and not the other when they become +lawyers (and must pay high subscription fees). +

+Still, the argument is not terribly persuasive. We don't give the alcoholic +a defense when he steals his first beer, merely because that will make it +more likely that he will buy the next three. Instead, we ordinarily allow +businesses to decide for themselves when it is best to give their product +away. If Microsoft fears the competition of GNU/Linux, then Microsoft can +give its product away, as it did, for example, with Internet Explorer to +fight Netscape. A property right means giving the property owner the right +to say who gets access to what—at least ordinarily. And if the law +properly balances the rights of the copyright owner with the rights of +access, then violating the law is still wrong. +

+ + +Thus, while I understand the pull of these justifications for piracy, and I +certainly see the motivation, in my view, in the end, these efforts at +justifying commercial piracy simply don't cut it. This kind of piracy is +rampant and just plain wrong. It doesn't transform the content it steals; it +doesn't transform the market it competes in. It merely gives someone access +to something that the law says he should not have. Nothing has changed to +draw that law into doubt. This form of piracy is flat out wrong. +

+But as the examples from the four chapters that introduced this part +suggest, even if some piracy is plainly wrong, not all "piracy" is. Or at +least, not all "piracy" is wrong if that term is understood in the way it is +increasingly used today. Many kinds of "piracy" are useful and productive, +to produce either new content or new ways of doing business. Neither our +tradition nor any tradition has ever banned all "piracy" in that sense of +the term. +

+This doesn't mean that there are no questions raised by the latest piracy +concern, peer-to-peer file sharing. But it does mean that we need to +understand the harm in peer-to-peer sharing a bit more before we condemn it +to the gallows with the charge of piracy. +

+For (1) like the original Hollywood, p2p sharing escapes an overly +controlling industry; and (2) like the original recording industry, it +simply exploits a new way to distribute content; but (3) unlike cable TV, no +one is selling the content that is shared on p2p services. +

+These differences distinguish p2p sharing from true piracy. They should push +us to find a way to protect artists while enabling this sharing to survive. +

Piracy II

+ +The key to the "piracy" that the law aims to quash is a use that "rob[s] the +author of [his] profit."[73] This means we +must determine whether and how much p2p sharing harms before we know how +strongly the law should seek to either prevent it or find an alternative to +assure the author of his profit. +

+Peer-to-peer sharing was made famous by Napster. But the inventors of the +Napster technology had not made any major technological innovations. Like +every great advance in innovation on the Internet (and, arguably, off the +Internet as well[74]), Shawn Fanning and +crew had simply put together components that had been developed +independently. +

+The result was spontaneous combustion. Launched in July 1999, Napster +amassed over 10 million users within nine months. After eighteen months, +there were close to 80 million registered users of the system.[75] Courts quickly shut Napster down, but other +services emerged to take its place. (Kazaa is currently the most popular p2p +service. It boasts over 100 million members.) These services' systems are +different architecturally, though not very different in function: Each +enables users to make content available to any number of other users. With a +p2p system, you can share your favorite songs with your best friend— +or your 20,000 best friends. +

+According to a number of estimates, a huge proportion of Americans have +tasted file-sharing technology. A study by Ipsos-Insight in September 2002 +estimated that 60 million Americans had downloaded music—28 percent of +Americans older than 12.[76] A survey by +the NPD group quoted in The New York Times estimated that 43 million +citizens used file-sharing networks to exchange content in May +2003.[77] The vast majority of these are +not kids. Whatever the actual figure, a massive quantity of content is being +"taken" on these networks. The ease and inexpensiveness of file-sharing +networks have inspired millions to enjoy music in a way that they hadn't +before. +

+Some of this enjoying involves copyright infringement. Some of it does +not. And even among the part that is technically copyright infringement, +calculating the actual harm to copyright owners is more complicated than one +might think. So consider—a bit more carefully than the polarized +voices around this debate usually do—the kinds of sharing that file +sharing enables, and the kinds of harm it entails. +

+ + +Fildelerne deler ulike typer innhold. Vi kan derel disse ulike typene inn i +fire typer. +

  1. + +There are some who use sharing networks as substitutes for purchasing +content. Thus, when a new Madonna CD is released, rather than buying the CD, +these users simply take it. We might quibble about whether everyone who +takes it would actually have bought it if sharing didn't make it available +for free. Most probably wouldn't have, but clearly there are some who +would. The latter are the target of category A: users who download instead +of purchasing. +

  2. + + +There are some who use sharing networks to sample music before purchasing +it. Thus, a friend sends another friend an MP3 of an artist he's not heard +of. The other friend then buys CDs by that artist. This is a kind of +targeted advertising, quite likely to succeed. If the friend recommending +the album gains nothing from a bad recommendation, then one could expect +that the recommendations will actually be quite good. The net effect of this +sharing could increase the quantity of music purchased. +

  3. + + +There are many who use sharing networks to get access to copyrighted content +that is no longer sold or that they would not have purchased because the +transaction costs off the Net are too high. This use of sharing networks is +among the most rewarding for many. Songs that were part of your childhood +but have long vanished from the marketplace magically appear again on the +network. (One friend told me that when she discovered Napster, she spent a +solid weekend "recalling" old songs. She was astonished at the range and mix +of content that was available.) For content not sold, this is still +technically a violation of copyright, though because the copyright owner is +not selling the content anymore, the economic harm is zero—the same +harm that occurs when I sell my collection of 1960s 45-rpm records to a +local collector. +

  4. + + + + +Finally, there are many who use sharing networks to get access to content +that is not copyrighted or that the copyright owner wants to give away. +

+Hvordan balanserer disse ulike delingstypene? +

+Let's start with some simple but important points. From the perspective of +the law, only type D sharing is clearly legal. From the perspective of +economics, only type A sharing is clearly harmful.[78] Type B sharing is illegal but plainly +beneficial. Type C sharing is illegal, yet good for society (since more +exposure to music is good) and harmless to the artist (since the work is +not otherwise available). So how sharing matters on balance is a hard +question to answer—and certainly much more difficult than the current +rhetoric around the issue suggests. +

+Whether on balance sharing is harmful depends importantly on how harmful +type A sharing is. Just as Edison complained about Hollywood, composers +complained about piano rolls, recording artists complained about radio, and +broadcasters complained about cable TV, the music industry complains that +type A sharing is a kind of "theft" that is "devastating" the industry. +

+While the numbers do suggest that sharing is harmful, how harmful is harder +to reckon. It has long been the recording industry's practice to blame +technology for any drop in sales. The history of cassette recording is a +good example. As a study by Cap Gemini Ernst & Young put it, "Rather +than exploiting this new, popular technology, the labels fought +it."[79] The labels claimed that every +album taped was an album unsold, and when record sales fell by 11.4 percent +in 1981, the industry claimed that its point was proved. Technology was the +problem, and banning or regulating technology was the answer. +

+Yet soon thereafter, and before Congress was given an opportunity to enact +regulation, MTV was launched, and the industry had a record turnaround. "In +the end," Cap Gemini concludes, "the `crisis' . . . was not the fault of the +tapers—who did not [stop after MTV came into being]—but had to a +large extent resulted from stagnation in musical innovation at the major +labels."[80] +

+But just because the industry was wrong before does not mean it is wrong +today. To evaluate the real threat that p2p sharing presents to the industry +in particular, and society in general—or at least the society that +inherits the tradition that gave us the film industry, the record industry, +the radio industry, cable TV, and the VCR—the question is not simply +whether type A sharing is harmful. The question is also how harmful type A +sharing is, and how beneficial the other types of sharing are. +

+We start to answer this question by focusing on the net harm, from the +standpoint of the industry as a whole, that sharing networks cause. The +"net harm" to the industry as a whole is the amount by which type A sharing +exceeds type B. If the record companies sold more records through sampling +than they lost through substitution, then sharing networks would actually +benefit music companies on balance. They would therefore have little static +reason to resist them. +

+Could that be true? Could the industry as a whole be gaining because of file +sharing? Odd as that might sound, the data about CD sales actually suggest +it might be close. +

+In 2002, the RIAA reported that CD sales had fallen by 8.9 percent, from 882 +million to 803 million units; revenues fell 6.7 percent.[81] This confirms a trend over the past few years. The +RIAA blames Internet piracy for the trend, though there are many other +causes that could account for this drop. SoundScan, for example, reports a +more than 20 percent drop in the number of CDs released since 1999. That no +doubt accounts for some of the decrease in sales. Rising prices could +account for at least some of the loss. "From 1999 to 2001, the average price +of a CD rose 7.2 percent, from $13.04 to $14.19."[82] Competition from other forms of media could also +account for some of the decline. As Jane Black of BusinessWeek notes, "The +soundtrack to the film High Fidelity has a list price of $18.98. You could +get the whole movie [on DVD] for $19.99."[83] +

+ + + +But let's assume the RIAA is right, and all of the decline in CD sales is +because of Internet sharing. Here's the rub: In the same period that the +RIAA estimates that 803 million CDs were sold, the RIAA estimates that 2.1 +billion CDs were downloaded for free. Thus, although 2.6 times the total +number of CDs sold were downloaded for free, sales revenue fell by just 6.7 +percent. +

+There are too many different things happening at the same time to explain +these numbers definitively, but one conclusion is unavoidable: The recording +industry constantly asks, "What's the difference between downloading a song +and stealing a CD?"—but their own numbers reveal the difference. If I +steal a CD, then there is one less CD to sell. Every taking is a lost +sale. But on the basis of the numbers the RIAA provides, it is absolutely +clear that the same is not true of downloads. If every download were a lost +sale—if every use of Kazaa "rob[bed] the author of [his] +profit"—then the industry would have suffered a 100 percent drop in +sales last year, not a 7 percent drop. If 2.6 times the number of CDs sold +were downloaded for free, and yet sales revenue dropped by just 6.7 percent, +then there is a huge difference between "downloading a song and stealing a +CD." +

+These are the harms—alleged and perhaps exaggerated but, let's assume, +real. What of the benefits? File sharing may impose costs on the recording +industry. What value does it produce in addition to these costs? +

+One benefit is type C sharing—making available content that is +technically still under copyright but is no longer commercially available. +This is not a small category of content. There are millions of tracks that +are no longer commercially available.[84] +And while it's conceivable that some of this content is not available +because the artist producing the content doesn't want it to be made +available, the vast majority of it is unavailable solely because the +publisher or the distributor has decided it no longer makes economic sense +to the company to make it available. +

+In real space—long before the Internet—the market had a simple +response to this problem: used book and record stores. There are thousands +of used book and used record stores in America today.[85] These stores buy content from owners, then sell the +content they buy. And under American copyright law, when they buy and sell +this content, even if the content is still under copyright, the copyright +owner doesn't get a dime. Used book and record stores are commercial +entities; their owners make money from the content they sell; but as with +cable companies before statutory licensing, they don't have to pay the +copyright owner for the content they sell. +

+Type C sharing, then, is very much like used book stores or used record +stores. It is different, of course, because the person making the content +available isn't making money from making the content available. It is also +different, of course, because in real space, when I sell a record, I don't +have it anymore, while in cyberspace, when someone shares my 1949 recording +of Bernstein's "Two Love Songs," I still have it. That difference would +matter economically if the owner of the copyright were selling the record in +competition to my sharing. But we're talking about the class of content that +is not currently commercially available. The Internet is making it +available, through cooperative sharing, without competing with the market. +

+It may well be, all things considered, that it would be better if the +copyright owner got something from this trade. But just because it may well +be better, it doesn't follow that it would be good to ban used book +stores. Or put differently, if you think that type C sharing should be +stopped, do you think that libraries and used book stores should be shut as +well? +

+ +Finally, and perhaps most importantly, file-sharing networks enable type D +sharing to occur—the sharing of content that copyright owners want to +have shared or for which there is no continuing copyright. This sharing +clearly benefits authors and society. Science fiction author Cory Doctorow, +for example, released his first novel, Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom, +both free on-line and in bookstores on the same day. His (and his +publisher's) thinking was that the on-line distribution would be a great +advertisement for the "real" book. People would read part on-line, and then +decide whether they liked the book or not. If they liked it, they would be +more likely to buy it. Doctorow's content is type D content. If sharing +networks enable his work to be spread, then both he and society are better +off. (Actually, much better off: It is a great book!) +

+Likewise for work in the public domain: This sharing benefits society with +no legal harm to authors at all. If efforts to solve the problem of type A +sharing destroy the opportunity for type D sharing, then we lose something +important in order to protect type A content. +

+The point throughout is this: While the recording industry understandably +says, "This is how much we've lost," we must also ask, "How much has society +gained from p2p sharing? What are the efficiencies? What is the content that +otherwise would be unavailable?" +

+For unlike the piracy I described in the first section of this chapter, much +of the "piracy" that file sharing enables is plainly legal and good. And +like the piracy I described in chapter 4, much of this piracy is motivated +by a new way of spreading content caused by changes in the technology of +distribution. Thus, consistent with the tradition that gave us Hollywood, +radio, the recording industry, and cable TV, the question we should be +asking about file sharing is how best to preserve its benefits while +minimizing (to the extent possible) the wrongful harm it causes artists. The +question is one of balance. The law should seek that balance, and that +balance will be found only with time. +

+Men er ikke krigen bare en krig mot ulovlig deling? Er ikke angrepsmålet +bare det du kaller type A-deling? +

+You would think. And we should hope. But so far, it is not. The effect of +the war purportedly on type A sharing alone has been felt far beyond that +one class of sharing. That much is obvious from the Napster case +itself. When Napster told the district court that it had developed a +technology to block the transfer of 99.4 percent of identified infringing +material, the district court told counsel for Napster 99.4 percent was not +good enough. Napster had to push the infringements "down to +zero."[86] +

+If 99.4 percent is not good enough, then this is a war on file-sharing +technologies, not a war on copyright infringement. There is no way to assure +that a p2p system is used 100 percent of the time in compliance with the +law, any more than there is a way to assure that 100 percent of VCRs or 100 +percent of Xerox machines or 100 percent of handguns are used in compliance +with the law. Zero tolerance means zero p2p. The court's ruling means that +we as a society must lose the benefits of p2p, even for the totally legal +and beneficial uses they serve, simply to assure that there are zero +copyright infringements caused by p2p. +

+Zero tolerance has not been our history. It has not produced the content +industry that we know today. The history of American law has been a process +of balance. As new technologies changed the way content was distributed, the +law adjusted, after some time, to the new technology. In this adjustment, +the law sought to ensure the legitimate rights of creators while protecting +innovation. Sometimes this has meant more rights for creators. Sometimes +less. +

+So, as we've seen, when "mechanical reproduction" threatened the interests +of composers, Congress balanced the rights of composers against the +interests of the recording industry. It granted rights to composers, but +also to the recording artists: Composers were to be paid, but at a price set +by Congress. But when radio started broadcasting the recordings made by +these recording artists, and they complained to Congress that their +"creative property" was not being respected (since the radio station did not +have to pay them for the creativity it broadcast), Congress rejected their +claim. An indirect benefit was enough. +

+Cable TV followed the pattern of record albums. When the courts rejected the +claim that cable broadcasters had to pay for the content they rebroadcast, +Congress responded by giving broadcasters a right to compensation, but at a +level set by the law. It likewise gave cable companies the right to the +content, so long as they paid the statutory price. +

+ + + +This compromise, like the compromise affecting records and player pianos, +served two important goals—indeed, the two central goals of any +copyright legislation. First, the law assured that new innovators would have +the freedom to develop new ways to deliver content. Second, the law assured +that copyright holders would be paid for the content that was +distributed. One fear was that if Congress simply required cable TV to pay +copyright holders whatever they demanded for their content, then copyright +holders associated with broadcasters would use their power to stifle this +new technology, cable. But if Congress had permitted cable to use +broadcasters' content for free, then it would have unfairly subsidized +cable. Thus Congress chose a path that would assure compensation without +giving the past (broadcasters) control over the future (cable). +

+In the same year that Congress struck this balance, two major producers and +distributors of film content filed a lawsuit against another technology, the +video tape recorder (VTR, or as we refer to them today, VCRs) that Sony had +produced, the Betamax. Disney's and Universal's claim against Sony was +relatively simple: Sony produced a device, Disney and Universal claimed, +that enabled consumers to engage in copyright infringement. Because the +device that Sony built had a "record" button, the device could be used to +record copyrighted movies and shows. Sony was therefore benefiting from the +copyright infringement of its customers. It should therefore, Disney and +Universal claimed, be partially liable for that infringement. +

+ +There was something to Disney's and Universal's claim. Sony did decide to +design its machine to make it very simple to record television shows. It +could have built the machine to block or inhibit any direct copying from a +television broadcast. Or possibly, it could have built the machine to copy +only if there were a special "copy me" signal on the line. It was clear that +there were many television shows that did not grant anyone permission to +copy. Indeed, if anyone had asked, no doubt the majority of shows would not +have authorized copying. And in the face of this obvious preference, Sony +could have designed its system to minimize the opportunity for copyright +infringement. It did not, and for that, Disney and Universal wanted to hold +it responsible for the architecture it chose. +

+MPAA president Jack Valenti became the studios' most vocal champion. Valenti +called VCRs "tapeworms." He warned, "When there are 20, 30, 40 million of +these VCRs in the land, we will be invaded by millions of `tapeworms,' +eating away at the very heart and essence of the most precious asset the +copyright owner has, his copyright."[87] +"One does not have to be trained in sophisticated marketing and creative +judgment," he told Congress, "to understand the devastation on the +after-theater marketplace caused by the hundreds of millions of tapings that +will adversely impact on the future of the creative community in this +country. It is simply a question of basic economics and plain common +sense."[88] Indeed, as surveys would later +show, percent of VCR owners had movie libraries of ten videos or +more[89] — a use the Court would +later hold was not "fair." By "allowing VCR owners to copy freely by the +means of an exemption from copyright infringementwithout creating a +mechanism to compensate copyrightowners," Valenti testified, Congress would +"take from the owners the very essence of their property: the exclusive +right to control who may use their work, that is, who may copy it and +thereby profit from its reproduction."[90] +

+It took eight years for this case to be resolved by the Supreme Court. In +the interim, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, which includes Hollywood in +its jurisdiction—leading Judge Alex Kozinski, who sits on that court, +refers to it as the "Hollywood Circuit"—held that Sony would be liable +for the copyright infringement made possible by its machines. Under the +Ninth Circuit's rule, this totally familiar technology—which Jack +Valenti had called "the Boston Strangler of the American film industry" +(worse yet, it was a Japanese Boston Strangler of the American film +industry)—was an illegal technology.[91] +

+ +But the Supreme Court reversed the decision of the Ninth Circuit. And in +its reversal, the Court clearly articulated its understanding of when and +whether courts should intervene in such disputes. As the Court wrote, +

+Sound policy, as well as history, supports our consistent deference to +Congress when major technological innovations alter the market for +copyrighted materials. Congress has the constitutional authority and the +institutional ability to accommodate fully the varied permutations of +competing interests that are inevitably implicated by such new +technology.[92] +

+Congress was asked to respond to the Supreme Court's decision. But as with +the plea of recording artists about radio broadcasts, Congress ignored the +request. Congress was convinced that American film got enough, this "taking" +notwithstanding. If we put these cases together, a pattern is clear: +

Tabell 2.1. Tabell

CASEWHOSE VALUE WAS "PIRATED"RESPONSE OF THE COURTSRESPONSE OF CONGRESS
InnspillingerKomponisterIngen beskyttelseStatutory license
RadioInnspillingsartisterN/AIngenting
Kabel-TVKringkastereIngen beskyttelseStatutory license
VCRFilmskapereIngen beskyttelseIngenting

+In each case throughout our history, a new technology changed the way +content was distributed.[93] In each case, +throughout our history, that change meant that someone got a "free ride" on +someone else's work. +

+ +In none of these cases did either the courts or Congress eliminate all free +riding. In none of these cases did the courts or Congress insist that the +law should assure that the copyright holder get all the value that his +copyright created. In every case, the copyright owners complained of +"piracy." In every case, Congress acted to recognize some of the legitimacy +in the behavior of the "pirates." In each case, Congress allowed some new +technology to benefit from content made before. It balanced the interests at +stake. + +

+When you think across these examples, and the other examples that make up +the first four chapters of this section, this balance makes sense. Was Walt +Disney a pirate? Would doujinshi be better if creators had to ask +permission? Should tools that enable others to capture and spread images as +a way to cultivate or criticize our culture be better regulated? Is it +really right that building a search engine should expose you to $15 million +in damages? Would it have been better if Edison had controlled film? Should +every cover band have to hire a lawyer to get permission to record a song? +

+We could answer yes to each of these questions, but our tradition has +answered no. In our tradition, as the Supreme Court has stated, copyright +"has never accorded the copyright owner complete control over all possible +uses of his work."[94] Instead, the +particular uses that the law regulates have been defined by balancing the +good that comes from granting an exclusive right against the burdens such an +exclusive right creates. And this balancing has historically been done after +a technology has matured, or settled into the mix of technologies that +facilitate the distribution of content. +

+We should be doing the same thing today. The technology of the Internet is +changing quickly. The way people connect to the Internet (wires +vs. wireless) is changing very quickly. No doubt the network should not +become a tool for "stealing" from artists. But neither should the law become +a tool to entrench one particular way in which artists (or more accurately, +distributors) get paid. As I describe in some detail in the last chapter of +this book, we should be securing income to artists while we allow the market +to secure the most efficient way to promote and distribute content. This +will require changes in the law, at least in the interim. These changes +should be designed to balance the protection of the law against the strong +public interest that innovation continue. +

+ + +This is especially true when a new technology enables a vastly superior mode +of distribution. And this p2p has done. P2p technologies can be ideally +efficient in moving content across a widely diverse network. Left to +develop, they could make the network vastly more efficient. Yet these +"potential public benefits," as John Schwartz writes in The New York Times, +"could be delayed in the P2P fight."[95] +Yet when anyone begins to talk about "balance," the copyright warriors raise +a different argument. "All this hand waving about balance and incentives," +they say, "misses a fundamental point. Our content," the warriors insist, +"is our property. Why should we wait for Congress to `rebalance' our +property rights? Do you have to wait before calling the police when your car +has been stolen? And why should Congress deliberate at all about the merits +of this theft? Do we ask whether the car thief had a good use for the car +before we arrest him?" +

+"It is our property," the warriors insist. "And it should be protected just +as any other property is protected." +



[15] + + +Bach v. Longman, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777) (Mansfield). +

[16] + + +Se Rochelle Dreyfuss, "Expressive Genericity: Trademarks as Language in the +Pepsi Generation," Notre Dame Law Review 65 (1990): 397. +

[17] + +Lisa Bannon, "The Birds May Sing, but Campers Can't Unless They Pay Up," +Wall Street Journal, 21. august 1996, tilgjengelig fra link #3; Jonathan Zittrain, +"Calling Off the Copyright War: In Battle of Property vs. Free Speech, No +One Wins," Boston Globe, 24. november 2002. +

[18] + +I The Rise of the Creative Class (New York: Basic Books, 2002), dokumenterer +Richard Florida en endring i arbeidsstokken mot kreativitetsarbeide. Hans +tekst omhandler derimot ikke direkte de juridiske vilkår som kreativiteten +blir muliggjort eller hindret under. Jeg er helt klart enig med ham i +viktigheten og betydningen av denne endringen, men jeg tror også at +vilkårene som disse endringene blir aktivert under er mye vanskeligere. + +

[19] + + +Leonard Maltin, Of Mice and Magic: A History of American Animated Cartoons +(New York: Penguin Books, 1987), 34–35. +

[20] + + +Jeg er takknemlig overfor David Gerstein og hans nøyaktige historie, +beskrevet på link #4. I +følge Dave Smith ved the Disney Archives, betalte Disney for å bruke +musikken til fem sanger i Steamboat Willie: "Steamboat Bill," "The +Simpleton" (Delille), "Mischief Makers" (Carbonara), "Joyful Hurry No. 1" +(Baron), og "Gawky Rube" (Lakay). En sjette sang, "The Turkey in the Straw," +var allerede allemannseie. Brev fra David Smith til Harry Surden, 10. juli +2003, tilgjenglig i arkivet til forfatteren. +

[21] + + +Han var også tilhenger av allmannseiet. Se Chris Sprigman, "The Mouse that +Ate the Public Domain," Findlaw, 5. mars 2002, fra link #5. +

[22] + + +Until 1976, copyright law granted an author the possibility of two terms: an +initial term and a renewal term. I have calculated the "average" term by +determining the weighted average of total registrations for any particular +year, and the proportion renewing. Thus, if 100 copyrights are registered in +year 1, and only 15 are renewed, and the renewal term is 28 years, then the +average term is 32.2 years. For the renewal data and other relevant data, +see the Web site associated with this book, available at link #6. +

[23] + + +For en utmerket historie, se Scott McCloud, Reinventing Comics (New York: +Perennial, 2000). +

[24] + + +See Salil K. Mehra, "Copyright and Comics in Japan: Does Law Explain Why All +the Comics My Kid Watches Are Japanese Imports?" Rutgers Law Review 55 +(2002): 155, 182. "[T]here might be a collective economic rationality that +would lead manga and anime artists to forgo bringing legal actions for +infringement. One hypothesis is that all manga artists may be better off +collectively if they set aside their individual self-interest and decide not +to press their legal rights. This is essentially a prisoner's dilemma +solved." +

[25] + +The term intellectual property is of relatively recent origin. See Siva +Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs, 11 (New York: New York University +Press, 2001). See also Lawrence Lessig, The Future of Ideas (New York: +Random House, 2001), 293 n. 26. The term accurately describes a set of +"property" rights—copyright, patents, trademark, and +trade-secret—but the nature of those rights is very different. + +

[26] + + +Reese V. Jenkins, Images and Enterprise (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University +Press, 1975), 112. +

[27] + +Brian Coe, The Birth of Photography (New York: Taplinger Publishing, 1977), +53. +

[28] + + +Jenkins, 177. +

[29] + + +Basert på et diagram i Jenkins, s. 178. +

[30] + + +Coe, 58. +

[31] + + +For illustrative cases, see, for example, Pavesich v. N.E. Life Ins. Co., 50 +S.E. +

[32] + +Samuel D. Warren and Louis D. Brandeis, "The Right to Privacy," Harvard Law +Review 4 (1890): 193. +

[33] + + +See Melville B. Nimmer, "The Right of Publicity," Law and Contemporary +Problems 19 (1954): 203; William L. Prosser, "Privacy," California Law +Review 48 (1960) 398–407; White v. Samsung Electronics America, Inc., +971 F. 2d 1395 (9th Cir. 1992), cert. denied, 508 U.S. 951 (1993). +

[34] + + +H. Edward Goldberg, "Essential Presentation Tools: Hardware and Software You +Need to Create Digital Multimedia Presentations," cadalyst, februar 2002, +tilgjengelig fra link #7. +

[35] + + +Judith Van Evra, Television and Child Development (Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence +Erlbaum Associates, 1990); "Findings on Family and TV Study," Denver Post, +25 May 1997, B6. +

[36] + +Intervju med Elizabeth Daley og Stephanie Barish, 13. desember 2002. + +

[37] + + +Se Scott Steinberg, "Crichton Gets Medieval on PCs," E!online, 4. november +2000, tilgjengelig fra link +#8; "Timeline," 22. november 2000, tilgjengelig fra link #9. +

[38] + +Intervju med Daley og Barish. +

[39] + + +Ibid. +

[40] + + +See, for example, Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, bk. 1, +trans. Henry Reeve (New York: Bantam Books, 2000), ch. 16. +

[41] + + +Bruce Ackerman and James Fishkin, "Deliberation Day," Journal of Political +Philosophy 10 (2) (2002): 129. +

[42] + + +Cass Sunstein, Republic.com (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001), +65–80, 175, 182, 183, 192. +

[43] + + +Noah Shachtman, "With Incessant Postings, a Pundit Stirs the Pot," New York +Times, 16 January 2003, G5. +

[44] + + +Telefonintervju med David Winer, 16. april 2003. +

[45] + + +John Schwartz, "Loss of the Shuttle: The Internet; A Wealth of Information +Online," New York Times, 2 February 2003, A28; Staci D. Kramer, "Shuttle +Disaster Coverage Mixed, but Strong Overall," Online Journalism Review, 2 +February 2003, available at link +#10. +

[46] + +See Michael Falcone, "Does an Editor's Pencil Ruin a Web Log?" New York +Times, 29 September 2003, C4. ("Not all news organizations have been as +accepting of employees who blog. Kevin Sites, a CNN correspondent in Iraq +who started a blog about his reporting of the war on March 9, stopped +posting 12 days later at his bosses' request. Last year Steve Olafson, a +Houston Chronicle reporter, was fired for keeping a personal Web log, +published under a pseudonym, that dealt with some of the issues and people +he was covering.") +

[47] + + +See, for example, Edward Felten and Andrew Appel, "Technological Access +Control Interferes with Noninfringing Scholarship," Communications of the +Association for Computer Machinery 43 (2000): 9. +

[48] + + +Tim Goral, "Recording Industry Goes After Campus P-2-P Networks: Suit +Alleges $97.8 Billion in Damages," Professional Media Group LCC 6 (2003): 5, +tilgjengelig fra 2003 WL 55179443. +

[49] + + +Occupational Employment Survey, U.S. Dept. of Labor (2001) +(27–2042—Musicians and Singers). See also National Endowment for +the Arts, More Than One in a Blue Moon (2000). +

[50] + + +Douglas Lichtman kommer med et relatert poeng i "KaZaA and Punishment," Wall +Street Journal, 10. september 2003, A24. +

[51] + +I am grateful to Peter DiMauro for pointing me to this extraordinary +history. See also Siva Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs, +87–93, which details Edison's "adventures" with copyright and patent. + +

[52] + + +J. A. Aberdeen, Hollywood Renegades: The Society of Independent Motion +Picture Producers (Cobblestone Entertainment, 2000) and expanded texts +posted at "The Edison Movie Monopoly: The Motion Picture Patents Company +vs. the Independent Outlaws," available at link #11. For a discussion of +the economic motive behind both these limits and the limits imposed by +Victor on phonographs, see Randal C. Picker, "From Edison to the Broadcast +Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and the Propertization of Copyright" +(September 2002), University of Chicago Law School, James M. Olin Program in +Law and Economics, Working Paper No. 159.

[53] + + +Marc Wanamaker, "The First Studios," The Silents Majority, arkivert på +link #12. +

[54] + + +To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright: Hearings on S. 6330 +and H.R. 19853 Before the ( Joint) Committees on Patents, 59th Cong. 59, 1st +sess. (1906) (statement of Senator Alfred B. Kittredge, of South Dakota, +chairman), reprinted in Legislative History of the Copyright Act, E. Fulton +Brylawski and Abe Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, +1976). +

[55] + + +To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 223 (statement of +Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association). +

[56] + + +To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 226 (statement of +Nathan Burkan, attorney for the Music Publishers Association). +

[57] + + +To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 23 (statement of +John Philip Sousa, composer). +

[58] + + + +To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 283–84 +(statement of Albert Walker, representative of the Auto-Music Perforating +Company of New York). +

[59] + + +To Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, 376 (prepared +memorandum of Philip Mauro, general patent counsel of the American +Graphophone Company Association). +

[60] + + +Copyright Law Revision: Hearings on S. 2499, S. 2900, H.R. 243, and +H.R. 11794 Before the ( Joint) Committee on Patents, 60th Cong., 1st sess., +217 (1908) (statement of Senator Reed Smoot, chairman), reprinted in +Legislative History of the 1909 Copyright Act, E. Fulton Brylawski and Abe +Goldman, eds. (South Hackensack, N.J.: Rothman Reprints, 1976). +

[61] + + +Copyright Law Revision: Report to Accompany H.R. 2512, House Committee on +the Judiciary, 90th Cong., 1st sess., House Document no. 83, (8 March +1967). I am grateful to Glenn Brown for drawing my attention to this report.

[62] + +See 17 United States Code, sections 106 and 110. At the beginning, record +companies printed "Not Licensed for Radio Broadcast" and other messages +purporting to restrict the ability to play a record on a radio station. +Judge Learned Hand rejected the argument that a warning attached to a record +might restrict the rights of the radio station. See RCA Manufacturing +Co. v. Whiteman, 114 F. 2d 86 (2nd Cir. 1940). See also Randal C. Picker, +"From Edison to the Broadcast Flag: Mechanisms of Consent and Refusal and +the Propertization of Copyright," University of Chicago Law Review 70 +(2003): 281. +

[63] + + +Copyright Law Revision—CATV: Hearing on S. 1006 Before the +Subcommittee on Patents, Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Senate Committee +on the Judiciary, 89th Cong., 2nd sess., 78 (1966) (statement of Rosel +H. Hyde, chairman of the Federal Communications Commission). +

[64] + + +Copyright Law Revision—CATV, 116 (statement of Douglas A. Anello, +general counsel of the National Association of Broadcasters). +

[65] + + +Copyright Law Revision—CATV, 126 (statement of Ernest W. Jennes, +general counsel of the Association of Maximum Service Telecasters, Inc.). +

[66] + + +Copyright Law Revision—CATV, 169 (joint statement of Arthur B. Krim, +president of United Artists Corp., and John Sinn, president of United +Artists Television, Inc.). +

[67] + + +Copyright Law Revision—CATV, 209 (vitnemål fra Charlton Heston, +president i Screen Actors Guild). +

[68] + +Copyright Law Revision—CATV, 216 (statement of Edwin M. Zimmerman, +acting assistant attorney general). +

[69] + + +See, for example, National Music Publisher's Association, The Engine of Free +Expression: Copyright on the Internet—The Myth of Free Information, +available at link +#13. "The threat of piracy—the use of someone else's creative +work without permission or compensation—has grown with the Internet." +

[70] + + +See IFPI (International Federation of the Phonographic Industry), The +Recording Industry Commercial Piracy Report 2003, July 2003, available at +link #14. See also Ben +Hunt, "Companies Warned on Music Piracy Risk," Financial Times, 14 February +2003, 11. +

[71] + +See Peter Drahos with John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism: Who Owns the +Knowledge Economy? (New York: The New Press, 2003), 10–13, 209. The +Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement +obligates member nations to create administrative and enforcement mechanisms +for intellectual property rights, a costly proposition for developing +countries. Additionally, patent rights may lead to higher prices for staple +industries such as agriculture. Critics of TRIPS question the disparity +between burdens imposed upon developing countries and benefits conferred to +industrialized nations. TRIPS does permit governments to use patents for +public, noncommercial uses without first obtaining the patent holder's +permission. Developing nations may be able to use this to gain the benefits +of foreign patents at lower prices. This is a promising strategy for +developing nations within the TRIPS framework. +

[72] + +For an analysis of the economic impact of copying technology, see Stan +Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy (New York: Amacom, 2002), +144–90. "In some instances . . . the impact of piracy on the copyright +holder's ability to appropriate the value of the work will be +negligible. One obvious instance is the case where the individual engaging +in pirating would not have purchased an original even if pirating were not +an option." Ibid., 149. +

[73] + + +Bach v. Longman, 98 Eng. Rep. 1274 (1777). +

[74] + +See Clayton M. Christensen, The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary +National Bestseller That Changed the Way We Do Business (New York: +HarperBusiness, 2000). Professor Christensen examines why companies that +give rise to and dominate a product area are frequently unable to come up +with the most creative, paradigm-shifting uses for their own products. This +job usually falls to outside innovators, who reassemble existing technology +in inventive ways. For a discussion of Christensen's ideas, see Lawrence +Lessig, Future, 89–92, 139. +

[75] + + +See Carolyn Lochhead, "Silicon Valley Dream, Hollywood Nightmare," San +Francisco Chronicle, 24 September 2002, A1; "Rock 'n' Roll Suicide," New +Scientist, 6 July 2002, 42; Benny Evangelista, "Napster Names CEO, Secures +New Financing," San Francisco Chronicle, 23 May 2003, C1; "Napster's Wake-Up +Call," Economist, 24 June 2000, 23; John Naughton, "Hollywood at War with +the Internet" (London) Times, 26 July 2002, 18. +

[76] + + + +See Ipsos-Insight, TEMPO: Keeping Pace with Online Music Distribution +(September 2002), reporting that 28 percent of Americans aged twelve and +older have downloaded music off of the Internet and 30 percent have listened +to digital music files stored on their computers. +

[77] + + +Amy Harmon, "Industry Offers a Carrot in Online Music Fight," New York +Times, 6 June 2003, A1. +

[78] + +Se Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy,148–49. +

[79] + + +See Cap Gemini Ernst & Young, Technology Evolution and the Music +Industry's Business Model Crisis (2003), 3. This report describes the music +industry's effort to stigmatize the budding practice of cassette taping in +the 1970s, including an advertising campaign featuring a cassette-shape +skull and the caption "Home taping is killing music." At the time digital +audio tape became a threat, the Office of Technical Assessment conducted a +survey of consumer behavior. In 1988, 40 percent of consumers older than ten +had taped music to a cassette format. U.S. Congress, Office of Technology +Assessment, Copyright and Home Copying: Technology Challenges the Law, +OTA-CIT-422 (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, October +1989), 145–56.

[80] + + +U.S. Congress, Copyright and Home Copying, 4. +

[81] + + +See Recording Industry Association of America, 2002 Yearend Statistics, +available at link #15. A +later report indicates even greater losses. See Recording Industry +Association of America, Some Facts About Music Piracy, 25 June 2003, +available at link #16: +"In the past four years, unit shipments of recorded music have fallen by 26 +percent from 1.16 billion units in to 860 million units in 2002 in the +United States (based on units shipped). In terms of sales, revenues are +down 14 percent, from $14.6 billion in to $12.6 billion last year (based on +U.S. dollar value of shipments). The music industry worldwide has gone from +a $39 billion industry in 2000 down to a $32 billion industry in 2002 (based +on U.S. dollar value of shipments)." +

[82] +Jane Black, "Big Music's Broken Record," BusinessWeek online, 13. februar +2003, tilgjengelig fra link +#17. +

[83] + + +Ibid. +

[84] + + +By one estimate, 75 percent of the music released by the major labels is no +longer in print. See Online Entertainment and Copyright Law—Coming +Soon to a Digital Device Near You: Hearing Before the Senate Committee on +the Judiciary, 107th Cong., 1st sess. (3 April 2001) (prepared statement of +the Future of Music Coalition), available at link #18. +

[85] + + +While there are not good estimates of the number of used record stores in +existence, in 2002, there were 7,198 used book dealers in the United States, +an increase of 20 percent since 1993. See Book Hunter Press, The Quiet +Revolution: The Expansion of the Used Book Market (2002), available at +link #19. Used records +accounted for $260 million in sales in 2002. See National Association of +Recording Merchandisers, "2002 Annual Survey Results," available at link #20. +

[86] + + +See Transcript of Proceedings, In Re: Napster Copyright Litigation at 34- 35 +(N.D. Cal., 11 July 2001), nos. MDL-00-1369 MHP, C 99-5183 MHP, available at +link #21. For an account +of the litigation and its toll on Napster, see Joseph Menn, All the Rave: +The Rise and Fall of Shawn Fanning's Napster (New York: Crown Business, +2003), 269–82. +

[87] + + +Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders): Hearing on S. 1758 +Before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 97th Cong., 1st and 2nd sess., +459 (1982) (testimony of Jack Valenti, president, Motion Picture Association +of America, Inc.). +

[88] + + +Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 475. +

[89] + + +Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Sony Corp. of America, 480 F. Supp. 429, +(C.D. Cal., 1979). +

[90] + + +Copyright Infringements (Audio and Video Recorders), 485 (testimony of Jack +Valenti). +

[91] + + +Universal City Studios, Inc. v. Sony Corp. of America, 659 F. 2d 963 (9th +Cir. 1981). +

[92] + + +Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, 431 +(1984). +

[93] + +These are the most important instances in our history, but there are other +cases as well. The technology of digital audio tape (DAT), for example, was +regulated by Congress to minimize the risk of piracy. The remedy Congress +imposed did burden DAT producers, by taxing tape sales and controlling the +technology of DAT. See Audio Home Recording Act of 1992 (Title 17 of the +United States Code), Pub. L. No. 102-563, 106 Stat. 4237, codified at 17 +U.S.C. §1001. Again, however, this regulation did not eliminate the +opportunity for free riding in the sense I've described. See Lessig, Future, +71. See also Picker, "From Edison to the Broadcast Flag," University of +Chicago Law Review 70 (2003): 293–96. +

[94] + + +Sony Corp. of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, (1984). +

[95] + + +John Schwartz, "New Economy: The Attack on Peer-to-Peer Software Echoes Past +Efforts," New York Times, 22 September 2003, C3. +

Kapittel 3. "Eiendom"

+ + + +The copyright warriors are right: A copyright is a kind of property. It can +be owned and sold, and the law protects against its theft. Ordinarily, the +copyright owner gets to hold out for any price he wants. Markets reckon the +supply and demand that partially determine the price she can get. +

+But in ordinary language, to call a copyright a "property" right is a bit +misleading, for the property of copyright is an odd kind of property. +Indeed, the very idea of property in any idea or any expression is very +odd. I understand what I am taking when I take the picnic table you put in +your backyard. I am taking a thing, the picnic table, and after I take it, +you don't have it. But what am I taking when I take the good idea you had to +put a picnic table in the backyard—by, for example, going to Sears, +buying a table, and putting it in my backyard? What is the thing I am taking +then? +

+The point is not just about the thingness of picnic tables versus ideas, +though that's an important difference. The point instead is that in the +ordinary case—indeed, in practically every case except for a narrow +range of exceptions—ideas released to the world are free. I don't take +anything from you when I copy the way you dress—though I might seem +weird if I did it every day, and especially weird if you are a +woman. Instead, as Thomas Jefferson said (and as is especially true when I +copy the way someone else dresses), "He who receives an idea from me, +receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who lights his +taper at mine, receives light without darkening me."[96] +

+The exceptions to free use are ideas and expressions within the reach of the +law of patent and copyright, and a few other domains that I won't discuss +here. Here the law says you can't take my idea or expression without my +permission: The law turns the intangible into property. +

+But how, and to what extent, and in what form—the details, in other +words—matter. To get a good sense of how this practice of turning the +intangible into property emerged, we need to place this "property" in its +proper context.[97] +

+My strategy in doing this will be the same as my strategy in the preceding +part. I offer four stories to help put the idea of "copyright material is +property" in context. Where did the idea come from? What are its limits? How +does it function in practice? After these stories, the significance of this +true statement—"copyright material is property"— will be a bit +more clear, and its implications will be revealed as quite different from +the implications that the copyright warriors would have us draw. +

Kapittel seks: Grunnleggerne

+William Shakespeare skrev "Romeo og Julie" i 1595. Skuespillet ble først +utgitt i 1597. Det var det ellevte store skuespillet Shakespeare hadde +skrevet. Han fortsatte å skrive skuespill helt til 1613, og stykkene han +skrevhar fortsatt å definere angloamerikansk kultur siden. Så dypt har +verkene av en 1500-talls forfatter sunket inn i vår kultur at vi ofte ikke +engang kjenner kilden. Jeg overhørte en gang noen som kommentere Kenneth +Branaghs utgave av Henry V: "Jeg likte det, men Shakespeare er så full av +klisjeer." +

+ +I 1774, nesten 180 år etter at Romeo og Julie ble skrevet, mente mange at +"opphavsretten" kun tilhørte én eneste utgiver i London, John +Tonson. [98] Tonson var den mest +fremstående av en liten gruppe utgivere kalt "the Conger"[99], som kontrollerte boksalget i England gjennom hele +1700-tallet. The Conger hevdet at de hadde en evigvarende rett over "kopier" +av bøker de hadde fått av forfatterne. Denne evigvarende retten innebar at +ingen andre kunne publisere kopier av disse bøkene. Slik ble prisen på +klassiske bøker holdt oppe; alle konkurrenter som lagde bedre eller +billigere utgaver, ble fjernet. +

+Men altså, det er noe spennende med året 1774 for alle som vet litt om +opphavsretts-lovgivning. Det mest kjente året for opphavsrett er 1710, da +det britiske parlamentet vedtok den første loven. Denne loven er kjent som +"Statute of Anne" og sa at alle publiserte verk skulle være beskyttet i +fjorten år, en periode som kunne fornyes én gang dersom forfatteren ennå +levde, og at alle verk publisert i eller før 1710 skulle ha en ekstraperiode +på 22 tillegsår.[100] På grunn av denne +loven, så skulle "Rome og Julie" ha falt i det fri i 1731. Hvordan kunne da +Tonson fortsatt ha kontroll over verket i 1774? +

+Årsaken var ganske enkelt at engelskmennene ikke hadde bestemt hva +opphavsrett innebar -- faktisk hadde ingen i verden det. På den tiden da +engelskmennene vedtok "Statute of Anne", var det ingen annen lovgivning om +opphavsrett. Den siste loven som regulerte utgivere var lisensieringsloven +av 1662, utløpt i 1695. At loven ga utgiverne monopol over publiseringen, +noe som gjorde det enklere for kronen å kontrollere hva ble publisert. Men +etter at det har utløpt, var det ingen positiv lov som sa at utgiverne hadde +en eksklusiv rett til å trykke bøker. +

+At det ikke fantes noen positiv lov, betydde ikke at det ikke fantes noen +lov. Den anglo-amerikanske juridiske tradisjon ser både til lover skapt av +politikere (det lovgivende statsorgen)og til lover (prejudikater) skapt av +domstolene for å bestemme hvordan folket skal leve. Vi kaller politikernes +lover for positiv lov og vi kaller lovene fra dommerne sedvanerett."Common +law" angir bakgrunnen for de lovgivendes lovgivning; retten til lovgiving, +vanligvis kan trumfe at bakgrunnen bare hvis det går gjennom en lov til å +forskyve den. Og så var det virkelige spørsmålet etter lisensiering lover +hadde utløpt om felles lov beskyttet opphavsretten, uavhengig av lovverket +positiv. +

+ +Dette spørsmålet var viktig for utgiverne eller "bokselgere," som de ble +kalt, fordi det var økende konkurranse fra utenlandske utgivere, Særlig fra +Skottland hvor publiseringen og eksporten av bøker til England hadde økt +veldig. Denne konkurransen reduserte fortjenesten til "The Conger", som +derfor krevde at parlamentet igjen skulle vedta en lov for å gi dem +eksklusiv kontroll over publisering. Dette kravet resulterte i "Statute of +Anne". +

+"Statute of Anne" ga forfatteren eller "eieren" av en bok en eksklusiv rett +til å publisere denne boken. Men det var, til bokhandernes forferdelse en +viktig begrensning, nemlig hvor lenge denne retten skulle vare. Etter dette +gikk trykkeretten bort og verket falt i det fri og kunne trykkes av hvem som +helst. Det var ihvertfall det lovgiverne hadde tenkt. +

+Men nå det mest interessante med dette: Hvorfor ville parlamentet begrense +trykkeretten? Sprøsmålet er ikke hvorfor de bestemte seg for denne perioden, +men hvorfor ville de begrense den i det hele tatt? +

+Bokhandlerne, og forfatterne som de representerte, hadde et veldig sterkt +krav. Ta romeo og Julie som et eksempel: Skuespillet ble skrevet av +Shakespeare. Det var hans kreativitet som brakte det til verden. Han krenket +ikke noens rett da han skrev dette verket (det er en kontroversiell +påstanden, men det er urelevant), og med sin egen rett skapte han verket, +han gjorde det ikke noe vanskeligere for andre til å lage skuespill. Så +hvorfor skulle loven tillate at noen annen kunne komme og ta Shakespeares +verkuten hans, eller hans arvingers, tillatelse? Hvilke grunner finnes for å +tillate at noen "stjeler" Shakespeares verk? +

+Svaret er todel. Først må vi se på noe spesielt med oppfatningen av +opphavsrett som fantes på tidspunktet da "Statute of Anne" ble +vedtatt. Deretter må vi se på noe spesielt med bokhandlerne. +

+ +Først om opphavsretten. I de siste tre hundre år har vi kommet til å bruke +begrepet "copyright" i stadig videre forstand. Men i 1710 var det ikke så +mye et konsept som det var en bestemt rett. Opphavsretten ble født som et +svært spesifikt sett med begrensninger: den forbød andre å reprodusere en +bok. I 1710 var "kopi-rett" en rett til å bruke en bestemt maskin til å +replikere en bestemt arbeid. Den gikk ikke utover dette svært smale +formålet. Denkontrollerte ikke mer generelt hvordan et verk kunne +brukes. Idag inkluderer retten en stor samling av restriksjoner på andres +frihet: den gir forfatteren eksklusiv rett til å kopiere, eksklusiv rett til +å distribuere, eksklusiv rett til å fremføre, og så videre. +

+Så selv om f. eks. opphavsretten til Shakespeares verker var evigvarende, +betydde det under den opprinnelige betydningen av begrepet at ingen kunne +trykke Shakespeares arbeid uten tillatelse fra Shakespeares arvinger. Den +ville ikke ha kontrollert noe mer, for eksempel om hvordan verket kunne +fremføres, om verket kunne oversettes eller om Kenneth Branagh ville hatt +lov til å lage filmer. "Kopi-retten" var bare en eksklusiv rett til å +trykke--ikke noe mindre, selvfølgelig, men heller ikke mer. +

+Selv dnne begrensede retten ble møtt med skepsis av britene. De hadde hatt +en lang og stygg erfaring med "eksklusive rettigheter," spesielt "enerett" +gitt av kronen. Engelskmennene hadde utkjempet en borgerkrig delvis mot +kronens praksis med å dele ut monopoler--spesielt monopoler for verk som +allerede eksisterte. Kong Henrik VIII hadde gitt patent til å trykke Bibelen +og monopol til Darcy for å lage spillkort. Det engelske parlamentet begynte +å kjempe tilbake mot denne makten hos kronen. I 1656 ble "Statute of +Monopolis" vedtatt for å begrense monopolene på patenter for nye +oppfinnelser. Og i 1710 var parlamentet ivrig etter å håndtere det voksende +monopolet på publisering. +

+Dermed ble "kopi-retten", når den sees på som en monopolrett, en rettighet +som bør være begrenset. (Uansett hvor overbevisende påstanden om at "det er +min eiendom, og jeg skal ha for alltid," prøv hvor overbevisende det er når +men sier "det er mitt monopol, og jeg skal ha det for alltid.") Staten ville +beskytte eneretten, men bare så lenge det gavnet samfunnet. Britene så +skadene særinteresserte kunne skape; de vedtok en lov for å stoppe dem. +

+Dernest, om bokhandlerne. Det var ikke bare at kopiretten var et +monopol. Det var også et monopol holdt av bokhandlerne. En bokhandler høres +greie og ufarlige ut for oss, men slik var det ikke i syttenhundretallets +England. Medlemmene i "the Conger" ble av en voksende mengde sett på som +monopolister av verste sort - et verktøy for kronens undertrykkelse, de +solgte Englands frihet mot å være garantert en monopolskinntekt. Men +monopolistene ble kvast kritisert: Milton beskrev dem som "gamle +patentholdere og monopolister i bokhandlerkunsten"; de var "menn som derfor +ikke hadde et ærlig arbeide hvor utdanning er nødvendig."[101] +

+Mange trodde at den makten bokhandlerne utøvde over spredning av kunnskap, +var til skade for selve spredningen, men på dette tidspunktet viste +Opplysningen viktigheten av utdannelse og kunnskap for alle. idéen om at +kunnskap burde være gratis er et kjennetegn for tiden, og disse kraftige +kommersielle interesser forstyrret denne idéen. +

+For å balansere denne makten, besluttet Parlamentet å øke konkurransen blant +bokhandlerne, og den enkleste måten å gjøre det på, var å spre mengden av +verdifulle bøker. Parlamentet begrenset derfor begrepet om opphavsrett, og +garantert slik at verdifulle bøker ville bli frie for alle utgiver å +publisere etter en begrenset periode. Slik ble det å gi eksisterende verk en +periode på tjueen år et kompromiss for å bekjempe bokhandlernes +makt. Begrensninger med dato var en indirekte måte å skape konkurranse +mellom utgivere, og slik en skapelse og spredning av kultur. +

+Når 1731 (1710+21) kom, ble bokhandlerne engstelige. De så konsekvensene av +mer konkurranse, og som alle konkurrenter, likte de det ikke. Først +ignorerte bokhandlere ganske enkelt "Statute of Anne", og fortsatte å kreve +en evigvarende rett til å kontrollere publiseringen. Men i 1735 og 1737 de +prøvde å tvinge Parlamentet til å utvide periodene. Tjueen år var ikke nok, +sa de; de trengte mer tid. +

+Parlamentet avslo kravene, Som en pamflett sa, i en vending som levere ennå +idag, +

+Jeg ser ingen grunn til å gi en utvidet perioden nå som ikke ville kunne gi +utvidelser om igjen og om igjen, så fort de gamle utgår; så dersom dette +lovforslaget blir vedtatt, vil effekten være: at et evig monopol blir skapt, +et stort nederlag for handelen, et angrep mot kunnskapen, ingen fordel for +forfatterne, men en stor avgift for folket; og alt dette kun for å øke +bokhandlernes personlige rikdom.[102] +

+Etter å ha mislyktes i Parlamentet gikk utgiverne til rettssalen i en rekke +saker. Deres argument var enkelt og direkte: "Statute of Anne" ga +forfatterne en viss beskyttelse gjennom positiv loven, men denne +beskyttelsenvar ikke ment som en erstatning for felles lov. Istedet var de +ment å supplere felles lov. Ifølge sedvanerett var det galt å ta en annen +persons kreative eiendom og bruke den uten hans tillatelse. "Statute of +Anne", hevdet bokhandlere, endret ikke dette faktum. Derfor betydde ikke det +at beskyttelsen gitt av "Statute of Anne" utløp, at beskyttelsen fra +sedvaneretten utløp: Ifølge sedvaneretten hadde de rett til å fordømme +publiseringen av en bok, selv følgelig om "Statute of Anne" sa at de var +falt i det fri. Dette, mente de, var den eneste måten å beskytte +forfatterne. +

+Dette var et godt argument, og hadde støtte fra flere av den tidens ledende +jurister. Det viste også en ekstraordinær chutzpah. Inntail da, som +jusprofessor Raymond Pattetson har sagt, "var utgiverne ... like bekymret +for forfatterne som en gjeter for sine lam."[103] Bokselgerne brydde seg ikke det spor om forfatternes +rettigheter. Deres bekymring var den monopolske inntekten forfatterens verk +ga. +

+Men bokhandlernes argument ble ikke godtatt uten kamp. Helten fra denne +kampen var den skotske bokselgeren Alexander Donaldson.[104] +

+Donaldson var en fremmed for Londons "the Conger". Han startet in karriere i +Edinburgh i 1750. Hans forretningsidé var billige kopier av standardverk +falt i det fri, ihvertfall fri ifølge "Statute of Anne".[105] Donaldsons forlag vokste og ble "et sentrum for +litterære skotter." "Blant dem," skriver professor Mark Rose, var "den unge +James Boswell som, sammen med sin venn Andrew Erskine, publiserte en hel +antologi av skotsk samtidspoesi sammen med Donaldson."[106] +

+Da Londons bokselgere prøvde å få stengt Donaldsons butikk i Skottland, så +flyttet han butikken til London. Her solgte han billige utgaver av "de mest +populære, engelske bøker, i kamp mot sedvanerettens rett til litterær +eiendom." [107] Bøkene hans var mellom 30% +og 50% billigere enn "the Conger"s, og han baserte sin rett til denne +konkurransen på at bøkene, takket være "Statute of Anne", var falt i det +fri. +

+Londons bokselgere begynte straks å slå ned mot "pirater" som +Donaldson. Flere tiltak var vellykkede, den viktigste var den tidlig seieren +i kampen mellom Millar og Taylor. +

+Millar var en bokhandler som i 1729 hadde kjøpt opp rettighetene til James +Thomsons dikt "The Seasons". Millar hadde da full beskyttelse gjennom +"Statute of Anne", men etter at denne beskyttelsen var uløpt, begynte Robert +Taylor å trykke et konkurrerende bind. Millar gikk til sak, og hevdet han +hadde en evig rett gjennom sedvaneretten, uansett hva "Statute of Anne" +sa.[108] +

+Til moderne juristers forbløffelse, var en av, ikke bare datidens, men en av +de største dommere i engelsk historie, Lord Mansfield, enig med +bokhandlerne. Uansett hvilken beskyttelse "Statute of Anne" gav +bokhandlerne, så sa han at den ikke fortrengte noe fra +sedvaneretten. Spørsmålet var hvorvidt sedvaneretten beskyttet forfatterne +mot pirater. Mansfield svar var ja: Sedvaneretten nektet Taylor å +reprodusere Thomsons dikt uten Millars tillatelse. Slik gav sedvaneretten +bokselgerne en evig publiseringsrett til bøker solgt til dem. +

+ +Ser man på det som et spørsmål innen abstrakt jus - dersom man resonnere som +om rettferdighet bare var logisk deduksjon fra de første bud - kunne +Mansfields konklusjon gitt mening. Men den overså det Parlamentet hadde +kjempet for i 1710: Hvordan man på best mulig vis kunne innskrenke +utgivernes monopolmakt. Parlamentets strategi hadde vært å kjøpe fred +gjennom å tilby en beskyttelsesperiode også for eksisterende verk, men +perioden måtte være så kort at kulturen ble utsatt for konkurranse innen +rimelig tid. Storbritannia skulle vokse fra den kontrollerte kulturen under +kronen, inn i en fri og åpen kultur. +

+Kampen for å forsvare "Statute of Anne"s begrensninger sluttet uansett ikke +der, for nå kommer Donaldson. +

+Millar døde kort tid etter sin seier. Boet hans solgte rettighetene over +Thomsons dikt til et syndikat av utgivere, deriblant Thomas +Beckett.[109] Da ga Donaldson ut en +uautorisert utgave av Thomsons verk. Etter avgjørelsen i Millar-saken, gikk +Beckett til sak mot Donaldson. Donaldson tok saken inn for Overhuset, som da +fungerte som en slags høyesterett. I februar 1774 hadde dette organet +muligheten til å tolke Parlamentets mening med utøpsdatoen fra seksti år +før. +

+Rettssaken Donaldson mot Beckett fikk en enorm oppmerksomhet i hele +Storbritannia. Donaldsons advokater mente at selv om det før fantes en del +rettigheter i sedvaneretten, så var disse fortrengt av "Statute of +Anne". Etter at "Statute of Anne" var blitt vedtatt, skulle den eneste +lovlige beskyttelse for trykkerett kom derfra. Og derfor, mente de, i tråd +med vilkårene i "Statute of Anne", falle i det fri så fort +beskyttelsesperioden var over. +

+Overhuset var en merkelig institusjon. Juridiske spørsmål ble presentert for +huset, og ble først stemt over av "juslorder", medlemmer av enspesiell +rettslig gruppe som fungerte nesten slik som justiariusene i vår +Høyesterett. Deretter, etter at "juslordene" hadde stemt, stemte resten av +Overhuset. +

+ +Rapportene om juslordene stemmer er uenige. På enkelte punkter ser det ut +som om evigvarende beskyttelse fikk flertall. Men det er ingen tvil om +hvordan resten av Overhuset stemte. Med en majoritet på to mot en (22 mot +11) stemte de ned forslaget om en evig beskyttelse. Uansett hvordan man +hadde tolket sedvaneretten, var nå kopiretten begrenset til en periode, og +etter denne ville verket falle i det fri. +

+"Å falle i det fri". Før rettssaken Donaldson mot Beckett var det ingen klar +oppfatning om hva å falle i det fri innebar. Før 1774 var det jo en allmenn +oppfatning om at kopiretten var evigvarende. Men etter 1774 ble Public +Domain født.For første gang i angloamerikansk historie var den lovlige +beskyttelsen av et verk utgått, og de største verk i engelsk historie - +inkludert Shakespeare, Bacon, Milton, Johnson og Bunyan - var frie. + +

+Vi kan knapt forestille oss det, men denne avgjørelsen fra Overhuset fyrte +opp under en svært populær og politisk reaksjon. I Skottland, hvor de fleste +piratugiverne hadde holdt til, ble avgjørelsen feiret i gatene. Som +Edinburgh Advertiser skrev "Ingen privatsak har noen gang fått slik +oppmerksomhet fra folket, og ingen sak som har blitt prøvet i Overhuset har +interessert så mange enkeltmennesker." "Stor glede i Edinburgh etter seieren +over litterær eiendom: bål og *illuminations*.[110] +

+I London, ihvertfall blant utgiverne, var reaksjonen like sterk, men i +motsatt retning. Morning Chronicle skrev: +

+Gjennom denne avgjørelsen ... er verdier til nesten 200 000 pund, som er +blitt ærlig kjøpt gjennom allment salg, og som i går var eiendom, er nå +redusert til ingenting. Bokselgerne i London og Westminster, mange av dem +har solgt hus og eiendom for å kjøpe kopirettigheter, er med ett ruinerte, +og mange som gjennom mange år har opparbeidet kompetanse for å brødfø +familien, sitter nå uten en shilling til sine.[111] +

+ + +Ruinert er en overdrivelse. Men det er ingen overdrivelse å si at endringen +var stor. Vedtaket fra Overhuset betydde at bokhandlerne ikke lenger kunnen +kontrollere hvordan kulturen i England ville vokse og utvikle seg. Kulturen +i England var etter dette fri. Ikke i den betydning at kopiretten ble +ignorert, for utgiverne hadde i en begrenset periode rett over +trykkingen. Og heller ikke i den betydningen at bøker kunne stjeles, for +selv etter at boken var falt i det fri, så måtte den kjøpes. Men i den +betydningen at kulturen og dens vekst ikke lenger var kontrollert av en +liten gruppe utgivere. Som alle frie markeder, ville dette markedet vokse og +utvikle seg etter tilbud og etterspørsel. Den engelske kulturen ble nå +formet slik flertallet Englands lesere ville at det skulle formes - gjennom +valget av hva de kjøpte og skrev, gjennom valget av *memes* de gjentok og +beundret. Valg i en konkurrerende sammenheng, ikke der hvor valgene var om +hvilken kultur som skulle være tilgjengelig for folket og hvor deres tilgang +til den ble styrt av noen få, på tros av flertallets ønsker. +

+Til sist, dette var en verden hvor Parlamentet var anitmonopolistisk, og +holdt stand mot utgivernes krav. I en verden hvor Parlamentet er mer +medgjørlig, vil den frie kultur være mindre beskyttet. +

Kapittel sju: Innspillerne

+Jon Else is a filmmaker. He is best known for his documentaries and has been +very successful in spreading his art. He is also a teacher, and as a teacher +myself, I envy the loyalty and admiration that his students feel for him. (I +met, by accident, two of his students at a dinner party. He was their god.) +

+Else worked on a documentary that I was involved in. At a break, he told me +a story about the freedom to create with film in America today. +

+In 1990, Else was working on a documentary about Wagner's Ring Cycle. The +focus was stagehands at the San Francisco Opera. Stagehands are a +particularly funny and colorful element of an opera. During a show, they +hang out below the stage in the grips' lounge and in the lighting loft. They +make a perfect contrast to the art on the stage. +

+ +During one of the performances, Else was shooting some stagehands playing +checkers. In one corner of the room was a television set. Playing on the +television set, while the stagehands played checkers and the opera company +played Wagner, was The Simpsons. As Else judged it, this touch of cartoon +helped capture the flavor of what was special about the scene. +

+Years later, when he finally got funding to complete the film, Else +attempted to clear the rights for those few seconds of The Simpsons. For of +course, those few seconds are copyrighted; and of course, to use copyrighted +material you need the permission of the copyright owner, unless "fair use" +or some other privilege applies. +

+Else called Simpsons creator Matt Groening's office to get permission. +Groening approved the shot. The shot was a four-and-a-halfsecond image on a +tiny television set in the corner of the room. How could it hurt? Groening +was happy to have it in the film, but he told Else to contact Gracie Films, +the company that produces the program. +

+Gracie Films was okay with it, too, but they, like Groening, wanted to be +careful. So they told Else to contact Fox, Gracie's parent company. Else +called Fox and told them about the clip in the corner of the one room shot +of the film. Matt Groening had already given permission, Else said. He was +just confirming the permission with Fox. +

+Then, as Else told me, "two things happened. First we discovered . . . that +Matt Groening doesn't own his own creation—or at least that someone +[at Fox] believes he doesn't own his own creation." And second, Fox "wanted +ten thousand dollars as a licensing fee for us to use this four-point-five +seconds of . . . entirely unsolicited Simpsons which was in the corner of +the shot." +

+Else was certain there was a mistake. He worked his way up to someone he +thought was a vice president for licensing, Rebecca Herrera. He explained +to her, "There must be some mistake here. . . . We're asking for your +educational rate on this." That was the educational rate, Herrera told +Else. A day or so later, Else called again to confirm what he had been told. +

+ +"I wanted to make sure I had my facts straight," he told me. "Yes, you have +your facts straight," she said. It would cost $10,000 to use the clip of The +Simpsons in the corner of a shot in a documentary film about Wagner's Ring +Cycle. And then, astonishingly, Herrera told Else, "And if you quote me, +I'll turn you over to our attorneys." As an assistant to Herrera told Else +later on, "They don't give a shit. They just want the money." +

+Else didn't have the money to buy the right to replay what was playing on +the television backstage at the San Francisco Opera. To reproduce this +reality was beyond the documentary filmmaker's budget. At the very last +minute before the film was to be released, Else digitally replaced the shot +with a clip from another film that he had worked on, The Day After Trinity, +from ten years before. +

+There's no doubt that someone, whether Matt Groening or Fox, owns the +copyright to The Simpsons. That copyright is their property. To use that +copyrighted material thus sometimes requires the permission of the copyright +owner. If the use that Else wanted to make of the Simpsons copyright were +one of the uses restricted by the law, then he would need to get the +permission of the copyright owner before he could use the work in that +way. And in a free market, it is the owner of the copyright who gets to set +the price for any use that the law says the owner gets to control. +

+For example, "public performance" is a use of The Simpsons that the +copyright owner gets to control. If you take a selection of favorite +episodes, rent a movie theater, and charge for tickets to come see "My +Favorite Simpsons," then you need to get permission from the copyright +owner. And the copyright owner (rightly, in my view) can charge whatever she +wants—$10 or $1,000,000. That's her right, as set by the law. +

+But when lawyers hear this story about Jon Else and Fox, their first thought +is "fair use."[112] Else's use of just 4.5 +seconds of an indirect shot of a Simpsons episode is clearly a fair use of +The Simpsons—and fair use does not require the permission of anyone. +

+ + +So I asked Else why he didn't just rely upon "fair use." Here's his reply: +

+The Simpsons fiasco was for me a great lesson in the gulf between what +lawyers find irrelevant in some abstract sense, and what is crushingly +relevant in practice to those of us actually trying to make and broadcast +documentaries. I never had any doubt that it was "clearly fair use" in an +absolute legal sense. But I couldn't rely on the concept in any concrete +way. Here's why: +

  1. + + +Before our films can be broadcast, the network requires that we buy Errors +and Omissions insurance. The carriers require a detailed "visual cue sheet" +listing the source and licensing status of each shot in the film. They take +a dim view of "fair use," and a claim of "fair use" can grind the +application process to a halt. +

  2. + +I probably never should have asked Matt Groening in the first place. But I +knew (at least from folklore) that Fox had a history of tracking down and +stopping unlicensed Simpsons usage, just as George Lucas had a very high +profile litigating Star Wars usage. So I decided to play by the book, +thinking that we would be granted free or cheap license to four seconds of +Simpsons. As a documentary producer working to exhaustion on a shoestring, +the last thing I wanted was to risk legal trouble, even nuisance legal +trouble, and even to defend a principle. +

  3. + + + +I did, in fact, speak with one of your colleagues at Stanford Law School +. . . who confirmed that it was fair use. He also confirmed that Fox would +"depose and litigate you to within an inch of your life," regardless of the +merits of my claim. He made clear that it would boil down to who had the +bigger legal department and the deeper pockets, me or them. + +

  4. + + +The question of fair use usually comes up at the end of the project, when we +are up against a release deadline and out of money. +

+In theory, fair use means you need no permission. The theory therefore +supports free culture and insulates against a permission culture. But in +practice, fair use functions very differently. The fuzzy lines of the law, +tied to the extraordinary liability if lines are crossed, means that the +effective fair use for many types of creators is slight. The law has the +right aim; practice has defeated the aim. +

+This practice shows just how far the law has come from its +eighteenth-century roots. The law was born as a shield to protect +publishers' profits against the unfair competition of a pirate. It has +matured into a sword that interferes with any use, transformative or not. +

Kapittel åtte: Omformere

+In 1993, Alex Alben was a lawyer working at Starwave, Inc. Starwave was an +innovative company founded by Microsoft cofounder Paul Allen to develop +digital entertainment. Long before the Internet became popular, Starwave +began investing in new technology for delivering entertainment in +anticipation of the power of networks. +

+Alben had a special interest in new technology. He was intrigued by the +emerging market for CD-ROM technology—not to distribute film, but to +do things with film that otherwise would be very difficult. In 1993, he +launched an initiative to develop a product to build retrospectives on the +work of particular actors. The first actor chosen was Clint Eastwood. The +idea was to showcase all of the work of Eastwood, with clips from his films +and interviews with figures important to his career. +

+At that time, Eastwood had made more than fifty films, as an actor and as a +director. Alben began with a series of interviews with Eastwood, asking him +about his career. Because Starwave produced those interviews, it was free to +include them on the CD. +

+ + +That alone would not have made a very interesting product, so Starwave +wanted to add content from the movies in Eastwood's career: posters, +scripts, and other material relating to the films Eastwood made. Most of his +career was spent at Warner Brothers, and so it was relatively easy to get +permission for that content. +

+Then Alben and his team decided to include actual film clips. "Our goal was +that we were going to have a clip from every one of Eastwood's films," Alben +told me. It was here that the problem arose. "No one had ever really done +this before," Alben explained. "No one had ever tried to do this in the +context of an artistic look at an actor's career." +

+Alben brought the idea to Michael Slade, the CEO of Starwave. Slade asked, +"Well, what will it take?" +

+Alben replied, "Well, we're going to have to clear rights from everyone who +appears in these films, and the music and everything else that we want to +use in these film clips." Slade said, "Great! Go for it."[113] +

+The problem was that neither Alben nor Slade had any idea what clearing +those rights would mean. Every actor in each of the films could have a claim +to royalties for the reuse of that film. But CD- ROMs had not been specified +in the contracts for the actors, so there was no clear way to know just what +Starwave was to do. +

+I asked Alben how he dealt with the problem. With an obvious pride in his +resourcefulness that obscured the obvious bizarreness of his tale, Alben +recounted just what they did: +

+So we very mechanically went about looking up the film clips. We made some +artistic decisions about what film clips to include—of course we were +going to use the "Make my day" clip from Dirty Harry. But you then need to +get the guy on the ground who's wiggling under the gun and you need to get +his permission. And then you have to decide what you are going to pay him. +

+ + +We decided that it would be fair if we offered them the dayplayer rate for +the right to reuse that performance. We're talking about a clip of less than +a minute, but to reuse that performance in the CD-ROM the rate at the time +was about $600. So we had to identify the people—some of them were +hard to identify because in Eastwood movies you can't tell who's the guy +crashing through the glass—is it the actor or is it the stuntman? And +then we just, we put together a team, my assistant and some others, and we +just started calling people. +

+Some actors were glad to help—Donald Sutherland, for example, followed +up himself to be sure that the rights had been cleared. Others were +dumbfounded at their good fortune. Alben would ask, "Hey, can I pay you $600 +or maybe if you were in two films, you know, $1,200?" And they would say, +"Are you for real? Hey, I'd love to get $1,200." And some of course were a +bit difficult (estranged ex-wives, in particular). But eventually, Alben and +his team had cleared the rights to this retrospective CD-ROM on Clint +Eastwood's career. +

+It was one year later—"and even then we weren't sure whether we were +totally in the clear." +

+Alben is proud of his work. The project was the first of its kind and the +only time he knew of that a team had undertaken such a massive project for +the purpose of releasing a retrospective. +

+Everyone thought it would be too hard. Everyone just threw up their hands +and said, "Oh, my gosh, a film, it's so many copyrights, there's the music, +there's the screenplay, there's the director, there's the actors." But we +just broke it down. We just put it into its constituent parts and said, +"Okay, there's this many actors, this many directors, . . . this many +musicians," and we just went at it very systematically and cleared the +rights. +

+ + + +And no doubt, the product itself was exceptionally good. Eastwood loved it, +and it sold very well. +

+But I pressed Alben about how weird it seems that it would have to take a +year's work simply to clear rights. No doubt Alben had done this +efficiently, but as Peter Drucker has famously quipped, "There is nothing so +useless as doing efficiently that which should not be done at +all."[114] Did it make sense, I asked Alben, +that this is the way a new work has to be made? +

+For, as he acknowledged, "very few . . . have the time and resources, and +the will to do this," and thus, very few such works would ever be made. Does +it make sense, I asked him, from the standpoint of what anybody really +thought they were ever giving rights for originally, that you would have to +go clear rights for these kinds of clips? +

+I don't think so. When an actor renders a performance in a movie, he or she +gets paid very well. . . . And then when 30 seconds of that performance is +used in a new product that is a retrospective of somebody's career, I don't +think that that person . . . should be compensated for that. +

+Or at least, is this how the artist should be compensated? Would it make +sense, I asked, for there to be some kind of statutory license that someone +could pay and be free to make derivative use of clips like this? Did it +really make sense that a follow-on creator would have to track down every +artist, actor, director, musician, and get explicit permission from each? +Wouldn't a lot more be created if the legal part of the creative process +could be made to be more clean? +

+ +Absolutely. I think that if there were some fair-licensing +mechanism—where you weren't subject to hold-ups and you weren't +subject to estranged former spouses—you'd see a lot more of this work, +because it wouldn't be so daunting to try to put together a retrospective of +someone's career and meaningfully illustrate it with lots of media from that +person's career. You'd build in a cost as the producer of one of these +things. You'd build in a cost of paying X dollars to the talent that +performed. But it would be a known cost. That's the thing that trips +everybody up and makes this kind of product hard to get off the ground. If +you knew I have a hundred minutes of film in this product and it's going to +cost me X, then you build your budget around it, and you can get investments +and everything else that you need to produce it. But if you say, "Oh, I want +a hundred minutes of something and I have no idea what it's going to cost +me, and a certain number of people are going to hold me up for money," then +it becomes difficult to put one of these things together. +

+Alben worked for a big company. His company was backed by some of the +richest investors in the world. He therefore had authority and access that +the average Web designer would not have. So if it took him a year, how long +would it take someone else? And how much creativity is never made just +because the costs of clearing the rights are so high? These costs are the +burdens of a kind of regulation. Put on a Republican hat for a moment, and +get angry for a bit. The government defines the scope of these rights, and +the scope defined determines how much it's going to cost to negotiate +them. (Remember the idea that land runs to the heavens, and imagine the +pilot purchasing flythrough rights as he negotiates to fly from Los Angeles +to San Francisco.) These rights might well have once made sense; but as +circumstances change, they make no sense at all. Or at least, a +well-trained, regulationminimizing Republican should look at the rights and +ask, "Does this still make sense?" +

+ +I've seen the flash of recognition when people get this point, but only a +few times. The first was at a conference of federal judges in California. +The judges were gathered to discuss the emerging topic of cyber-law. I was +asked to be on the panel. Harvey Saferstein, a well-respected lawyer from an +L.A. firm, introduced the panel with a video that he and a friend, Robert +Fairbank, had produced. +

+Videoen var en glimrende sammenstilling av filmer fra hver periode i det +tjuende århundret, rammet inn rundt idéen om en episode i TV-serien 60 +Minutes. Utførelsen var perfekt, ned til seksti minutter +stoppeklokken. Dommerne elsket enhver minutt av den. +

+Da lysene kom på, kikket jeg over til min medpaneldeltager, David Nimmer, +kanskje den ledende opphavsrettakademiker og utøver i nasjonen. Han hadde en +forbauset uttrykk i ansiktet sitt, mens han tittet ut over rommet med over +250 godt underholdte dommere. Med en en illevarslende tone, begynte han sin +tale med et spørsmål: "Vet dere hvor mange føderale lover som nettopp brutt +i dette rommet?" +

+For of course, the two brilliantly talented creators who made this film +hadn't done what Alben did. They hadn't spent a year clearing the rights to +these clips; technically, what they had done violated the law. Of course, +it wasn't as if they or anyone were going to be prosecuted for this +violation (the presence of 250 judges and a gaggle of federal marshals +notwithstanding). But Nimmer was making an important point: A year before +anyone would have heard of the word Napster, and two years before another +member of our panel, David Boies, would defend Napster before the Ninth +Circuit Court of Appeals, Nimmer was trying to get the judges to see that +the law would not be friendly to the capacities that this technology would +enable. Technology means you can now do amazing things easily; but you +couldn't easily do them legally. +

+We live in a "cut and paste" culture enabled by technology. Anyone building +a presentation knows the extraordinary freedom that the cut and paste +architecture of the Internet created—in a second you can find just +about any image you want; in another second, you can have it planted in your +presentation. +

+But presentations are just a tiny beginning. Using the Internet and its +archives, musicians are able to string together mixes of sound never before +imagined; filmmakers are able to build movies out of clips on computers +around the world. An extraordinary site in Sweden takes images of +politicians and blends them with music to create biting political +commentary. A site called Camp Chaos has produced some of the most biting +criticism of the record industry that there is through the mixing of Flash! +and music. +

+All of these creations are technically illegal. Even if the creators wanted +to be "legal," the cost of complying with the law is impossibly +high. Therefore, for the law-abiding sorts, a wealth of creativity is never +made. And for that part that is made, if it doesn't follow the clearance +rules, it doesn't get released. +

+To some, these stories suggest a solution: Let's alter the mix of rights so +that people are free to build upon our culture. Free to add or mix as they +see fit. We could even make this change without necessarily requiring that +the "free" use be free as in "free beer." Instead, the system could simply +make it easy for follow-on creators to compensate artists without requiring +an army of lawyers to come along: a rule, for example, that says "the +royalty owed the copyright owner of an unregistered work for the derivative +reuse of his work will be a flat 1 percent of net revenues, to be held in +escrow for the copyright owner." Under this rule, the copyright owner could +benefit from some royalty, but he would not have the benefit of a full +property right (meaning the right to name his own price) unless he registers +the work. +

+Who could possibly object to this? And what reason would there be for +objecting? We're talking about work that is not now being made; which if +made, under this plan, would produce new income for artists. What reason +would anyone have to oppose it? +

+ +In February 2003, DreamWorks studios announced an agreement with Mike Myers, +the comic genius of Saturday Night Live and Austin Powers. According to the +announcement, Myers and Dream-Works would work together to form a "unique +filmmaking pact." Under the agreement, DreamWorks "will acquire the rights +to existing motion picture hits and classics, write new storylines +and—with the use of stateof-the-art digital technology—insert +Myers and other actors into the film, thereby creating an entirely new piece +of entertainment." +

+The announcement called this "film sampling." As Myers explained, "Film +Sampling is an exciting way to put an original spin on existing films and +allow audiences to see old movies in a new light. Rap artists have been +doing this for years with music and now we are able to take that same +concept and apply it to film." Steven Spielberg is quoted as saying, "If +anyone can create a way to bring old films to new audiences, it is Mike." +

+Spielberg is right. Film sampling by Myers will be brilliant. But if you +don't think about it, you might miss the truly astonishing point about this +announcement. As the vast majority of our film heritage remains under +copyright, the real meaning of the DreamWorks announcement is just this: It +is Mike Myers and only Mike Myers who is free to sample. Any general freedom +to build upon the film archive of our culture, a freedom in other contexts +presumed for us all, is now a privilege reserved for the funny and +famous—and presumably rich. +

+This privilege becomes reserved for two sorts of reasons. The first +continues the story of the last chapter: the vagueness of "fair use." Much +of "sampling" should be considered "fair use." But few would rely upon so +weak a doctrine to create. That leads to the second reason that the +privilege is reserved for the few: The costs of negotiating the legal rights +for the creative reuse of content are astronomically high. These costs +mirror the costs with fair use: You either pay a lawyer to defend your fair +use rights or pay a lawyer to track down permissions so you don't have to +rely upon fair use rights. Either way, the creative process is a process of +paying lawyers—again a privilege, or perhaps a curse, reserved for the +few. +

Kapittel ni: Samlere

+In April 1996, millions of "bots"—computer codes designed to "spider," +or automatically search the Internet and copy content—began running +across the Net. Page by page, these bots copied Internet-based information +onto a small set of computers located in a basement in San Francisco's +Presidio. Once the bots finished the whole of the Internet, they started +again. Over and over again, once every two months, these bits of code took +copies of the Internet and stored them. +

+By October 2001, the bots had collected more than five years of copies. And +at a small announcement in Berkeley, California, the archive that these +copies created, the Internet Archive, was opened to the world. Using a +technology called "the Way Back Machine," you could enter a Web page, and +see all of its copies going back to 1996, as well as when those pages +changed. +

+This is the thing about the Internet that Orwell would have appreciated. In +the dystopia described in 1984, old newspapers were constantly updated to +assure that the current view of the world, approved of by the government, +was not contradicted by previous news reports. +

+ + +Thousands of workers constantly reedited the past, meaning there was no way +ever to know whether the story you were reading today was the story that was +printed on the date published on the paper. +

+It's the same with the Internet. If you go to a Web page today, there's no +way for you to know whether the content you are reading is the same as the +content you read before. The page may seem the same, but the content could +easily be different. The Internet is Orwell's library—constantly +updated, without any reliable memory. +

+Until the Way Back Machine, at least. With the Way Back Machine, and the +Internet Archive underlying it, you can see what the Internet was. You have +the power to see what you remember. More importantly, perhaps, you also have +the power to find what you don't remember and what others might prefer you +forget.[115] +

+We take it for granted that we can go back to see what we remember +reading. Think about newspapers. If you wanted to study the reaction of your +hometown newspaper to the race riots in Watts in 1965, or to Bull Connor's +water cannon in 1963, you could go to your public library and look at the +newspapers. Those papers probably exist on microfiche. If you're lucky, they +exist in paper, too. Either way, you are free, using a library, to go back +and remember—not just what it is convenient to remember, but remember +something close to the truth. +

+It is said that those who fail to remember history are doomed to repeat +it. That's not quite correct. We all forget history. The key is whether we +have a way to go back to rediscover what we forget. More directly, the key +is whether an objective past can keep us honest. Libraries help do that, by +collecting content and keeping it, for schoolchildren, for researchers, for +grandma. A free society presumes this knowedge. +

+ +The Internet was an exception to this presumption. Until the Internet +Archive, there was no way to go back. The Internet was the quintessentially +transitory medium. And yet, as it becomes more important in forming and +reforming society, it becomes more and more important to maintain in some +historical form. It's just bizarre to think that we have scads of archives +of newspapers from tiny towns around the world, yet there is but one copy of +the Internet—the one kept by the Internet Archive. +

+Brewster Kahle is the founder of the Internet Archive. He was a very +successful Internet entrepreneur after he was a successful computer +researcher. In the 1990s, Kahle decided he had had enough business +success. It was time to become a different kind of success. So he launched +a series of projects designed to archive human knowledge. The Internet +Archive was just the first of the projects of this Andrew Carnegie of the +Internet. By December of 2002, the archive had over 10 billion pages, and it +was growing at about a billion pages a month. +

+The Way Back Machine is the largest archive of human knowledge in human +history. At the end of 2002, it held "two hundred and thirty terabytes of +material"—and was "ten times larger than the Library of Congress." And +this was just the first of the archives that Kahle set out to build. In +addition to the Internet Archive, Kahle has been constructing the Television +Archive. Television, it turns out, is even more ephemeral than the +Internet. While much of twentieth-century culture was constructed through +television, only a tiny proportion of that culture is available for anyone +to see today. Three hours of news are recorded each evening by Vanderbilt +University—thanks to a specific exemption in the copyright law. That +content is indexed, and is available to scholars for a very low fee. "But +other than that, [television] is almost unavailable," Kahle told me. "If you +were Barbara Walters you could get access to [the archives], but if you are +just a graduate student?" As Kahle put it, +

+ +Do you remember when Dan Quayle was interacting with Murphy Brown? Remember +that back and forth surreal experience of a politician interacting with a +fictional television character? If you were a graduate student wanting to +study that, and you wanted to get those original back and forth exchanges +between the two, the 60 Minutes episode that came out after it . . . it +would be almost impossible. . . . Those materials are almost +unfindable. . . . +

+Why is that? Why is it that the part of our culture that is recorded in +newspapers remains perpetually accessible, while the part that is recorded +on videotape is not? How is it that we've created a world where researchers +trying to understand the effect of media on nineteenthcentury America will +have an easier time than researchers trying to understand the effect of +media on twentieth-century America? +

+In part, this is because of the law. Early in American copyright law, +copyright owners were required to deposit copies of their work in +libraries. These copies were intended both to facilitate the spread of +knowledge and to assure that a copy of the work would be around once the +copyright expired, so that others might access and copy the work. +

+These rules applied to film as well. But in 1915, the Library of Congress +made an exception for film. Film could be copyrighted so long as such +deposits were made. But the filmmaker was then allowed to borrow back the +deposits—for an unlimited time at no cost. In 1915 alone, there were +more than 5,475 films deposited and "borrowed back." Thus, when the +copyrights to films expire, there is no copy held by any library. The copy +exists—if it exists at all—in the library archive of the film +company.[116] +

+The same is generally true about television. Television broadcasts were +originally not copyrighted—there was no way to capture the broadcasts, +so there was no fear of "theft." But as technology enabled capturing, +broadcasters relied increasingly upon the law. The law required they make a +copy of each broadcast for the work to be "copyrighted." But those copies +were simply kept by the broadcasters. No library had any right to them; the +government didn't demand them. The content of this part of American culture +is practically invisible to anyone who would look. +

+ +Kahle was eager to correct this. Before September 11, 2001, he and his +allies had started capturing television. They selected twenty stations from +around the world and hit the Record button. After September 11, Kahle, +working with dozens of others, selected twenty stations from around the +world and, beginning October 11, 2001, made their coverage during the week +of September 11 available free on-line. Anyone could see how news reports +from around the world covered the events of that day. +

+Kahle had the same idea with film. Working with Rick Prelinger, whose +archive of film includes close to 45,000 "ephemeral films" (meaning films +other than Hollywood movies, films that were never copyrighted), Kahle +established the Movie Archive. Prelinger let Kahle digitize 1,300 films in +this archive and post those films on the Internet to be downloaded for +free. Prelinger's is a for-profit company. It sells copies of these films as +stock footage. What he has discovered is that after he made a significant +chunk available for free, his stock footage sales went up +dramatically. People could easily find the material they wanted to use. Some +downloaded that material and made films on their own. Others purchased +copies to enable other films to be made. Either way, the archive enabled +access to this important part of our culture. Want to see a copy of the +"Duck and Cover" film that instructed children how to save themselves in the +middle of nuclear attack? Go to archive.org, and you can download the film +in a few minutes—for free. +

+Here again, Kahle is providing access to a part of our culture that we +otherwise could not get easily, if at all. It is yet another part of what +defines the twentieth century that we have lost to history. The law doesn't +require these copies to be kept by anyone, or to be deposited in an archive +by anyone. Therefore, there is no simple way to find them. +

+The key here is access, not price. Kahle wants to enable free access to this +content, but he also wants to enable others to sell access to it. His aim is +to ensure competition in access to this important part of our culture. Not +during the commercial life of a bit of creative property, but during a +second life that all creative property has—a noncommercial life. +

+ +For here is an idea that we should more clearly recognize. Every bit of +creative property goes through different "lives." In its first life, if the +creator is lucky, the content is sold. In such cases the commercial market +is successful for the creator. The vast majority of creative property +doesn't enjoy such success, but some clearly does. For that content, +commercial life is extremely important. Without this commercial market, +there would be, many argue, much less creativity. +

+After the commercial life of creative property has ended, our tradition has +always supported a second life as well. A newspaper delivers the news every +day to the doorsteps of America. The very next day, it is used to wrap fish +or to fill boxes with fragile gifts or to build an archive of knowledge +about our history. In this second life, the content can continue to inform +even if that information is no longer sold. +

+The same has always been true about books. A book goes out of print very +quickly (the average today is after about a year[117]). After it is out of print, it can be sold in used book stores +without the copyright owner getting anything and stored in libraries, where +many get to read the book, also for free. Used book stores and libraries are +thus the second life of a book. That second life is extremely important to +the spread and stability of culture. +

+Yet increasingly, any assumption about a stable second life for creative +property does not hold true with the most important components of popular +culture in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries. For +these—television, movies, music, radio, the Internet—there is no +guarantee of a second life. For these sorts of culture, it is as if we've +replaced libraries with Barnes & Noble superstores. With this culture, +what's accessible is nothing but what a certain limited market demands. +Beyond that, culture disappears. +

+ +For most of the twentieth century, it was economics that made this so. It +would have been insanely expensive to collect and make accessible all +television and film and music: The cost of analog copies is extraordinarily +high. So even though the law in principle would have restricted the ability +of a Brewster Kahle to copy culture generally, the real restriction was +economics. The market made it impossibly difficult to do anything about this +ephemeral culture; the law had little practical effect. +

+Perhaps the single most important feature of the digital revolution is that +for the first time since the Library of Alexandria, it is feasible to +imagine constructing archives that hold all culture produced or distributed +publicly. Technology makes it possible to imagine an archive of all books +published, and increasingly makes it possible to imagine an archive of all +moving images and sound. +

+The scale of this potential archive is something we've never imagined +before. The Brewster Kahles of our history have dreamed about it; but we are +for the first time at a point where that dream is possible. As Kahle +describes, +

+It looks like there's about two to three million recordings of music. +Ever. There are about a hundred thousand theatrical releases of movies, +. . . and about one to two million movies [distributed] during the twentieth +century. There are about twenty-six million different titles of books. All +of these would fit on computers that would fit in this room and be able to +be afforded by a small company. So we're at a turning point in our +history. Universal access is the goal. And the opportunity of leading a +different life, based on this, is . . . thrilling. It could be one of the +things humankind would be most proud of. Up there with the Library of +Alexandria, putting a man on the moon, and the invention of the printing +press. +

+ +Kahle is not the only librarian. The Internet Archive is not the only +archive. But Kahle and the Internet Archive suggest what the future of +libraries or archives could be. When the commercial life of creative +property ends, I don't know. But it does. And whenever it does, Kahle and +his archive hint at a world where this knowledge, and culture, remains +perpetually available. Some will draw upon it to understand it; some to +criticize it. Some will use it, as Walt Disney did, to re-create the past +for the future. These technologies promise something that had become +unimaginable for much of our past—a future for our past. The +technology of digital arts could make the dream of the Library of Alexandria +real again. +

+Technologists have thus removed the economic costs of building such an +archive. But lawyers' costs remain. For as much as we might like to call +these "archives," as warm as the idea of a "library" might seem, the +"content" that is collected in these digital spaces is also someone's +"property." And the law of property restricts the freedoms that Kahle and +others would exercise. +

Kapittel ti: "Eiendom"

+Jack Valenti has been the president of the Motion Picture Association of +America since 1966. He first came to Washington, D.C., with Lyndon Johnson's +administration—literally. The famous picture of Johnson's swearing-in +on Air Force One after the assassination of President Kennedy has Valenti in +the background. In his almost forty years of running the MPAA, Valenti has +established himself as perhaps the most prominent and effective lobbyist in +Washington. +

+The MPAA is the American branch of the international Motion Picture +Association. It was formed in 1922 as a trade association whose goal was to +defend American movies against increasing domestic criticism. The +organization now represents not only filmmakers but producers and +distributors of entertainment for television, video, and cable. Its board is +made up of the chairmen and presidents of the seven major producers and +distributors of motion picture and television programs in the United States: +Walt Disney, Sony Pictures Entertainment, MGM, Paramount Pictures, Twentieth +Century Fox, Universal Studios, and Warner Brothers. + +

+ + +Valenti is only the third president of the MPAA. No president before him has +had as much influence over that organization, or over Washington. As a +Texan, Valenti has mastered the single most important political skill of a +Southerner—the ability to appear simple and slow while hiding a +lightning-fast intellect. To this day, Valenti plays the simple, humble +man. But this Harvard MBA, and author of four books, who finished high +school at the age of fifteen and flew more than fifty combat missions in +World War II, is no Mr. Smith. When Valenti went to Washington, he mastered +the city in a quintessentially Washingtonian way. +

+In defending artistic liberty and the freedom of speech that our culture +depends upon, the MPAA has done important good. In crafting the MPAA rating +system, it has probably avoided a great deal of speech-regulating harm. But +there is an aspect to the organization's mission that is both the most +radical and the most important. This is the organization's effort, +epitomized in Valenti's every act, to redefine the meaning of "creative +property." +

+In 1982, Valenti's testimony to Congress captured the strategy perfectly: +

+No matter the lengthy arguments made, no matter the charges and the +counter-charges, no matter the tumult and the shouting, reasonable men and +women will keep returning to the fundamental issue, the central theme which +animates this entire debate: Creative property owners must be accorded the +same rights and protection resident in all other property owners in the +nation. That is the issue. That is the question. And that is the rostrum on +which this entire hearing and the debates to follow must rest.[118] +

+ +The strategy of this rhetoric, like the strategy of most of Valenti's +rhetoric, is brilliant and simple and brilliant because simple. The "central +theme" to which "reasonable men and women" will return is this: "Creative +property owners must be accorded the same rights and protections resident in +all other property owners in the nation." There are no second-class +citizens, Valenti might have continued. There should be no second-class +property owners. +

+This claim has an obvious and powerful intuitive pull. It is stated with +such clarity as to make the idea as obvious as the notion that we use +elections to pick presidents. But in fact, there is no more extreme a claim +made by anyone who is serious in this debate than this claim of +Valenti's. Jack Valenti, however sweet and however brilliant, is perhaps the +nation's foremost extremist when it comes to the nature and scope of +"creative property." His views have no reasonable connection to our actual +legal tradition, even if the subtle pull of his Texan charm has slowly +redefined that tradition, at least in Washington. +

+While "creative property" is certainly "property" in a nerdy and precise +sense that lawyers are trained to understand,[119] it has never been the case, nor should it be, that "creative +property owners" have been "accorded the same rights and protection resident +in all other property owners." Indeed, if creative property owners were +given the same rights as all other property owners, that would effect a +radical, and radically undesirable, change in our tradition. +

+Valenti knows this. But he speaks for an industry that cares squat for our +tradition and the values it represents. He speaks for an industry that is +instead fighting to restore the tradition that the British overturned in +1710. In the world that Valenti's changes would create, a powerful few would +exercise powerful control over how our creative culture would develop. +

+ +I have two purposes in this chapter. The first is to convince you that, +historically, Valenti's claim is absolutely wrong. The second is to convince +you that it would be terribly wrong for us to reject our history. We have +always treated rights in creative property differently from the rights +resident in all other property owners. They have never been the same. And +they should never be the same, because, however counterintuitive this may +seem, to make them the same would be to fundamentally weaken the opportunity +for new creators to create. Creativity depends upon the owners of +creativity having less than perfect control. +

+Organizations such as the MPAA, whose board includes the most powerful of +the old guard, have little interest, their rhetoric notwithstanding, in +assuring that the new can displace them. No organization does. No person +does. (Ask me about tenure, for example.) But what's good for the MPAA is +not necessarily good for America. A society that defends the ideals of free +culture must preserve precisely the opportunity for new creativity to +threaten the old. To get just a hint that there is something fundamentally +wrong in Valenti's argument, we need look no further than the United States +Constitution itself. +

+The framers of our Constitution loved "property." Indeed, so strongly did +they love property that they built into the Constitution an important +requirement. If the government takes your property—if it condemns your +house, or acquires a slice of land from your farm—it is required, +under the Fifth Amendment's "Takings Clause," to pay you "just compensation" +for that taking. The Constitution thus guarantees that property is, in a +certain sense, sacred. It cannot ever be taken from the property owner +unless the government pays for the privilege. +

+ +Yet the very same Constitution speaks very differently about what Valenti +calls "creative property." In the clause granting Congress the power to +create "creative property," the Constitution requires that after a "limited +time," Congress take back the rights that it has granted and set the +"creative property" free to the public domain. Yet when Congress does this, +when the expiration of a copyright term "takes" your copyright and turns it +over to the public domain, Congress does not have any obligation to pay +"just compensation" for this "taking." Instead, the same Constitution that +requires compensation for your land requires that you lose your "creative +property" right without any compensation at all. +

+The Constitution thus on its face states that these two forms of property +are not to be accorded the same rights. They are plainly to be treated +differently. Valenti is therefore not just asking for a change in our +tradition when he argues that creative-property owners should be accorded +the same rights as every other property-right owner. He is effectively +arguing for a change in our Constitution itself. +

+Arguing for a change in our Constitution is not necessarily wrong. There +was much in our original Constitution that was plainly wrong. The +Constitution of 1789 entrenched slavery; it left senators to be appointed +rather than elected; it made it possible for the electoral college to +produce a tie between the president and his own vice president (as it did in +1800). The framers were no doubt extraordinary, but I would be the first to +admit that they made big mistakes. We have since rejected some of those +mistakes; no doubt there could be others that we should reject as well. So +my argument is not simply that because Jefferson did it, we should, too. +

+Instead, my argument is that because Jefferson did it, we should at least +try to understand why. Why did the framers, fanatical property types that +they were, reject the claim that creative property be given the same rights +as all other property? Why did they require that for creative property there +must be a public domain? +

+To answer this question, we need to get some perspective on the history of +these "creative property" rights, and the control that they enabled. Once +we see clearly how differently these rights have been defined, we will be in +a better position to ask the question that should be at the core of this +war: Not whether creative property should be protected, but how. Not whether +we will enforce the rights the law gives to creative-property owners, but +what the particular mix of rights ought to be. Not whether artists should be +paid, but whether institutions designed to assure that artists get paid need +also control how culture develops. +

+ + + +To answer these questions, we need a more general way to talk about how +property is protected. More precisely, we need a more general way than the +narrow language of the law allows. In Code and Other Laws of Cyberspace, I +used a simple model to capture this more general perspective. For any +particular right or regulation, this model asks how four different +modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or +regulation. I represented it with this diagram: +

Figur 3.1. How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken +the right or regulation.

How four different modalities of regulation interact to support or weaken the right or regulation.

+At the center of this picture is a regulated dot: the individual or group +that is the target of regulation, or the holder of a right. (In each case +throughout, we can describe this either as regulation or as a right. For +simplicity's sake, I will speak only of regulations.) The ovals represent +four ways in which the individual or group might be regulated— either +constrained or, alternatively, enabled. Law is the most obvious constraint +(to lawyers, at least). It constrains by threatening punishments after the +fact if the rules set in advance are violated. So if, for example, you +willfully infringe Madonna's copyright by copying a song from her latest CD +and posting it on the Web, you can be punished with a $150,000 fine. The +fine is an ex post punishment for violating an ex ante rule. It is imposed +by the state. +

+Norms are a different kind of constraint. They, too, punish an individual +for violating a rule. But the punishment of a norm is imposed by a +community, not (or not only) by the state. There may be no law against +spitting, but that doesn't mean you won't be punished if you spit on the +ground while standing in line at a movie. The punishment might not be harsh, +though depending upon the community, it could easily be more harsh than many +of the punishments imposed by the state. The mark of the difference is not +the severity of the rule, but the source of the enforcement. +

+The market is a third type of constraint. Its constraint is effected through +conditions: You can do X if you pay Y; you'll be paid M if you do N. These +constraints are obviously not independent of law or norms—it is +property law that defines what must be bought if it is to be taken legally; +it is norms that say what is appropriately sold. But given a set of norms, +and a background of property and contract law, the market imposes a +simultaneous constraint upon how an individual or group might behave. +

+Finally, and for the moment, perhaps, most mysteriously, +"architecture"—the physical world as one finds it—is a +constraint on behavior. A fallen bridge might constrain your ability to get +across a river. Railroad tracks might constrain the ability of a community +to integrate its social life. As with the market, architecture does not +effect its constraint through ex post punishments. Instead, also as with the +market, architecture effects its constraint through simultaneous +conditions. These conditions are imposed not by courts enforcing contracts, +or by police punishing theft, but by nature, by "architecture." If a +500-pound boulder blocks your way, it is the law of gravity that enforces +this constraint. If a $500 airplane ticket stands between you and a flight +to New York, it is the market that enforces this constraint. +

+ + + +So the first point about these four modalities of regulation is obvious: +They interact. Restrictions imposed by one might be reinforced by +another. Or restrictions imposed by one might be undermined by another. +

+The second point follows directly: If we want to understand the effective +freedom that anyone has at a given moment to do any particular thing, we +have to consider how these four modalities interact. Whether or not there +are other constraints (there may well be; my claim is not about +comprehensiveness), these four are among the most significant, and any +regulator (whether controlling or freeing) must consider how these four in +particular interact. +

+So, for example, consider the "freedom" to drive a car at a high speed. That +freedom is in part restricted by laws: speed limits that say how fast you +can drive in particular places at particular times. It is in part restricted +by architecture: speed bumps, for example, slow most rational drivers; +governors in buses, as another example, set the maximum rate at which the +driver can drive. The freedom is in part restricted by the market: Fuel +efficiency drops as speed increases, thus the price of gasoline indirectly +constrains speed. And finally, the norms of a community may or may not +constrain the freedom to speed. Drive at 50 mph by a school in your own +neighborhood and you're likely to be punished by the neighbors. The same +norm wouldn't be as effective in a different town, or at night. +

+ +The final point about this simple model should also be fairly clear: While +these four modalities are analytically independent, law has a special role +in affecting the three.[120] The law, in +other words, sometimes operates to increase or decrease the constraint of a +particular modality. Thus, the law might be used to increase taxes on +gasoline, so as to increase the incentives to drive more slowly. The law +might be used to mandate more speed bumps, so as to increase the difficulty +of driving rapidly. The law might be used to fund ads that stigmatize +reckless driving. Or the law might be used to require that other laws be +more strict—a federal requirement that states decrease the speed +limit, for example—so as to decrease the attractiveness of fast +driving. +

Figur 3.2. Law has a special role in affecting the three.

Law has a special role in affecting the three.

+These constraints can thus change, and they can be changed. To understand +the effective protection of liberty or protection of property at any +particular moment, we must track these changes over time. A restriction +imposed by one modality might be erased by another. A freedom enabled by one +modality might be displaced by another.[121] +

Hvorfor Hollywood har rett

+The most obvious point that this model reveals is just why, or just how, +Hollywood is right. The copyright warriors have rallied Congress and the +courts to defend copyright. This model helps us see why that rallying makes +sense. +

+Let's say this is the picture of copyright's regulation before the Internet: +

Figur 3.3. Copyright's regulation before the Internet.

Copyright's regulation before the Internet.

+ + +There is balance between law, norms, market, and architecture. The law +limits the ability to copy and share content, by imposing penalties on those +who copy and share content. Those penalties are reinforced by technologies +that make it hard to copy and share content (architecture) and expensive to +copy and share content (market). Finally, those penalties are mitigated by +norms we all recognize—kids, for example, taping other kids' +records. These uses of copyrighted material may well be infringement, but +the norms of our society (before the Internet, at least) had no problem with +this form of infringement. +

+Enter the Internet, or, more precisely, technologies such as MP3s and p2p +sharing. Now the constraint of architecture changes dramatically, as does +the constraint of the market. And as both the market and architecture relax +the regulation of copyright, norms pile on. The happy balance (for the +warriors, at least) of life before the Internet becomes an effective state +of anarchy after the Internet. +

+ +Thus the sense of, and justification for, the warriors' response. +Technology has changed, the warriors say, and the effect of this change, +when ramified through the market and norms, is that a balance of protection +for the copyright owners' rights has been lost. This is Iraq after the fall +of Saddam, but this time no government is justifying the looting that +results. +

Figur 3.4. effective state of anarchy after the Internet.

effective state of anarchy after the Internet.

+Neither this analysis nor the conclusions that follow are new to the +warriors. Indeed, in a "White Paper" prepared by the Commerce Department +(one heavily influenced by the copyright warriors) in 1995, this mix of +regulatory modalities had already been identified and the strategy to +respond already mapped. In response to the changes the Internet had +effected, the White Paper argued (1) Congress should strengthen intellectual +property law, (2) businesses should adopt innovative marketing techniques, +(3) technologists should push to develop code to protect copyrighted +material, and (4) educators should educate kids to better protect copyright. +

+ +This mixed strategy is just what copyright needed—if it was to +preserve the particular balance that existed before the change induced by +the Internet. And it's just what we should expect the content industry to +push for. It is as American as apple pie to consider the happy life you have +as an entitlement, and to look to the law to protect it if something comes +along to change that happy life. Homeowners living in a flood plain have no +hesitation appealing to the government to rebuild (and rebuild again) when a +flood (architecture) wipes away their property (law). Farmers have no +hesitation appealing to the government to bail them out when a virus +(architecture) devastates their crop. Unions have no hesitation appealing to +the government to bail them out when imports (market) wipe out the +U.S. steel industry. +

+Thus, there's nothing wrong or surprising in the content industry's campaign +to protect itself from the harmful consequences of a technological +innovation. And I would be the last person to argue that the changing +technology of the Internet has not had a profound effect on the content +industry's way of doing business, or as John Seely Brown describes it, its +"architecture of revenue." +

+But just because a particular interest asks for government support, it +doesn't follow that support should be granted. And just because technology +has weakened a particular way of doing business, it doesn't follow that the +government should intervene to support that old way of doing +business. Kodak, for example, has lost perhaps as much as 20 percent of +their traditional film market to the emerging technologies of digital +cameras.[122] Does anyone believe the +government should ban digital cameras just to support Kodak? Highways have +weakened the freight business for railroads. Does anyone think we should ban +trucks from roads for the purpose of protecting the railroads? Closer to the +subject of this book, remote channel changers have weakened the "stickiness" +of television advertising (if a boring commercial comes on the TV, the +remote makes it easy to surf ), and it may well be that this change has +weakened the television advertising market. But does anyone believe we +should regulate remotes to reinforce commercial television? (Maybe by +limiting them to function only once a second, or to switch to only ten +channels within an hour?) +

+The obvious answer to these obviously rhetorical questions is no. In a free +society, with a free market, supported by free enterprise and free trade, +the government's role is not to support one way of doing business against +others. Its role is not to pick winners and protect them against loss. If +the government did this generally, then we would never have any progress. As +Microsoft chairman Bill Gates wrote in 1991, in a memo criticizing software +patents, "established companies have an interest in excluding future +competitors."[123] And relative to a +startup, established companies also have the means. (Think RCA and FM +radio.) A world in which competitors with new ideas must fight not only the +market but also the government is a world in which competitors with new +ideas will not succeed. It is a world of stasis and increasingly +concentrated stagnation. It is the Soviet Union under Brezhnev. + +

+Thus, while it is understandable for industries threatened with new +technologies that change the way they do business to look to the government +for protection, it is the special duty of policy makers to guarantee that +that protection not become a deterrent to progress. It is the duty of policy +makers, in other words, to assure that the changes they create, in response +to the request of those hurt by changing technology, are changes that +preserve the incentives and opportunities for innovation and change. +

+In the context of laws regulating speech—which include, obviously, +copyright law—that duty is even stronger. When the industry +complaining about changing technologies is asking Congress to respond in a +way that burdens speech and creativity, policy makers should be especially +wary of the request. It is always a bad deal for the government to get into +the business of regulating speech markets. The risks and dangers of that +game are precisely why our framers created the First Amendment to our +Constitution: "Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of +speech." So when Congress is being asked to pass laws that would "abridge" +the freedom of speech, it should ask— carefully—whether such +regulation is justified. +

+ +My argument just now, however, has nothing to do with whether the changes +that are being pushed by the copyright warriors are "justified." My argument +is about their effect. For before we get to the question of justification, a +hard question that depends a great deal upon your values, we should first +ask whether we understand the effect of the changes the content industry +wants. +

+Her kommer metaforen som vil forklare argumentet. +

+In 1873, the chemical DDT was first synthesized. In 1948, Swiss chemist Paul +Hermann Müller won the Nobel Prize for his work demonstrating the +insecticidal properties of DDT. By the 1950s, the insecticide was widely +used around the world to kill disease-carrying pests. It was also used to +increase farm production. +

+No one doubts that killing disease-carrying pests or increasing crop +production is a good thing. No one doubts that the work of Müller was +important and valuable and probably saved lives, possibly millions. +

+But in 1962, Rachel Carson published Silent Spring, which argued that DDT, +whatever its primary benefits, was also having unintended environmental +consequences. Birds were losing the ability to reproduce. Whole chains of +the ecology were being destroyed. + +

+No one set out to destroy the environment. Paul Müller certainly did not aim +to harm any birds. But the effort to solve one set of problems produced +another set which, in the view of some, was far worse than the problems that +were originally attacked. Or more accurately, the problems DDT caused were +worse than the problems it solved, at least when considering the other, more +environmentally friendly ways to solve the problems that DDT was meant to +solve. +

+ +It is to this image precisely that Duke University law professor James Boyle +appeals when he argues that we need an "environmentalism" for +culture.[124] His point, and the point I +want to develop in the balance of this chapter, is not that the aims of +copyright are flawed. Or that authors should not be paid for their work. Or +that music should be given away "for free." The point is that some of the +ways in which we might protect authors will have unintended consequences for +the cultural environment, much like DDT had for the natural environment. And +just as criticism of DDT is not an endorsement of malaria or an attack on +farmers, so, too, is criticism of one particular set of regulations +protecting copyright not an endorsement of anarchy or an attack on authors. +It is an environment of creativity that we seek, and we should be aware of +our actions' effects on the environment. +

+My argument, in the balance of this chapter, tries to map exactly this +effect. No doubt the technology of the Internet has had a dramatic effect on +the ability of copyright owners to protect their content. But there should +also be little doubt that when you add together the changes in copyright law +over time, plus the change in technology that the Internet is undergoing +just now, the net effect of these changes will not be only that copyrighted +work is effectively protected. Also, and generally missed, the net effect of +this massive increase in protection will be devastating to the environment +for creativity. +

+In a line: To kill a gnat, we are spraying DDT with consequences for free +culture that will be far more devastating than that this gnat will be lost. +

Opphav

+America copied English copyright law. Actually, we copied and improved +English copyright law. Our Constitution makes the purpose of "creative +property" rights clear; its express limitations reinforce the English aim to +avoid overly powerful publishers. +

+The power to establish "creative property" rights is granted to Congress in +a way that, for our Constitution, at least, is very odd. Article I, section +8, clause 8 of our Constitution states that: +

+ +Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, +by securing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right +to their respective Writings and Discoveries. We can call this the +"Progress Clause," for notice what this clause does not say. It does not say +Congress has the power to grant "creative property rights." It says that +Congress has the power to promote progress. The grant of power is its +purpose, and its purpose is a public one, not the purpose of enriching +publishers, nor even primarily the purpose of rewarding authors. +

+The Progress Clause expressly limits the term of copyrights. As we saw in +chapter 6, the English limited the term of copyright so as to assure that a +few would not exercise disproportionate control over culture by exercising +disproportionate control over publishing. We can assume the framers followed +the English for a similar purpose. Indeed, unlike the English, the framers +reinforced that objective, by requiring that copyrights extend "to Authors" +only. +

+The design of the Progress Clause reflects something about the +Constitution's design in general. To avoid a problem, the framers built +structure. To prevent the concentrated power of publishers, they built a +structure that kept copyrights away from publishers and kept them short. To +prevent the concentrated power of a church, they banned the federal +government from establishing a church. To prevent concentrating power in the +federal government, they built structures to reinforce the power of the +states—including the Senate, whose members were at the time selected +by the states, and an electoral college, also selected by the states, to +select the president. In each case, a structure built checks and balances +into the constitutional frame, structured to prevent otherwise inevitable +concentrations of power. +

+I doubt the framers would recognize the regulation we call "copyright" +today. The scope of that regulation is far beyond anything they ever +considered. To begin to understand what they did, we need to put our +"copyright" in context: We need to see how it has changed in the 210 years +since they first struck its design. +

+ +Some of these changes come from the law: some in light of changes in +technology, and some in light of changes in technology given a particular +concentration of market power. In terms of our model, we started here: +

Figur 3.5. Copyright's regulation before the Internet.

Copyright's regulation before the Internet.

+Vi kommer til å ende opp her: +

Figur 3.6. "Opphavsrett" i dag.

"Opphavsrett" i dag.

+ +La meg forklare hvordan. + +

Loven: Varighet

+When the first Congress enacted laws to protect creative property, it faced +the same uncertainty about the status of creative property that the English +had confronted in 1774. Many states had passed laws protecting creative +property, and some believed that these laws simply supplemented common law +rights that already protected creative authorship.[125] This meant that there was no guaranteed public +domain in the United States in 1790. If copyrights were protected by the +common law, then there was no simple way to know whether a work published in +the United States was controlled or free. Just as in England, this lingering +uncertainty would make it hard for publishers to rely upon a public domain +to reprint and distribute works. +

+That uncertainty ended after Congress passed legislation granting +copyrights. Because federal law overrides any contrary state law, federal +protections for copyrighted works displaced any state law protections. Just +as in England the Statute of Anne eventually meant that the copyrights for +all English works expired, a federal statute meant that any state copyrights +expired as well. +

+In 1790, Congress enacted the first copyright law. It created a federal +copyright and secured that copyright for fourteen years. If the author was +alive at the end of that fourteen years, then he could opt to renew the +copyright for another fourteen years. If he did not renew the copyright, his +work passed into the public domain. +

+Selv om det ble skapt mange verker i USA i de første 10 årene til +republikken, så ble kun 5 prosent av verkene registrert under det føderale +opphavsrettsregimet. Av alle verker skapt i USA både før 1790 og fra 1790 +fram til 1800, så ble 95 prosent øyeblikkelig allemannseie (public +domain). Resten ble allemannseie etter maksimalt 20 år, og som oftest etter +14 år.[126] +

+ +Dette fornyelsessystemet var en avgjørende del av det amerikanske systemet +for opphavsrett. Det sikret at maksimal vernetid i opphavsretten bare ble +gitt til verker der det var ønsket. Etter den første perioden på fjorten år, +hvis forfatteren ikke så verdien av å fornye sin opphavsrett, var det heller +ikke verdt det for samfunnet å håndheve opphavsretten. +

+Fourteen years may not seem long to us, but for the vast majority of +copyright owners at that time, it was long enough: Only a small minority of +them renewed their copyright after fourteen years; the balance allowed their +work to pass into the public domain.[127] +

+Even today, this structure would make sense. Most creative work has an +actual commercial life of just a couple of years. Most books fall out of +print after one year.[128] When that +happens, the used books are traded free of copyright regulation. Thus the +books are no longer effectively controlled by copyright. The only practical +commercial use of the books at that time is to sell the books as used books; +that use—because it does not involve publication—is effectively +free. +

+In the first hundred years of the Republic, the term of copyright was +changed once. In 1831, the term was increased from a maximum of 28 years to +a maximum of 42 by increasing the initial term of copyright from 14 years to +28 years. In the next fifty years of the Republic, the term increased once +again. In 1909, Congress extended the renewal term of 14 years to 28 years, +setting a maximum term of 56 years. +

+Then, beginning in 1962, Congress started a practice that has defined +copyright law since. Eleven times in the last forty years, Congress has +extended the terms of existing copyrights; twice in those forty years, +Congress extended the term of future copyrights. Initially, the extensions +of existing copyrights were short, a mere one to two years. In 1976, +Congress extended all existing copyrights by nineteen years. And in 1998, +in the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, Congress extended the term +of existing and future copyrights by twenty years. +

+ +The effect of these extensions is simply to toll, or delay, the passing of +works into the public domain. This latest extension means that the public +domain will have been tolled for thirty-nine out of fifty-five years, or 70 +percent of the time since 1962. Thus, in the twenty years after the Sonny +Bono Act, while one million patents will pass into the public domain, zero +copyrights will pass into the public domain by virtue of the expiration of a +copyright term. +

+The effect of these extensions has been exacerbated by another, +little-noticed change in the copyright law. Remember I said that the framers +established a two-part copyright regime, requiring a copyright owner to +renew his copyright after an initial term. The requirement of renewal meant +that works that no longer needed copyright protection would pass more +quickly into the public domain. The works remaining under protection would +be those that had some continuing commercial value. +

+The United States abandoned this sensible system in 1976. For all works +created after 1978, there was only one copyright term—the maximum +term. For "natural" authors, that term was life plus fifty years. For +corporations, the term was seventy-five years. Then, in 1992, Congress +abandoned the renewal requirement for all works created before 1978. All +works still under copyright would be accorded the maximum term then +available. After the Sonny Bono Act, that term was ninety-five years. +

+This change meant that American law no longer had an automatic way to assure +that works that were no longer exploited passed into the public domain. And +indeed, after these changes, it is unclear whether it is even possible to +put works into the public domain. The public domain is orphaned by these +changes in copyright law. Despite the requirement that terms be "limited," +we have no evidence that anything will limit them. +

+The effect of these changes on the average duration of copyright is +dramatic. In 1973, more than 85 percent of copyright owners failed to renew +their copyright. That meant that the average term of copyright in 1973 was +just 32.2 years. Because of the elimination of the renewal requirement, the +average term of copyright is now the maximum term. In thirty years, then, +the average term has tripled, from 32.2 years to 95 years.[129] +

Loven: Virkeområde

+The "scope" of a copyright is the range of rights granted by the law. The +scope of American copyright has changed dramatically. Those changes are not +necessarily bad. But we should understand the extent of the changes if we're +to keep this debate in context. +

+In 1790, that scope was very narrow. Copyright covered only "maps, charts, +and books." That means it didn't cover, for example, music or +architecture. More significantly, the right granted by a copyright gave the +author the exclusive right to "publish" copyrighted works. That means +someone else violated the copyright only if he republished the work without +the copyright owner's permission. Finally, the right granted by a copyright +was an exclusive right to that particular book. The right did not extend to +what lawyers call "derivative works." It would not, therefore, interfere +with the right of someone other than the author to translate a copyrighted +book, or to adapt the story to a different form (such as a drama based on a +published book). +

+This, too, has changed dramatically. While the contours of copyright today +are extremely hard to describe simply, in general terms, the right covers +practically any creative work that is reduced to a tangible form. It covers +music as well as architecture, drama as well as computer programs. It gives +the copyright owner of that creative work not only the exclusive right to +"publish" the work, but also the exclusive right of control over any +"copies" of that work. And most significant for our purposes here, the right +gives the copyright owner control over not only his or her particular work, +but also any "derivative work" that might grow out of the original work. In +this way, the right covers more creative work, protects the creative work +more broadly, and protects works that are based in a significant way on the +initial creative work. +

+ +At the same time that the scope of copyright has expanded, procedural +limitations on the right have been relaxed. I've already described the +complete removal of the renewal requirement in 1992. In addition to the +renewal requirement, for most of the history of American copyright law, +there was a requirement that a work be registered before it could receive +the protection of a copyright. There was also a requirement that any +copyrighted work be marked either with that famous © or the word +copyright. And for most of the history of American copyright law, there was +a requirement that works be deposited with the government before a copyright +could be secured. +

+The reason for the registration requirement was the sensible understanding +that for most works, no copyright was required. Again, in the first ten +years of the Republic, 95 percent of works eligible for copyright were never +copyrighted. Thus, the rule reflected the norm: Most works apparently didn't +need copyright, so registration narrowed the regulation of the law to the +few that did. The same reasoning justified the requirement that a work be +marked as copyrighted—that way it was easy to know whether a copyright +was being claimed. The requirement that works be deposited was to assure +that after the copyright expired, there would be a copy of the work +somewhere so that it could be copied by others without locating the original +author. +

+All of these "formalities" were abolished in the American system when we +decided to follow European copyright law. There is no requirement that you +register a work to get a copyright; the copyright now is automatic; the +copyright exists whether or not you mark your work with a ©; and the +copyright exists whether or not you actually make a copy available for +others to copy. +

+Vurder et praktisk eksempel for å forstå omfanget av disse forskjellene. +

+If, in 1790, you wrote a book and you were one of the 5 percent who actually +copyrighted that book, then the copyright law protected you against another +publisher's taking your book and republishing it without your +permission. The aim of the act was to regulate publishers so as to prevent +that kind of unfair competition. In 1790, there were 174 publishers in the +United States.[130] The Copyright Act was +thus a tiny regulation of a tiny proportion of a tiny part of the creative +market in the United States—publishers. +

+ + +The act left other creators totally unregulated. If I copied your poem by +hand, over and over again, as a way to learn it by heart, my act was totally +unregulated by the 1790 act. If I took your novel and made a play based upon +it, or if I translated it or abridged it, none of those activities were +regulated by the original copyright act. These creative activities remained +free, while the activities of publishers were restrained. +

+Today the story is very different: If you write a book, your book is +automatically protected. Indeed, not just your book. Every e-mail, every +note to your spouse, every doodle, every creative act that's reduced to a +tangible form—all of this is automatically copyrighted. There is no +need to register or mark your work. The protection follows the creation, not +the steps you take to protect it. +

+That protection gives you the right (subject to a narrow range of fair use +exceptions) to control how others copy the work, whether they copy it to +republish it or to share an excerpt. +

+That much is the obvious part. Any system of copyright would control +competing publishing. But there's a second part to the copyright of today +that is not at all obvious. This is the protection of "derivative rights." +If you write a book, no one can make a movie out of your book without +permission. No one can translate it without permission. CliffsNotes can't +make an abridgment unless permission is granted. All of these derivative +uses of your original work are controlled by the copyright holder. The +copyright, in other words, is now not just an exclusive right to your +writings, but an exclusive right to your writings and a large proportion of +the writings inspired by them. +

+It is this derivative right that would seem most bizarre to our framers, +though it has become second nature to us. Initially, this expansion was +created to deal with obvious evasions of a narrower copyright. If I write a +book, can you change one word and then claim a copyright in a new and +different book? Obviously that would make a joke of the copyright, so the +law was properly expanded to include those slight modifications as well as +the verbatim original work. +

+ + +In preventing that joke, the law created an astonishing power within a free +culture—at least, it's astonishing when you understand that the law +applies not just to the commercial publisher but to anyone with a +computer. I understand the wrong in duplicating and selling someone else's +work. But whatever that wrong is, transforming someone else's work is a +different wrong. Some view transformation as no wrong at all—they +believe that our law, as the framers penned it, should not protect +derivative rights at all.[131] Whether or +not you go that far, it seems plain that whatever wrong is involved is +fundamentally different from the wrong of direct piracy. +

+Yet copyright law treats these two different wrongs in the same way. I can +go to court and get an injunction against your pirating my book. I can go to +court and get an injunction against your transformative use of my +book.[132] These two different uses of my +creative work are treated the same. +

+This again may seem right to you. If I wrote a book, then why should you be +able to write a movie that takes my story and makes money from it without +paying me or crediting me? Or if Disney creates a creature called "Mickey +Mouse," why should you be able to make Mickey Mouse toys and be the one to +trade on the value that Disney originally created? +

+These are good arguments, and, in general, my point is not that the +derivative right is unjustified. My aim just now is much narrower: simply to +make clear that this expansion is a significant change from the rights +originally granted. +

Lov og arkitektur: Rekkevidde

+Whereas originally the law regulated only publishers, the change in +copyright's scope means that the law today regulates publishers, users, and +authors. It regulates them because all three are capable of making copies, +and the core of the regulation of copyright law is copies.[133] +

+ + +"Copies." That certainly sounds like the obvious thing for copyright law to +regulate. But as with Jack Valenti's argument at the start of this chapter, +that "creative property" deserves the "same rights" as all other property, +it is the obvious that we need to be most careful about. For while it may be +obvious that in the world before the Internet, copies were the obvious +trigger for copyright law, upon reflection, it should be obvious that in the +world with the Internet, copies should not be the trigger for copyright +law. More precisely, they should not always be the trigger for copyright +law. +

+This is perhaps the central claim of this book, so let me take this very +slowly so that the point is not easily missed. My claim is that the Internet +should at least force us to rethink the conditions under which the law of +copyright automatically applies,[134] +because it is clear that the current reach of copyright was never +contemplated, much less chosen, by the legislators who enacted copyright +law. +

+We can see this point abstractly by beginning with this largely empty +circle. +

Figur 3.7. Alle potensielle bruk av en bok.

Alle potensielle bruk av en bok.

+ + +Think about a book in real space, and imagine this circle to represent all +its potential uses. Most of these uses are unregulated by copyright law, +because the uses don't create a copy. If you read a book, that act is not +regulated by copyright law. If you give someone the book, that act is not +regulated by copyright law. If you resell a book, that act is not regulated +(copyright law expressly states that after the first sale of a book, the +copyright owner can impose no further conditions on the disposition of the +book). If you sleep on the book or use it to hold up a lamp or let your +puppy chew it up, those acts are not regulated by copyright law, because +those acts do not make a copy. +

Figur 3.8. Eksempler på uregulert bruk av en bok.

Eksempler på uregulert bruk av en bok.

+Obviously, however, some uses of a copyrighted book are regulated by +copyright law. Republishing the book, for example, makes a copy. It is +therefore regulated by copyright law. Indeed, this particular use stands at +the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work. It is the +paradigmatic use properly regulated by copyright regulation (see first +diagram on next page). +

+Finally, there is a tiny sliver of otherwise regulated copying uses that +remain unregulated because the law considers these "fair uses." +

Figur 3.9. Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a +copyrighted work.

Republishing stands at the core of this circle of possible uses of a copyrighted work.

+These are uses that themselves involve copying, but which the law treats as +unregulated because public policy demands that they remain unregulated. You +are free to quote from this book, even in a review that is quite negative, +without my permission, even though that quoting makes a copy. That copy +would ordinarily give the copyright owner the exclusive right to say whether +the copy is allowed or not, but the law denies the owner any exclusive right +over such "fair uses" for public policy (and possibly First Amendment) +reasons. +

Figur 3.10. Unregulated copying considered "fair uses."

Unregulated copying considered "fair uses."

Figur 3.11. Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively +regulated.

Uses that before were presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated.

+ + +In real space, then, the possible uses of a book are divided into three +sorts: (1) unregulated uses, (2) regulated uses, and (3) regulated uses that +are nonetheless deemed "fair" regardless of the copyright owner's views. +

+Enter the Internet—a distributed, digital network where every use of a +copyrighted work produces a copy.[135] And +because of this single, arbitrary feature of the design of a digital +network, the scope of category 1 changes dramatically. Uses that before were +presumptively unregulated are now presumptively regulated. No longer is +there a set of presumptively unregulated uses that define a freedom +associated with a copyrighted work. Instead, each use is now subject to the +copyright, because each use also makes a copy—category 1 gets sucked +into category 2. And those who would defend the unregulated uses of +copyrighted work must look exclusively to category 3, fair uses, to bear the +burden of this shift. +

+ +So let's be very specific to make this general point clear. Before the +Internet, if you purchased a book and read it ten times, there would be no +plausible copyright-related argument that the copyright owner could make to +control that use of her book. Copyright law would have nothing to say about +whether you read the book once, ten times, or every night before you went to +bed. None of those instances of use—reading— could be regulated +by copyright law because none of those uses produced a copy. +

+But the same book as an e-book is effectively governed by a different set of +rules. Now if the copyright owner says you may read the book only once or +only once a month, then copyright law would aid the copyright owner in +exercising this degree of control, because of the accidental feature of +copyright law that triggers its application upon there being a copy. Now if +you read the book ten times and the license says you may read it only five +times, then whenever you read the book (or any portion of it) beyond the +fifth time, you are making a copy of the book contrary to the copyright +owner's wish. +

+There are some people who think this makes perfect sense. My aim just now is +not to argue about whether it makes sense or not. My aim is only to make +clear the change. Once you see this point, a few other points also become +clear: +

+First, making category 1 disappear is not anything any policy maker ever +intended. Congress did not think through the collapse of the presumptively +unregulated uses of copyrighted works. There is no evidence at all that +policy makers had this idea in mind when they allowed our policy here to +shift. Unregulated uses were an important part of free culture before the +Internet. +

+Second, this shift is especially troubling in the context of transformative +uses of creative content. Again, we can all understand the wrong in +commercial piracy. But the law now purports to regulate any transformation +you make of creative work using a machine. "Copy and paste" and "cut and +paste" become crimes. Tinkering with a story and releasing it to others +exposes the tinkerer to at least a requirement of justification. However +troubling the expansion with respect to copying a particular work, it is +extraordinarily troubling with respect to transformative uses of creative +work. +

+ +Third, this shift from category 1 to category 2 puts an extraordinary burden +on category 3 ("fair use") that fair use never before had to bear. If a +copyright owner now tried to control how many times I could read a book +on-line, the natural response would be to argue that this is a violation of +my fair use rights. But there has never been any litigation about whether I +have a fair use right to read, because before the Internet, reading did not +trigger the application of copyright law and hence the need for a fair use +defense. The right to read was effectively protected before because reading +was not regulated. +

+This point about fair use is totally ignored, even by advocates for free +culture. We have been cornered into arguing that our rights depend upon fair +use—never even addressing the earlier question about the expansion in +effective regulation. A thin protection grounded in fair use makes sense +when the vast majority of uses are unregulated. But when everything becomes +presumptively regulated, then the protections of fair use are not enough. +

+The case of Video Pipeline is a good example. Video Pipeline was in the +business of making "trailer" advertisements for movies available to video +stores. The video stores displayed the trailers as a way to sell +videos. Video Pipeline got the trailers from the film distributors, put the +trailers on tape, and sold the tapes to the retail stores. +

+The company did this for about fifteen years. Then, in 1997, it began to +think about the Internet as another way to distribute these previews. The +idea was to expand their "selling by sampling" technique by giving on-line +stores the same ability to enable "browsing." Just as in a bookstore you can +read a few pages of a book before you buy the book, so, too, you would be +able to sample a bit from the movie on-line before you bought it. +

+ +In 1998, Video Pipeline informed Disney and other film distributors that it +intended to distribute the trailers through the Internet (rather than +sending the tapes) to distributors of their videos. Two years later, Disney +told Video Pipeline to stop. The owner of Video Pipeline asked Disney to +talk about the matter—he had built a business on distributing this +content as a way to help sell Disney films; he had customers who depended +upon his delivering this content. Disney would agree to talk only if Video +Pipeline stopped the distribution immediately. Video Pipeline thought it +was within their "fair use" rights to distribute the clips as they had. So +they filed a lawsuit to ask the court to declare that these rights were in +fact their rights. +

+Disney countersued—for $100 million in damages. Those damages were +predicated upon a claim that Video Pipeline had "willfully infringed" on +Disney's copyright. When a court makes a finding of willful infringement, it +can award damages not on the basis of the actual harm to the copyright +owner, but on the basis of an amount set in the statute. Because Video +Pipeline had distributed seven hundred clips of Disney movies to enable +video stores to sell copies of those movies, Disney was now suing Video +Pipeline for $100 million. +

+Disney has the right to control its property, of course. But the video +stores that were selling Disney's films also had some sort of right to be +able to sell the films that they had bought from Disney. Disney's claim in +court was that the stores were allowed to sell the films and they were +permitted to list the titles of the films they were selling, but they were +not allowed to show clips of the films as a way of selling them without +Disney's permission. +

+Now, you might think this is a close case, and I think the courts would +consider it a close case. My point here is to map the change that gives +Disney this power. Before the Internet, Disney couldn't really control how +people got access to their content. Once a video was in the marketplace, the +"first-sale doctrine" would free the seller to use the video as he wished, +including showing portions of it in order to engender sales of the entire +movie video. But with the Internet, it becomes possible for Disney to +centralize control over access to this content. Because each use of the +Internet produces a copy, use on the Internet becomes subject to the +copyright owner's control. The technology expands the scope of effective +control, because the technology builds a copy into every transaction. +

+ + +No doubt, a potential is not yet an abuse, and so the potential for control +is not yet the abuse of control. Barnes & Noble has the right to say you +can't touch a book in their store; property law gives them that right. But +the market effectively protects against that abuse. If Barnes & Noble +banned browsing, then consumers would choose other bookstores. Competition +protects against the extremes. And it may well be (my argument so far does +not even question this) that competition would prevent any similar danger +when it comes to copyright. Sure, publishers exercising the rights that +authors have assigned to them might try to regulate how many times you read +a book, or try to stop you from sharing the book with anyone. But in a +competitive market such as the book market, the dangers of this happening +are quite slight. +

+Again, my aim so far is simply to map the changes that this changed +architecture enables. Enabling technology to enforce the control of +copyright means that the control of copyright is no longer defined by +balanced policy. The control of copyright is simply what private owners +choose. In some contexts, at least, that fact is harmless. But in some +contexts it is a recipe for disaster. +

Arkitektur og lov: Makt

+The disappearance of unregulated uses would be change enough, but a second +important change brought about by the Internet magnifies its +significance. This second change does not affect the reach of copyright +regulation; it affects how such regulation is enforced. +

+In the world before digital technology, it was generally the law that +controlled whether and how someone was regulated by copyright law. The law, +meaning a court, meaning a judge: In the end, it was a human, trained in the +tradition of the law and cognizant of the balances that tradition embraced, +who said whether and how the law would restrict your freedom. +

+Det er en berømt historie om en kamp mellom Marx-brødrene (the Marx +Brothers) og Warner Brothers. Marx-brødrene planla å lage en parodi av +Casablanca. Warner Brothers protesterte. De skrev et ufint brev til +Marx-brødrene og advarte dem om at det ville få seriøse juridiske +konsekvenser hvis de gikk videre med sin plan.[136] +

+Dette fikk Marx-brødrene til å svare tilbake med samme mynt. De advarte +Warner Brothers om at Marx-brødrene "var brødre lenge før dere var +det".[137] Marx-brødrene eide derfor ordet +Brothers, og hvis Warner Brothers insisterte på å forsøke å kontrollere +Casablanca, så ville Marx-brødrene insistere på kontroll over Brothers. +

+Det var en absurd og hul trussel, selvfølgelig, fordi Warner Brothers, på +samme måte som Marx-brødrene, visste at ingen domstol noensinne ville +håndheve et slikt dumt krav. Denne ekstremismen var irrelevant for de ekte +friheter som alle (inkludert Warner Brothers) nøt godt av. +

+On the Internet, however, there is no check on silly rules, because on the +Internet, increasingly, rules are enforced not by a human but by a machine: +Increasingly, the rules of copyright law, as interpreted by the copyright +owner, get built into the technology that delivers copyrighted content. It +is code, rather than law, that rules. And the problem with code regulations +is that, unlike law, code has no shame. Code would not get the humor of the +Marx Brothers. The consequence of that is not at all funny. +

+La oss se på livet til min Adobe eBook Reader. +

+En ebok er en bok levert i elektronisk form. En Adobe eBook er ikke en bok +som Adobe har publisert. Adobe produserer kun programvaren som utgivere +bruker å levere e-bøker. Den bidrar med teknologien, og utgiveren leverer +innholdet ved hjelp av teknologien. +

+On the next page is a picture of an old version of my Adobe eBook Reader. +

+ +As you can see, I have a small collection of e-books within this e-book +library. Some of these books reproduce content that is in the public domain: +Middlemarch, for example, is in the public domain. Some of them reproduce +content that is not in the public domain: My own book The Future of Ideas is +not yet within the public domain. Consider Middlemarch first. If you click +on my e-book copy of Middlemarch, you'll see a fancy cover, and then a +button at the bottom called Permissions. +

Figur 3.12. Bilde av en gammel versjon av Adobe eBook Reader.

Bilde av en gammel versjon av Adobe eBook Reader.

+If you click on the Permissions button, you'll see a list of the permissions +that the publisher purports to grant with this book. +

Figur 3.13. List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.

List of the permissions that the publisher purports to grant.

+ + +According to my eBook Reader, I have the permission to copy to the clipboard +of the computer ten text selections every ten days. (So far, I've copied no +text to the clipboard.) I also have the permission to print ten pages from +the book every ten days. Lastly, I have the permission to use the Read Aloud +button to hear Middlemarch read aloud through the computer. +

+Here's the e-book for another work in the public domain (including the +translation): Aristotle's Politics. +

Figur 3.14. E-book of Aristotle;s "Politics"

E-book of Aristotle;s "Politics"

+According to its permissions, no printing or copying is permitted at +all. But fortunately, you can use the Read Aloud button to hear the book. +

Figur 3.15. Liste med tillatelser for Aristotles "Politics".

Liste med tillatelser for Aristotles "Politics".

+Finally (and most embarrassingly), here are the permissions for the original +e-book version of my last book, The Future of Ideas: +

Figur 3.16. List of the permissions for "The Future of Ideas".

List of the permissions for "The Future of Ideas".

+Ingen kopiering, ingen utskrift, og våg ikke å prøve å lytte til denne +boken! +

+Now, the Adobe eBook Reader calls these controls "permissions"— as if +the publisher has the power to control how you use these works. For works +under copyright, the copyright owner certainly does have the power—up +to the limits of the copyright law. But for work not under copyright, there +is no such copyright power.[138] When my +e-book of Middlemarch says I have the permission to copy only ten text +selections into the memory every ten days, what that really means is that +the eBook Reader has enabled the publisher to control how I use the book on +my computer, far beyond the control that the law would enable. +

+The control comes instead from the code—from the technology within +which the e-book "lives." Though the e-book says that these are permissions, +they are not the sort of "permissions" that most of us deal with. When a +teenager gets "permission" to stay out till midnight, she knows (unless +she's Cinderella) that she can stay out till 2 A.M., but will suffer a +punishment if she's caught. But when the Adobe eBook Reader says I have the +permission to make ten copies of the text into the computer's memory, that +means that after I've made ten copies, the computer will not make any +more. The same with the printing restrictions: After ten pages, the eBook +Reader will not print any more pages. It's the same with the silly +restriction that says that you can't use the Read Aloud button to read my +book aloud—it's not that the company will sue you if you do; instead, +if you push the Read Aloud button with my book, the machine simply won't +read aloud. +

+ + +These are controls, not permissions. Imagine a world where the Marx Brothers +sold word processing software that, when you tried to type "Warner +Brothers," erased "Brothers" from the sentence. +

+This is the future of copyright law: not so much copyright law as copyright +code. The controls over access to content will not be controls that are +ratified by courts; the controls over access to content will be controls +that are coded by programmers. And whereas the controls that are built into +the law are always to be checked by a judge, the controls that are built +into the technology have no similar built-in check. +

+How significant is this? Isn't it always possible to get around the controls +built into the technology? Software used to be sold with technologies that +limited the ability of users to copy the software, but those were trivial +protections to defeat. Why won't it be trivial to defeat these protections +as well? +

+We've only scratched the surface of this story. Return to the Adobe eBook +Reader. +

+Early in the life of the Adobe eBook Reader, Adobe suffered a public +relations nightmare. Among the books that you could download for free on the +Adobe site was a copy of Alice's Adventures in Wonderland. This wonderful +book is in the public domain. Yet when you clicked on Permissions for that +book, you got the following report: +

Figur 3.17. List of the permissions for "Alice's Adventures in Wonderland".

List of the permissions for "Alice's Adventures in Wonderland".

+ + +Here was a public domain children's book that you were not allowed to copy, +not allowed to lend, not allowed to give, and, as the "permissions" +indicated, not allowed to "read aloud"! +

+The public relations nightmare attached to that final permission. For the +text did not say that you were not permitted to use the Read Aloud button; +it said you did not have the permission to read the book aloud. That led +some people to think that Adobe was restricting the right of parents, for +example, to read the book to their children, which seemed, to say the least, +absurd. +

+Adobe responded quickly that it was absurd to think that it was trying to +restrict the right to read a book aloud. Obviously it was only restricting +the ability to use the Read Aloud button to have the book read aloud. But +the question Adobe never did answer is this: Would Adobe thus agree that a +consumer was free to use software to hack around the restrictions built into +the eBook Reader? If some company (call it Elcomsoft) developed a program to +disable the technological protection built into an Adobe eBook so that a +blind person, say, could use a computer to read the book aloud, would Adobe +agree that such a use of an eBook Reader was fair? Adobe didn't answer +because the answer, however absurd it might seem, is no. +

+The point is not to blame Adobe. Indeed, Adobe is among the most innovative +companies developing strategies to balance open access to content with +incentives for companies to innovate. But Adobe's technology enables +control, and Adobe has an incentive to defend this control. That incentive +is understandable, yet what it creates is often crazy. +

+To see the point in a particularly absurd context, consider a favorite story +of mine that makes the same point. +

+Consider the robotic dog made by Sony named "Aibo." The Aibo learns tricks, +cuddles, and follows you around. It eats only electricity and that doesn't +leave that much of a mess (at least in your house). +

+ +The Aibo is expensive and popular. Fans from around the world have set up +clubs to trade stories. One fan in particular set up a Web site to enable +information about the Aibo dog to be shared. This fan set up aibopet.com +(and aibohack.com, but that resolves to the same site), and on that site he +provided information about how to teach an Aibo to do tricks in addition to +the ones Sony had taught it. +

+"Teach" here has a special meaning. Aibos are just cute computers. You +teach a computer how to do something by programming it differently. So to +say that aibopet.com was giving information about how to teach the dog to do +new tricks is just to say that aibopet.com was giving information to users +of the Aibo pet about how to hack their computer "dog" to make it do new +tricks (thus, aibohack.com). +

+If you're not a programmer or don't know many programmers, the word hack has +a particularly unfriendly connotation. Nonprogrammers hack bushes or +weeds. Nonprogrammers in horror movies do even worse. But to programmers, or +coders, as I call them, hack is a much more positive term. Hack just means +code that enables the program to do something it wasn't originally intended +or enabled to do. If you buy a new printer for an old computer, you might +find the old computer doesn't run, or "drive," the printer. If you +discovered that, you'd later be happy to discover a hack on the Net by +someone who has written a driver to enable the computer to drive the printer +you just bought. +

+Some hacks are easy. Some are unbelievably hard. Hackers as a community like +to challenge themselves and others with increasingly difficult +tasks. There's a certain respect that goes with the talent to hack +well. There's a well-deserved respect that goes with the talent to hack +ethically. +

+The Aibo fan was displaying a bit of both when he hacked the program and +offered to the world a bit of code that would enable the Aibo to dance +jazz. The dog wasn't programmed to dance jazz. It was a clever bit of +tinkering that turned the dog into a more talented creature than Sony had +built. +

+ +I've told this story in many contexts, both inside and outside the United +States. Once I was asked by a puzzled member of the audience, is it +permissible for a dog to dance jazz in the United States? We forget that +stories about the backcountry still flow across much of the world. So let's +just be clear before we continue: It's not a crime anywhere (anymore) to +dance jazz. Nor is it a crime to teach your dog to dance jazz. Nor should it +be a crime (though we don't have a lot to go on here) to teach your robot +dog to dance jazz. Dancing jazz is a completely legal activity. One imagines +that the owner of aibopet.com thought, What possible problem could there be +with teaching a robot dog to dance? +

+Let's put the dog to sleep for a minute, and turn to a pony show— not +literally a pony show, but rather a paper that a Princeton academic named Ed +Felten prepared for a conference. This Princeton academic is well known and +respected. He was hired by the government in the Microsoft case to test +Microsoft's claims about what could and could not be done with its own +code. In that trial, he demonstrated both his brilliance and his +coolness. Under heavy badgering by Microsoft lawyers, Ed Felten stood his +ground. He was not about to be bullied into being silent about something he +knew very well. +

+But Felten's bravery was really tested in April 2001.[139] He and a group of colleagues were working on a +paper to be submitted at conference. The paper was intended to describe the +weakness in an encryption system being developed by the Secure Digital Music +Initiative as a technique to control the distribution of music. +

+The SDMI coalition had as its goal a technology to enable content owners to +exercise much better control over their content than the Internet, as it +originally stood, granted them. Using encryption, SDMI hoped to develop a +standard that would allow the content owner to say "this music cannot be +copied," and have a computer respect that command. The technology was to be +part of a "trusted system" of control that would get content owners to trust +the system of the Internet much more. +

+When SDMI thought it was close to a standard, it set up a competition. In +exchange for providing contestants with the code to an SDMI-encrypted bit of +content, contestants were to try to crack it and, if they did, report the +problems to the consortium. +

+ + +Felten and his team figured out the encryption system quickly. He and the +team saw the weakness of this system as a type: Many encryption systems +would suffer the same weakness, and Felten and his team thought it +worthwhile to point this out to those who study encryption. +

+Let's review just what Felten was doing. Again, this is the United +States. We have a principle of free speech. We have this principle not just +because it is the law, but also because it is a really great idea. A +strongly protected tradition of free speech is likely to encourage a wide +range of criticism. That criticism is likely, in turn, to improve the +systems or people or ideas criticized. +

+What Felten and his colleagues were doing was publishing a paper describing +the weakness in a technology. They were not spreading free music, or +building and deploying this technology. The paper was an academic essay, +unintelligible to most people. But it clearly showed the weakness in the +SDMI system, and why SDMI would not, as presently constituted, succeed. +

+What links these two, aibopet.com and Felten, is the letters they then +received. Aibopet.com received a letter from Sony about the aibopet.com +hack. Though a jazz-dancing dog is perfectly legal, Sony wrote: +

+Your site contains information providing the means to circumvent AIBO-ware's +copy protection protocol constituting a violation of the anti-circumvention +provisions of the Digital Millennium Copyright Act. +

+And though an academic paper describing the weakness in a system of +encryption should also be perfectly legal, Felten received a letter from an +RIAA lawyer that read: +

+ +Any disclosure of information gained from participating in the Public +Challenge would be outside the scope of activities permitted by the +Agreement and could subject you and your research team to actions under the +Digital Millennium Copyright Act ("DMCA"). +

+In both cases, this weirdly Orwellian law was invoked to control the spread +of information. The Digital Millennium Copyright Act made spreading such +information an offense. +

+The DMCA was enacted as a response to copyright owners' first fear about +cyberspace. The fear was that copyright control was effectively dead; the +response was to find technologies that might compensate. These new +technologies would be copyright protection technologies— technologies +to control the replication and distribution of copyrighted material. They +were designed as code to modify the original code of the Internet, to +reestablish some protection for copyright owners. +

+The DMCA was a bit of law intended to back up the protection of this code +designed to protect copyrighted material. It was, we could say, legal code +intended to buttress software code which itself was intended to support the +legal code of copyright. +

+But the DMCA was not designed merely to protect copyrighted works to the +extent copyright law protected them. Its protection, that is, did not end at +the line that copyright law drew. The DMCA regulated devices that were +designed to circumvent copyright protection measures. It was designed to ban +those devices, whether or not the use of the copyrighted material made +possible by that circumvention would have been a copyright violation. +

+ +Aibopet.com and Felten make the point. The Aibo hack circumvented a +copyright protection system for the purpose of enabling the dog to dance +jazz. That enablement no doubt involved the use of copyrighted material. But +as aibopet.com's site was noncommercial, and the use did not enable +subsequent copyright infringements, there's no doubt that aibopet.com's hack +was fair use of Sony's copyrighted material. Yet fair use is not a defense +to the DMCA. The question is not whether the use of the copyrighted material +was a copyright violation. The question is whether a copyright protection +system was circumvented. +

+The threat against Felten was more attenuated, but it followed the same line +of reasoning. By publishing a paper describing how a copyright protection +system could be circumvented, the RIAA lawyer suggested, Felten himself was +distributing a circumvention technology. Thus, even though he was not +himself infringing anyone's copyright, his academic paper was enabling +others to infringe others' copyright. +

+The bizarreness of these arguments is captured in a cartoon drawn in 1981 by +Paul Conrad. At that time, a court in California had held that the VCR could +be banned because it was a copyright-infringing technology: It enabled +consumers to copy films without the permission of the copyright owner. No +doubt there were uses of the technology that were legal: Fred Rogers, aka +"Mr. Rogers," for example, had testified in that case that he wanted people +to feel free to tape Mr. Rogers' Neighborhood. +

+Some public stations, as well as commercial stations, program the +"Neighborhood" at hours when some children cannot use it. I think that it's +a real service to families to be able to record such programs and show them +at appropriate times. I have always felt that with the advent of all of this +new technology that allows people to tape the "Neighborhood" off-the-air, +and I'm speaking for the "Neighborhood" because that's what I produce, that +they then become much more active in the programming of their family's +television life. Very frankly, I am opposed to people being programmed by +others. My whole approach in broadcasting has always been "You are an +important person just the way you are. You can make healthy decisions." +Maybe I'm going on too long, but I just feel that anything that allows a +person to be more active in the control of his or her life, in a healthy +way, is important.[140] +

+ + +Even though there were uses that were legal, because there were some uses +that were illegal, the court held the companies producing the VCR +responsible. +

+This led Conrad to draw the cartoon below, which we can adopt to the DMCA. +

+No argument I have can top this picture, but let me try to get close. +

+The anticircumvention provisions of the DMCA target copyright circumvention +technologies. Circumvention technologies can be used for different +ends. They can be used, for example, to enable massive pirating of +copyrighted material—a bad end. Or they can be used to enable the use +of particular copyrighted materials in ways that would be considered fair +use—a good end. +

+ +A handgun can be used to shoot a police officer or a child. Most would agree +such a use is bad. Or a handgun can be used for target practice or to +protect against an intruder. At least some would say that such a use would +be good. It, too, is a technology that has both good and bad uses. +

Figur 3.18. VCR/handgun cartoon.

VCR/handgun cartoon.

+The obvious point of Conrad's cartoon is the weirdness of a world where guns +are legal, despite the harm they can do, while VCRs (and circumvention +technologies) are illegal. Flash: No one ever died from copyright +circumvention. Yet the law bans circumvention technologies absolutely, +despite the potential that they might do some good, but permits guns, +despite the obvious and tragic harm they do. +

+The Aibo and RIAA examples demonstrate how copyright owners are changing the +balance that copyright law grants. Using code, copyright owners restrict +fair use; using the DMCA, they punish those who would attempt to evade the +restrictions on fair use that they impose through code. Technology becomes a +means by which fair use can be erased; the law of the DMCA backs up that +erasing. +

+This is how code becomes law. The controls built into the technology of copy +and access protection become rules the violation of which is also a +violation of the law. In this way, the code extends the law—increasing +its regulation, even if the subject it regulates (activities that would +otherwise plainly constitute fair use) is beyond the reach of the law. Code +becomes law; code extends the law; code thus extends the control that +copyright owners effect—at least for those copyright holders with the +lawyers who can write the nasty letters that Felten and aibopet.com +received. +

+There is one final aspect of the interaction between architecture and law +that contributes to the force of copyright's regulation. This is the ease +with which infringements of the law can be detected. For contrary to the +rhetoric common at the birth of cyberspace that on the Internet, no one +knows you're a dog, increasingly, given changing technologies deployed on +the Internet, it is easy to find the dog who committed a legal wrong. The +technologies of the Internet are open to snoops as well as sharers, and the +snoops are increasingly good at tracking down the identity of those who +violate the rules. +

+ + +For example, imagine you were part of a Star Trek fan club. You gathered +every month to share trivia, and maybe to enact a kind of fan fiction about +the show. One person would play Spock, another, Captain Kirk. The characters +would begin with a plot from a real story, then simply continue +it.[141] +

+Before the Internet, this was, in effect, a totally unregulated activity. +No matter what happened inside your club room, you would never be interfered +with by the copyright police. You were free in that space to do as you +wished with this part of our culture. You were allowed to build on it as you +wished without fear of legal control. +

+But if you moved your club onto the Internet, and made it generally +available for others to join, the story would be very different. Bots +scouring the Net for trademark and copyright infringement would quickly find +your site. Your posting of fan fiction, depending upon the ownership of the +series that you're depicting, could well inspire a lawyer's threat. And +ignoring the lawyer's threat would be extremely costly indeed. The law of +copyright is extremely efficient. The penalties are severe, and the process +is quick. +

+This change in the effective force of the law is caused by a change in the +ease with which the law can be enforced. That change too shifts the law's +balance radically. It is as if your car transmitted the speed at which you +traveled at every moment that you drove; that would be just one step before +the state started issuing tickets based upon the data you transmitted. That +is, in effect, what is happening here. +

Marked: Konsentrasjon

+ +So copyright's duration has increased dramatically—tripled in the past +thirty years. And copyright's scope has increased as well—from +regulating only publishers to now regulating just about everyone. And +copyright's reach has changed, as every action becomes a copy and hence +presumptively regulated. And as technologists find better ways to control +the use of content, and as copyright is increasingly enforced through +technology, copyright's force changes, too. Misuse is easier to find and +easier to control. This regulation of the creative process, which began as a +tiny regulation governing a tiny part of the market for creative work, has +become the single most important regulator of creativity there is. It is a +massive expansion in the scope of the government's control over innovation +and creativity; it would be totally unrecognizable to those who gave birth +to copyright's control. +

+Still, in my view, all of these changes would not matter much if it weren't +for one more change that we must also consider. This is a change that is in +some sense the most familiar, though its significance and scope are not well +understood. It is the one that creates precisely the reason to be concerned +about all the other changes I have described. +

+This is the change in the concentration and integration of the media. In +the past twenty years, the nature of media ownership has undergone a radical +alteration, caused by changes in legal rules governing the media. Before +this change happened, the different forms of media were owned by separate +media companies. Now, the media is increasingly owned by only a few +companies. Indeed, after the changes that the FCC announced in June 2003, +most expect that within a few years, we will live in a world where just +three companies control more than percent of the media. +

+Det er her to sorter endringer: omfanget av konsentrasjon, og dens natur. +

+Changes in scope are the easier ones to describe. As Senator John McCain +summarized the data produced in the FCC's review of media ownership, "five +companies control 85 percent of our media sources."[142] The five recording labels of Universal Music Group, +BMG, Sony Music Entertainment, Warner Music Group, and EMI control 84.8 +percent of the U.S. music market.[143] The +"five largest cable companies pipe programming to 74 percent of the cable +subscribers nationwide."[144] +

+ +The story with radio is even more dramatic. Before deregulation, the +nation's largest radio broadcasting conglomerate owned fewer than +seventy-five stations. Today one company owns more than 1,200 stations. +During that period of consolidation, the total number of radio owners +dropped by 34 percent. Today, in most markets, the two largest broadcasters +control 74 percent of that market's revenues. Overall, just four companies +control 90 percent of the nation's radio advertising revenues. +

+Newspaper ownership is becoming more concentrated as well. Today, there are +six hundred fewer daily newspapers in the United States than there were +eighty years ago, and ten companies control half of the nation's +circulation. There are twenty major newspaper publishers in the United +States. The top ten film studios receive 99 percent of all film revenue. The +ten largest cable companies account for 85 percent of all cable +revenue. This is a market far from the free press the framers sought to +protect. Indeed, it is a market that is quite well protected— by the +market. +

+Concentration in size alone is one thing. The more invidious change is in +the nature of that concentration. As author James Fallows put it in a recent +article about Rupert Murdoch, +

+Murdoch's companies now constitute a production system unmatched in its +integration. They supply content—Fox movies . . . Fox TV shows +. . . Fox-controlled sports broadcasts, plus newspapers and books. They sell +the content to the public and to advertisers—in newspapers, on the +broadcast network, on the cable channels. And they operate the physical +distribution system through which the content reaches the +customers. Murdoch's satellite systems now distribute News Corp. content in +Europe and Asia; if Murdoch becomes DirecTV's largest single owner, that +system will serve the same function in the United States.[145] +

+The pattern with Murdoch is the pattern of modern media. Not just large +companies owning many radio stations, but a few companies owning as many +outlets of media as possible. A picture describes this pattern better than a +thousand words could do: +

Figur 3.19. Mønster for moderne mediaeierskap.

Mønster for moderne mediaeierskap.

+ + +Does this concentration matter? Will it affect what is made, or what is +distributed? Or is it merely a more efficient way to produce and distribute +content? +

+My view was that concentration wouldn't matter. I thought it was nothing +more than a more efficient financial structure. But now, after reading and +listening to a barrage of creators try to convince me to the contrary, I am +beginning to change my mind. +

+Here's a representative story that begins to suggest how this integration +may matter. +

+In 1969, Norman Lear created a pilot for All in the Family. He took the +pilot to ABC. The network didn't like it. It was too edgy, they told +Lear. Make it again. Lear made a second pilot, more edgy than the first. ABC +was exasperated. You're missing the point, they told Lear. We wanted less +edgy, not more. +

+Rather than comply, Lear simply took the show elsewhere. CBS was happy to +have the series; ABC could not stop Lear from walking. The copyrights that +Lear held assured an independence from network control.[146] +

+ + + +The network did not control those copyrights because the law forbade the +networks from controlling the content they syndicated. The law required a +separation between the networks and the content producers; that separation +would guarantee Lear freedom. And as late as 1992, because of these rules, +the vast majority of prime time television—75 percent of it—was +"independent" of the networks. +

+In 1994, the FCC abandoned the rules that required this independence. After +that change, the networks quickly changed the balance. In 1985, there were +twenty-five independent television production studios; in 2002, only five +independent television studios remained. "In 1992, only 15 percent of new +series were produced for a network by a company it controlled. Last year, +the percentage of shows produced by controlled companies more than +quintupled to 77 percent." "In 1992, 16 new series were produced +independently of conglomerate control, last year there was one."[147] In 2002, 75 percent of prime time television was +owned by the networks that ran it. "In the ten-year period between 1992 and +2002, the number of prime time television hours per week produced by network +studios increased over 200%, whereas the number of prime time television +hours per week produced by independent studios decreased 63%."[148] +

+Today, another Norman Lear with another All in the Family would find that he +had the choice either to make the show less edgy or to be fired: The content +of any show developed for a network is increasingly owned by the network. +

+While the number of channels has increased dramatically, the ownership of +those channels has narrowed to an ever smaller and smaller few. As Barry +Diller said to Bill Moyers, + +

+Well, if you have companies that produce, that finance, that air on their +channel and then distribute worldwide everything that goes through their +controlled distribution system, then what you get is fewer and fewer actual +voices participating in the process. [We u]sed to have dozens and dozens of +thriving independent production companies producing television programs. Now +you have less than a handful.[149] +

+This narrowing has an effect on what is produced. The product of such large +and concentrated networks is increasingly homogenous. Increasingly +safe. Increasingly sterile. The product of news shows from networks like +this is increasingly tailored to the message the network wants to +convey. This is not the communist party, though from the inside, it must +feel a bit like the communist party. No one can question without risk of +consequence—not necessarily banishment to Siberia, but punishment +nonetheless. Independent, critical, different views are quashed. This is not +the environment for a democracy. +

+Economics itself offers a parallel that explains why this integration +affects creativity. Clay Christensen has written about the "Innovator's +Dilemma": the fact that large traditional firms find it rational to ignore +new, breakthrough technologies that compete with their core business. The +same analysis could help explain why large, traditional media companies +would find it rational to ignore new cultural trends.[150] Lumbering giants not only don't, but should not, +sprint. Yet if the field is only open to the giants, there will be far too +little sprinting. +

+I don't think we know enough about the economics of the media market to say +with certainty what concentration and integration will do. The efficiencies +are important, and the effect on culture is hard to measure. +

+But there is a quintessentially obvious example that does strongly suggest +the concern. +

+In addition to the copyright wars, we're in the middle of the drug +wars. Government policy is strongly directed against the drug cartels; +criminal and civil courts are filled with the consequences of this battle. +

+ +Let me hereby disqualify myself from any possible appointment to any +position in government by saying I believe this war is a profound mistake. I +am not pro drugs. Indeed, I come from a family once wrecked by +drugs—though the drugs that wrecked my family were all quite legal. I +believe this war is a profound mistake because the collateral damage from it +is so great as to make waging the war insane. When you add together the +burdens on the criminal justice system, the desperation of generations of +kids whose only real economic opportunities are as drug warriors, the +queering of constitutional protections because of the constant surveillance +this war requires, and, most profoundly, the total destruction of the legal +systems of many South American nations because of the power of the local +drug cartels, I find it impossible to believe that the marginal benefit in +reduced drug consumption by Americans could possibly outweigh these costs. +

+You may not be convinced. That's fine. We live in a democracy, and it is +through votes that we are to choose policy. But to do that, we depend +fundamentally upon the press to help inform Americans about these issues. +

+Beginning in 1998, the Office of National Drug Control Policy launched a +media campaign as part of the "war on drugs." The campaign produced scores +of short film clips about issues related to illegal drugs. In one series +(the Nick and Norm series) two men are in a bar, discussing the idea of +legalizing drugs as a way to avoid some of the collateral damage from the +war. One advances an argument in favor of drug legalization. The other +responds in a powerful and effective way against the argument of the +first. In the end, the first guy changes his mind (hey, it's +television). The plug at the end is a damning attack on the pro-legalization +campaign. +

+Fair enough. It's a good ad. Not terribly misleading. It delivers its +message well. It's a fair and reasonable message. +

+But let's say you think it is a wrong message, and you'd like to run a +countercommercial. Say you want to run a series of ads that try to +demonstrate the extraordinary collateral harm that comes from the drug +war. Can you do it? +

+ +Well, obviously, these ads cost lots of money. Assume you raise the +money. Assume a group of concerned citizens donates all the money in the +world to help you get your message out. Can you be sure your message will be +heard then? +

+No. You cannot. Television stations have a general policy of avoiding +"controversial" ads. Ads sponsored by the government are deemed +uncontroversial; ads disagreeing with the government are controversial. +This selectivity might be thought inconsistent with the First Amendment, but +the Supreme Court has held that stations have the right to choose what they +run. Thus, the major channels of commercial media will refuse one side of a +crucial debate the opportunity to present its case. And the courts will +defend the rights of the stations to be this biased.[151] +

+I'd be happy to defend the networks' rights, as well—if we lived in a +media market that was truly diverse. But concentration in the media throws +that condition into doubt. If a handful of companies control access to the +media, and that handful of companies gets to decide which political +positions it will allow to be promoted on its channels, then in an obvious +and important way, concentration matters. You might like the positions the +handful of companies selects. But you should not like a world in which a +mere few get to decide which issues the rest of us get to know about. +

Sammen

+There is something innocent and obvious about the claim of the copyright +warriors that the government should "protect my property." In the abstract, +it is obviously true and, ordinarily, totally harmless. No sane sort who is +not an anarchist could disagree. +

+ +But when we see how dramatically this "property" has changed— when we +recognize how it might now interact with both technology and markets to mean +that the effective constraint on the liberty to cultivate our culture is +dramatically different—the claim begins to seem less innocent and +obvious. Given (1) the power of technology to supplement the law's control, +and (2) the power of concentrated markets to weaken the opportunity for +dissent, if strictly enforcing the massively expanded "property" rights +granted by copyright fundamentally changes the freedom within this culture +to cultivate and build upon our past, then we have to ask whether this +property should be redefined. +

+Not starkly. Or absolutely. My point is not that we should abolish copyright +or go back to the eighteenth century. That would be a total mistake, +disastrous for the most important creative enterprises within our culture +today. +

+But there is a space between zero and one, Internet culture +notwithstanding. And these massive shifts in the effective power of +copyright regulation, tied to increased concentration of the content +industry and resting in the hands of technology that will increasingly +enable control over the use of culture, should drive us to consider whether +another adjustment is called for. Not an adjustment that increases +copyright's power. Not an adjustment that increases its term. Rather, an +adjustment to restore the balance that has traditionally defined copyright's +regulation—a weakening of that regulation, to strengthen creativity. +

+Copyright law has not been a rock of Gibraltar. It's not a set of constant +commitments that, for some mysterious reason, teenagers and geeks now +flout. Instead, copyright power has grown dramatically in a short period of +time, as the technologies of distribution and creation have changed and as +lobbyists have pushed for more control by copyright holders. Changes in the +past in response to changes in technology suggest that we may well need +similar changes in the future. And these changes have to be reductions in +the scope of copyright, in response to the extraordinary increase in control +that technology and the market enable. +

+ +For the single point that is lost in this war on pirates is a point that we +see only after surveying the range of these changes. When you add together +the effect of changing law, concentrated markets, and changing technology, +together they produce an astonishing conclusion: Never in our history have +fewer had a legal right to control more of the development of our culture +than now. +

+Not when copyrights were perpetual, for when copyrights were perpetual, they +affected only that precise creative work. Not when only publishers had the +tools to publish, for the market then was much more diverse. Not when there +were only three television networks, for even then, newspapers, film +studios, radio stations, and publishers were independent of the +networks. Never has copyright protected such a wide range of rights, against +as broad a range of actors, for a term that was remotely as long. This form +of regulation—a tiny regulation of a tiny part of the creative energy +of a nation at the founding—is now a massive regulation of the overall +creative process. Law plus technology plus the market now interact to turn +this historically benign regulation into the most significant regulation of +culture that our free society has known.[152] +

+This has been a long chapter. Its point can now be briefly stated. +

+At the start of this book, I distinguished between commercial and +noncommercial culture. In the course of this chapter, I have distinguished +between copying a work and transforming it. We can now combine these two +distinctions and draw a clear map of the changes that copyright law has +undergone. In 1790, the law looked like this: +

Tabell 3.1.

 PubliserTRANSFORM
Kommersiell©Fri
Ikke-kommersiellFriFri

+ +The act of publishing a map, chart, and book was regulated by copyright +law. Nothing else was. Transformations were free. And as copyright attached +only with registration, and only those who intended to benefit commercially +would register, copying through publishing of noncommercial work was also +free. +

+By the end of the nineteenth century, the law had changed to this: +

Tabell 3.2.

 PubliserTRANSFORM
Kommersiell©©
Ikke-kommersiellFriFri

+Derivative works were now regulated by copyright law—if published, +which again, given the economics of publishing at the time, means if offered +commercially. But noncommercial publishing and transformation were still +essentially free. +

+In 1909 the law changed to regulate copies, not publishing, and after this +change, the scope of the law was tied to technology. As the technology of +copying became more prevalent, the reach of the law expanded. Thus by 1975, +as photocopying machines became more common, we could say the law began to +look like this: +

Tabell 3.3.

 KopierTRANSFORM
Kommersiell©©
Ikke-kommersiell©/FriFri

+The law was interpreted to reach noncommercial copying through, say, copy +machines, but still much of copying outside of the commercial market +remained free. But the consequence of the emergence of digital technologies, +especially in the context of a digital network, means that the law now looks +like this: +

Tabell 3.4.

 KopierTRANSFORM
Kommersiell©©
Ikke-kommersiell©©

+ +Every realm is governed by copyright law, whereas before most creativity was +not. The law now regulates the full range of creativity— commercial or +not, transformative or not—with the same rules designed to regulate +commercial publishers. +

+Obviously, copyright law is not the enemy. The enemy is regulation that does +no good. So the question that we should be asking just now is whether +extending the regulations of copyright law into each of these domains +actually does any good. +

+I have no doubt that it does good in regulating commercial copying. But I +also have no doubt that it does more harm than good when regulating (as it +regulates just now) noncommercial copying and, especially, noncommercial +transformation. And increasingly, for the reasons sketched especially in +chapters 7 and 8, one might well wonder whether it does more harm than good +for commercial transformation. More commercial transformative work would be +created if derivative rights were more sharply restricted. +

+The issue is therefore not simply whether copyright is property. Of course +copyright is a kind of "property," and of course, as with any property, the +state ought to protect it. But first impressions notwithstanding, +historically, this property right (as with all property rights[153]) has been crafted to balance the important need to +give authors and artists incentives with the equally important need to +assure access to creative work. This balance has always been struck in light +of new technologies. And for almost half of our tradition, the "copyright" +did not control at all the freedom of others to build upon or transform a +creative work. American culture was born free, and for almost 180 years our +country consistently protected a vibrant and rich free culture. +

+ +We achieved that free culture because our law respected important limits on +the scope of the interests protected by "property." The very birth of +"copyright" as a statutory right recognized those limits, by granting +copyright owners protection for a limited time only (the story of chapter +6). The tradition of "fair use" is animated by a similar concern that is +increasingly under strain as the costs of exercising any fair use right +become unavoidably high (the story of chapter 7). Adding statutory rights +where markets might stifle innovation is another familiar limit on the +property right that copyright is (chapter 8). And granting archives and +libraries a broad freedom to collect, claims of property notwithstanding, is +a crucial part of guaranteeing the soul of a culture (chapter 9). Free +cultures, like free markets, are built with property. But the nature of the +property that builds a free culture is very different from the extremist +vision that dominates the debate today. +

+Free culture is increasingly the casualty in this war on piracy. In response +to a real, if not yet quantified, threat that the technologies of the +Internet present to twentieth-century business models for producing and +distributing culture, the law and technology are being transformed in a way +that will undermine our tradition of free culture. The property right that +is copyright is no longer the balanced right that it was, or was intended to +be. The property right that is copyright has become unbalanced, tilted +toward an extreme. The opportunity to create and transform becomes weakened +in a world in which creation requires permission and creativity must check +with a lawyer. +



[96] + + +Letter from Thomas Jefferson to Isaac McPherson (13 August 1813) in The +Writings of Thomas Jefferson, vol. 6 (Andrew A. Lipscomb and Albert Ellery +Bergh, eds., 1903), 330, 333–34. +

[97] + + +As the legal realists taught American law, all property rights are +intangible. A property right is simply a right that an individual has +against the world to do or not do certain things that may or may not attach +to a physical object. The right itself is intangible, even if the object to +which it is (metaphorically) attached is tangible. See Adam Mossoff, "What +Is Property? Putting the Pieces Back Together," Arizona Law Review 45 +(2003): 373, 429 n. 241. +

[98] + + +Jacob Tonson er vanligvis husket for sin omgang med 1700-tallets litterære +storheter, spesielt John Dryden, og for hans kjekke"ferdige versjoner" av +klassiske verk. I tillegg til Romeo og Julie, utga han en utrolig rekke +liste av verk som ennå er hjertet av den engelske kanon, inkludert de +samlede verk av Shakespeare, Ben Jonson, John Milton, og John Dryden. Se +Keith Walker: "Jacob Tonson, Bookseller," American Scholar 61:3 (1992): +424-­31. +

[99] + + +Lyman Ray Patterson, Copyright in Historical Perspective (Nashville: +Vanderbilt University Press, 1968), 151–52. +

[100] + +Som Siva Vaidhyanathan så pent argumenterer, er det feilaktige å kalle dette +en "opphavsrettslov." Se Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs, 40. + +

[101] + + +Philip Wittenberg, The Protection and Marketing of Literary Property (New +York: J. Messner, Inc., 1937), 31. +

[102] + + +A Letter to a Member of Parliament concerning the Bill now depending in the +House of Commons, for making more effectual an Act in the Eighth Year of the +Reign of Queen Anne, entitled, An Act for the Encouragement of Learning, by +Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in the Authors or Purchasers of such +Copies, during the Times therein mentioned (London, 1735), in Brief Amici +Curiae of Tyler T. Ochoa et al., 8, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) +(No. 01-618). +

[103] + +Lyman Ray Patterson, "Free Speech, Copyright, and Fair Use," Vanderbilt Law +Review 40 (1987): 28. For en fantastisk overbevisende fortelling, se +Vaidhyanathan, 37–48. +

[104] + + +For a compelling account, see David Saunders, Authorship and Copyright +(London: Routledge, 1992), 62–69. +

[105] + + +Mark Rose, Authors and Owners (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1993), +92. +

[106] + + +Ibid., 93. +

[107] + + +Lyman Ray Patterson, Copyright in Historical Perspective, 167 (quoting +Borwell). +

[108] + + +Howard B. Abrams, "The Historic Foundation of American Copyright Law: +Exploding the Myth of Common Law Copyright," Wayne Law Review 29 (1983): +1152. +

[109] + + +Ibid., 1156. +

[110] + + +Rose, 97. +

[111] + + +Ibid. +

[112] + + +For an excellent argument that such use is "fair use," but that lawyers +don't permit recognition that it is "fair use," see Richard A. Posner with +William F. Patry, "Fair Use and Statutory Reform in the Wake of Eldred " +(draft on file with author), University of Chicago Law School, 5 August +2003. +

[113] + +Technically, the rights that Alben had to clear were mainly those of +publicity—rights an artist has to control the commercial exploitation +of his image. But these rights, too, burden "Rip, Mix, Burn" creativity, as +this chapter evinces. +

[114] + + +U.S. Department of Commerce Office of Acquisition Management, Seven Steps to +Performance-Based Services Acquisition, available at link #22. +

[115] + + +The temptations remain, however. Brewster Kahle reports that the White House +changes its own press releases without notice. A May 13, 2003, press release +stated, "Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended." That was later changed, +without notice, to "Major Combat Operations in Iraq Have Ended." E-mail from +Brewster Kahle, 1 December 2003. +

[116] + + +Doug Herrick, "Toward a National Film Collection: Motion Pictures at the +Library of Congress," Film Library Quarterly 13 nos. 2–3 (1980): 5; +Anthony Slide, Nitrate Won't Wait: A History of Film Preservation in the +United States ( Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland & Co., 1992), 36. +

[117] + + +Dave Barns, "Fledgling Career in Antique Books: Woodstock Landlord, Bar +Owner Starts a New Chapter by Adopting Business," Chicago Tribune, 5 +September 1997, at Metro Lake 1L. Of books published between 1927 and 1946, +only 2.2 percent were in print in 2002. R. Anthony Reese, "The First Sale +Doctrine in the Era of Digital Networks," Boston College Law Review 44 +(2003): 593 n. 51. +

[118] + + +Home Recording of Copyrighted Works: Hearings on H.R. 4783, H.R. 4794, +H.R. 4808, H.R. 5250, H.R. 5488, and H.R. 5705 Before the Subcommittee on +Courts, Civil Liberties, and the Administration of Justice of the Committee +on the Judiciary of the House of Representatives, 97th Cong., 2nd +sess. (1982): 65 (testimony of Jack Valenti). +

[119] + + +Lawyers speak of "property" not as an absolute thing, but as a bundle of +rights that are sometimes associated with a particular object. Thus, my +"property right" to my car gives me the right to exclusive use, but not the +right to drive at 150 miles an hour. For the best effort to connect the +ordinary meaning of "property" to "lawyer talk," see Bruce Ackerman, Private +Property and the Constitution (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), +26–27. +

[120] + + +By describing the way law affects the other three modalities, I don't mean +to suggest that the other three don't affect law. Obviously, they do. Law's +only distinction is that it alone speaks as if it has a right +self-consciously to change the other three. The right of the other three is +more timidly expressed. See Lawrence Lessig, Code: And Other Laws of +Cyberspace (New York: Basic Books, 1999): 90–95; Lawrence Lessig, "The +New Chicago School," Journal of Legal Studies, June 1998. +

[121] + +Some people object to this way of talking about "liberty." They object +because their focus when considering the constraints that exist at any +particular moment are constraints imposed exclusively by the government. For +instance, if a storm destroys a bridge, these people think it is meaningless +to say that one's liberty has been restrained. A bridge has washed out, and +it's harder to get from one place to another. To talk about this as a loss +of freedom, they say, is to confuse the stuff of politics with the vagaries +of ordinary life. I don't mean to deny the value in this narrower view, +which depends upon the context of the inquiry. I do, however, mean to argue +against any insistence that this narrower view is the only proper view of +liberty. As I argued in Code, we come from a long tradition of political +thought with a broader focus than the narrow question of what the government +did when. John Stuart Mill defended freedom of speech, for example, from +the tyranny of narrow minds, not from the fear of government prosecution; +John Stuart Mill, On Liberty (Indiana: Hackett Publishing Co., 1978), 19. +John R. Commons famously defended the economic freedom of labor from +constraints imposed by the market; John R. Commons, "The Right to Work," in +Malcom Rutherford and Warren J. Samuels, eds., John R. Commons: Selected +Essays (London: Routledge: 1997), 62. The Americans with Disabilities Act +increases the liberty of people with physical disabilities by changing the +architecture of certain public places, thereby making access to those places +easier; 42 United States Code, section 12101 (2000). Each of these +interventions to change existing conditions changes the liberty of a +particular group. The effect of those interventions should be accounted for +in order to understand the effective liberty that each of these groups might +face. +

[122] + + +See Geoffrey Smith, "Film vs. Digital: Can Kodak Build a Bridge?" +BusinessWeek online, 2 August 1999, available at link #23. For a more recent +analysis of Kodak's place in the market, see Chana R. Schoenberger, "Can +Kodak Make Up for Lost Moments?" Forbes.com, 6 October 2003, available at +link #24. +

[123] + + +Fred Warshofsky, The Patent Wars (New York: Wiley, 1994), 170–71. +

[124] + + +Se, for eksempel, James Boyle, "A Politics of Intellectual Property: +Environmentalism for the Net?" Duke Law Journal 47 (1997): 87. +

[125] + +William W. Crosskey, Politics and the Constitution in the History of the +United States (London: Cambridge University Press, 1953), vol. 1, +485–86: "extinguish[ing], by plain implication of `the supreme Law of +the Land,' the perpetual rights which authors had, or were supposed by some +to have, under the Common Law" (emphasis added). +

[126] + + +Although 13,000 titles were published in the United States from 1790 to +1799, only 556 copyright registrations were filed; John Tebbel, A History of +Book Publishing in the United States, vol. 1, The Creation of an Industry, +1630–1865 (New York: Bowker, 1972), 141. Of the 21,000 imprints +recorded before 1790, only twelve were copyrighted under the 1790 act; +William J. Maher, Copyright Term, Retrospective Extension and the Copyright +Law of 1790 in Historical Context, 7–10 (2002), available at link #25. Thus, the +overwhelming majority of works fell immediately into the public domain. Even +those works that were copyrighted fell into the public domain quickly, +because the term of copyright was short. The initial term of copyright was +fourteen years, with the option of renewal for an additional fourteen +years. Copyright Act of May 31, 1790, §1, 1 stat. 124.

[127] + + +Few copyright holders ever chose to renew their copyrights. For instance, of +the 25,006 copyrights registered in 1883, only 894 were renewed in 1910. For +a year-by-year analysis of copyright renewal rates, see Barbara A. Ringer, +"Study No. 31: Renewal of Copyright," Studies on Copyright, vol. 1 (New +York: Practicing Law Institute, 1963), 618. For a more recent and +comprehensive analysis, see William M. Landes and Richard A. Posner, +"Indefinitely Renewable Copyright," University of Chicago Law Review 70 +(2003): 471, 498–501, and accompanying figures.

[128] + + +Se Ringer, kap. 9, n. 2.

[129] + + +These statistics are understated. Between the years 1910 and 1962 (the first +year the renewal term was extended), the average term was never more than +thirty-two years, and averaged thirty years. See Landes and Posner, +"Indefinitely Renewable Copyright," loc. cit. +

[130] + + +See Thomas Bender and David Sampliner, "Poets, Pirates, and the Creation of +American Literature," 29 New York University Journal of International Law +and Politics 255 (1997), and James Gilraeth, ed., Federal Copyright Records, +1790–1800 (U.S. G.P.O., 1987). +

[131] + +Jonathan Zittrain, "The Copyright Cage," Legal Affairs, juli/august 2003, +tilgjengelig fra link +#26. +

[132] + + +Professor Rubenfeld has presented a powerful constitutional argument about +the difference that copyright law should draw (from the perspective of the +First Amendment) between mere "copies" and derivative works. See Jed +Rubenfeld, "The Freedom of Imagination: Copyright's Constitutionality," Yale +Law Journal 112 (2002): 1–60 (see especially pp. 53–59). +

[133] + + +This is a simplification of the law, but not much of one. The law certainly +regulates more than "copies"—a public performance of a copyrighted +song, for example, is regulated even though performance per se doesn't make +a copy; 17 United States Code, section 106(4). And it certainly sometimes +doesn't regulate a "copy"; 17 United States Code, section 112(a). But the +presumption under the existing law (which regulates "copies;" 17 United +States Code, section 102) is that if there is a copy, there is a right. +

[134] + + +Thus, my argument is not that in each place that copyright law extends, we +should repeal it. It is instead that we should have a good argument for its +extending where it does, and should not determine its reach on the basis of +arbitrary and automatic changes caused by technology. +

[135] + + +I don't mean "nature" in the sense that it couldn't be different, but rather +that its present instantiation entails a copy. Optical networks need not +make copies of content they transmit, and a digital network could be +designed to delete anything it copies so that the same number of copies +remain. +

[136] + + +Se David Lange, "Recognizing the Public Domain," Law and Contemporary +Problems 44 (1981): 172–73. +

[137] + +Ibid. Se også Vaidhyanathan, Copyrights and Copywrongs, 1–3. + +

[138] + + +In principle, a contract might impose a requirement on me. I might, for +example, buy a book from you that includes a contract that says I will read +it only three times, or that I promise to read it three times. But that +obligation (and the limits for creating that obligation) would come from the +contract, not from copyright law, and the obligations of contract would not +necessarily pass to anyone who subsequently acquired the book. +

[139] + +See Pamela Samuelson, "Anticircumvention Rules: Threat to Science," Science +293 (2001): 2028; Brendan I. Koerner, "Play Dead: Sony Muzzles the Techies +Who Teach a Robot Dog New Tricks," American Prospect, January 2002; "Court +Dismisses Computer Scientists' Challenge to DMCA," Intellectual Property +Litigation Reporter, 11 December 2001; Bill Holland, "Copyright Act Raising +Free-Speech Concerns," Billboard, May 2001; Janelle Brown, "Is the RIAA +Running Scared?" Salon.com, April 2001; Electronic Frontier Foundation, +"Frequently Asked Questions about Felten and USENIX v. RIAA Legal Case," +available at link #27. + +

[140] + + +Sony Corporation of America v. Universal City Studios, Inc., 464 U.S. 417, +455 fn. 27 (1984). Rogers never changed his view about the VCR. See James +Lardner, Fast Forward: Hollywood, the Japanese, and the Onslaught of the VCR +(New York: W. W. Norton, 1987), 270–71. +

[141] + + +For an early and prescient analysis, see Rebecca Tushnet, "Legal Fictions, +Copyright, Fan Fiction, and a New Common Law," Loyola of Los Angeles +Entertainment Law Journal 17 (1997): 651. +

[142] + + +FCC Oversight: Hearing Before the Senate Commerce, Science and +Transportation Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (22 May 2003) (statement +of Senator John McCain).

[143] + + +Lynette Holloway, "Despite a Marketing Blitz, CD Sales Continue to Slide," +New York Times, 23 December 2002. +

[144] + + +Molly Ivins, "Media Consolidation Must Be Stopped," Charleston Gazette, 31 +May 2003. +

[145] + +James Fallows, "The Age of Murdoch," Atlantic Monthly (september 2003): 89. + +

[146] + + +Leonard Hill, "The Axis of Access," remarks before Weidenbaum Center Forum, +"Entertainment Economics: The Movie Industry," St. Louis, Missouri, 3 April +2003 (transcript of prepared remarks available at link #28; for the Lear story, +not included in the prepared remarks, see link #29). +

[147] + + +NewsCorp./DirecTV Merger and Media Consolidation: Hearings on Media +Ownership Before the Senate Commerce Committee, 108th Cong., 1st +sess. (2003) (testimony of Gene Kimmelman on behalf of Consumers Union and +the Consumer Federation of America), available at link #30. Kimmelman quotes +Victoria Riskin, president of Writers Guild of America, West, in her Remarks +at FCC En Banc Hearing, Richmond, Virginia, 27 February 2003. +

[148] + + +Ibid. +

[149] + + +"Barry Diller Takes on Media Deregulation," Now with Bill Moyers, Bill +Moyers, 25 April 2003, edited transcript available at link #31. +

[150] + + +Clayton M. Christensen, The Innovator's Dilemma: The Revolutionary National +Bestseller that Changed the Way We Do Business (Cambridge: Harvard Business +School Press, 1997). Christensen acknowledges that the idea was first +suggested by Dean Kim Clark. See Kim B. Clark, "The Interaction of Design +Hierarchies and Market Concepts in Technological Evolution," Research Policy +14 (1985): 235–51. For a more recent study, see Richard Foster and +Sarah Kaplan, Creative Destruction: Why Companies That Are Built to Last +Underperform the Market—and How to Successfully Transform Them (New +York: Currency/Doubleday, 2001).

[151] + +The Marijuana Policy Project, in February 2003, sought to place ads that +directly responded to the Nick and Norm series on stations within the +Washington, D.C., area. Comcast rejected the ads as "against [their] +policy." The local NBC affiliate, WRC, rejected the ads without reviewing +them. The local ABC affiliate, WJOA, originally agreed to run the ads and +accepted payment to do so, but later decided not to run the ads and returned +the collected fees. Interview with Neal Levine, 15 October 2003. These +restrictions are, of course, not limited to drug policy. See, for example, +Nat Ives, "On the Issue of an Iraq War, Advocacy Ads Meet with Rejection +from TV Networks," New York Times, 13 March 2003, C4. Outside of +election-related air time there is very little that the FCC or the courts +are willing to do to even the playing field. For a general overview, see +Rhonda Brown, "Ad Hoc Access: The Regulation of Editorial Advertising on +Television and Radio," Yale Law and Policy Review 6 (1988): 449–79, +and for a more recent summary of the stance of the FCC and the courts, see +Radio-Television News Directors Association v. FCC, 184 F. 3d 872 +(D.C. Cir. 1999). Municipal authorities exercise the same authority as the +networks. In a recent example from San Francisco, the San Francisco transit +authority rejected an ad that criticized its Muni diesel buses. Phillip +Matier and Andrew Ross, "Antidiesel Group Fuming After Muni Rejects Ad," +SFGate.com, 16 June 2003, available at link #32. The ground was that +the criticism was "too controversial." +

[152] + +Siva Vaidhyanathan fanger et lignende poeng i hans "fire kapitulasjoner" for +opphavsrettsloven i den digitale tidsalder. Se Vaidhyanathan, 159–60. + +

[153] + + +It was the single most important contribution of the legal realist movement +to demonstrate that all property rights are always crafted to balance public +and private interests. See Thomas C. Grey, "The Disintegration of Property," +in Nomos XXII: Property, J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman, eds. (New +York: New York University Press, 1980). +

Kapittel 4. Nøtter

Kapittel elleve: Chimera

+In a well-known short story by H. G. Wells, a mountain climber named Nunez +trips (literally, down an ice slope) into an unknown and isolated valley in +the Peruvian Andes.[154] The valley is +extraordinarily beautiful, with "sweet water, pasture, an even climate, +slopes of rich brown soil with tangles of a shrub that bore an excellent +fruit." But the villagers are all blind. Nunez takes this as an +opportunity. "In the Country of the Blind," he tells himself, "the One-Eyed +Man is King." So he resolves to live with the villagers to explore life as a +king. +

+Things don't go quite as he planned. He tries to explain the idea of sight +to the villagers. They don't understand. He tells them they are "blind." +They don't have the word blind. They think he's just thick. Indeed, as they +increasingly notice the things he can't do (hear the sound of grass being +stepped on, for example), they increasingly try to control him. He, in turn, +becomes increasingly frustrated. "`You don't understand,' he cried, in a +voice that was meant to be great and resolute, and which broke. `You are +blind and I can see. Leave me alone!'" +

+ + +The villagers don't leave him alone. Nor do they see (so to speak) the +virtue of his special power. Not even the ultimate target of his affection, +a young woman who to him seems "the most beautiful thing in the whole of +creation," understands the beauty of sight. Nunez's description of what he +sees "seemed to her the most poetical of fancies, and she listened to his +description of the stars and the mountains and her own sweet white-lit +beauty as though it was a guilty indulgence." "She did not believe," Wells +tells us, and "she could only half understand, but she was mysteriously +delighted." +

+When Nunez announces his desire to marry his "mysteriously delighted" love, +the father and the village object. "You see, my dear," her father instructs, +"he's an idiot. He has delusions. He can't do anything right." They take +Nunez to the village doctor. +

+After a careful examination, the doctor gives his opinion. "His brain is +affected," he reports. +

+"What affects it?" the father asks. "Those queer things that are called the +eyes . . . are diseased . . . in such a way as to affect his brain." +

+The doctor continues: "I think I may say with reasonable certainty that in +order to cure him completely, all that we need to do is a simple and easy +surgical operation—namely, to remove these irritant bodies [the +eyes]." +

+ +"Thank Heaven for science!" says the father to the doctor. They inform Nunez +of this condition necessary for him to be allowed his bride. (You'll have +to read the original to learn what happens in the end. I believe in free +culture, but never in giving away the end of a story.) It sometimes happens +that the eggs of twins fuse in the mother's womb. That fusion produces a +"chimera." A chimera is a single creature with two sets of DNA. The DNA in +the blood, for example, might be different from the DNA of the skin. This +possibility is an underused plot for murder mysteries. "But the DNA shows +with 100 percent certainty that she was not the person whose blood was at +the scene. . . ." +

+Before I had read about chimeras, I would have said they were impossible. A +single person can't have two sets of DNA. The very idea of DNA is that it is +the code of an individual. Yet in fact, not only can two individuals have +the same set of DNA (identical twins), but one person can have two different +sets of DNA (a chimera). Our understanding of a "person" should reflect this +reality. +

+The more I work to understand the current struggle over copyright and +culture, which I've sometimes called unfairly, and sometimes not unfairly +enough, "the copyright wars," the more I think we're dealing with a +chimera. For example, in the battle over the question "What is p2p file +sharing?" both sides have it right, and both sides have it wrong. One side +says, "File sharing is just like two kids taping each others' +records—the sort of thing we've been doing for the last thirty years +without any question at all." That's true, at least in part. When I tell my +best friend to try out a new CD that I've bought, but rather than just send +the CD, I point him to my p2p server, that is, in all relevant respects, +just like what every executive in every recording company no doubt did as a +kid: sharing music. +

+But the description is also false in part. For when my p2p server is on a +p2p network through which anyone can get access to my music, then sure, my +friends can get access, but it stretches the meaning of "friends" beyond +recognition to say "my ten thousand best friends" can get access. Whether or +not sharing my music with my best friend is what "we have always been +allowed to do," we have not always been allowed to share music with "our ten +thousand best friends." +

+Likewise, when the other side says, "File sharing is just like walking into +a Tower Records and taking a CD off the shelf and walking out with it," +that's true, at least in part. If, after Lyle Lovett (finally) releases a +new album, rather than buying it, I go to Kazaa and find a free copy to +take, that is very much like stealing a copy from Tower. +

+ + + +But it is not quite stealing from Tower. After all, when I take a CD from +Tower Records, Tower has one less CD to sell. And when I take a CD from +Tower Records, I get a bit of plastic and a cover, and something to show on +my shelves. (And, while we're at it, we could also note that when I take a +CD from Tower Records, the maximum fine that might be imposed on me, under +California law, at least, is $1,000. According to the RIAA, by contrast, if +I download a ten-song CD, I'm liable for $1,500,000 in damages.) +

+The point is not that it is as neither side describes. The point is that it +is both—both as the RIAA describes it and as Kazaa describes it. It is +a chimera. And rather than simply denying what the other side asserts, we +need to begin to think about how we should respond to this chimera. What +rules should govern it? +

+We could respond by simply pretending that it is not a chimera. We could, +with the RIAA, decide that every act of file sharing should be a felony. We +could prosecute families for millions of dollars in damages just because +file sharing occurred on a family computer. And we can get universities to +monitor all computer traffic to make sure that no computer is used to commit +this crime. These responses might be extreme, but each of them has either +been proposed or actually implemented.[155] + +

+Alternatively, we could respond to file sharing the way many kids act as +though we've responded. We could totally legalize it. Let there be no +copyright liability, either civil or criminal, for making copyrighted +content available on the Net. Make file sharing like gossip: regulated, if +at all, by social norms but not by law. +

+Either response is possible. I think either would be a mistake. Rather than +embrace one of these two extremes, we should embrace something that +recognizes the truth in both. And while I end this book with a sketch of a +system that does just that, my aim in the next chapter is to show just how +awful it would be for us to adopt the zero-tolerance extreme. I believe +either extreme would be worse than a reasonable alternative. But I believe +the zero-tolerance solution would be the worse of the two extremes. +

+ + + +Yet zero tolerance is increasingly our government's policy. In the middle of +the chaos that the Internet has created, an extraordinary land grab is +occurring. The law and technology are being shifted to give content holders +a kind of control over our culture that they have never had before. And in +this extremism, many an opportunity for new innovation and new creativity +will be lost. +

+I'm not talking about the opportunities for kids to "steal" music. My focus +instead is the commercial and cultural innovation that this war will also +kill. We have never seen the power to innovate spread so broadly among our +citizens, and we have just begun to see the innovation that this power will +unleash. Yet the Internet has already seen the passing of one cycle of +innovation around technologies to distribute content. The law is responsible +for this passing. As the vice president for global public policy at one of +these new innovators, eMusic.com, put it when criticizing the DMCA's added +protection for copyrighted material, +

+eMusic opposes music piracy. We are a distributor of copyrighted material, +and we want to protect those rights. +

+But building a technology fortress that locks in the clout of the major +labels is by no means the only way to protect copyright interests, nor is it +necessarily the best. It is simply too early to answer that question. Market +forces operating naturally may very well produce a totally different +industry model. +

+This is a critical point. The choices that industry sectors make with +respect to these systems will in many ways directly shape the market for +digital media and the manner in which digital media are distributed. This in +turn will directly influence the options that are available to consumers, +both in terms of the ease with which they will be able to access digital +media and the equipment that they will require to do so. Poor choices made +this early in the game will retard the growth of this market, hurting +everyone's interests.[156] +

+In April 2001, eMusic.com was purchased by Vivendi Universal, one of "the +major labels." Its position on these matters has now changed. +

+Reversing our tradition of tolerance now will not merely quash piracy. It +will sacrifice values that are important to this culture, and will kill +opportunities that could be extraordinarily valuable. +

Kapittel tolv: Skader

+ +To fight "piracy," to protect "property," the content industry has launched +a war. Lobbying and lots of campaign contributions have now brought the +government into this war. As with any war, this one will have both direct +and collateral damage. As with any war of prohibition, these damages will be +suffered most by our own people. +

+My aim so far has been to describe the consequences of this war, in +particular, the consequences for "free culture." But my aim now is to extend +this description of consequences into an argument. Is this war justified? +

+In my view, it is not. There is no good reason why this time, for the first +time, the law should defend the old against the new, just when the power of +the property called "intellectual property" is at its greatest in our +history. +

+Yet "common sense" does not see it this way. Common sense is still on the +side of the Causbys and the content industry. The extreme claims of control +in the name of property still resonate; the uncritical rejection of "piracy" +still has play. +

+ + +There will be many consequences of continuing this war. I want to describe +just three. All three might be said to be unintended. I am quite confident +the third is unintended. I'm less sure about the first two. The first two +protect modern RCAs, but there is no Howard Armstrong in the wings to fight +today's monopolists of culture. +

Constraining Creators

+In the next ten years we will see an explosion of digital technologies. +These technologies will enable almost anyone to capture and share +content. Capturing and sharing content, of course, is what humans have done +since the dawn of man. It is how we learn and communicate. But capturing and +sharing through digital technology is different. The fidelity and power are +different. You could send an e-mail telling someone about a joke you saw on +Comedy Central, or you could send the clip. You could write an essay about +the inconsistencies in the arguments of the politician you most love to +hate, or you could make a short film that puts statement against +statement. You could write a poem to express your love, or you could weave +together a string—a mash-up— of songs from your favorite artists +in a collage and make it available on the Net. +

+This digital "capturing and sharing" is in part an extension of the +capturing and sharing that has always been integral to our culture, and in +part it is something new. It is continuous with the Kodak, but it explodes +the boundaries of Kodak-like technologies. The technology of digital +"capturing and sharing" promises a world of extraordinarily diverse +creativity that can be easily and broadly shared. And as that creativity is +applied to democracy, it will enable a broad range of citizens to use +technology to express and criticize and contribute to the culture all +around. +

+ +Teknologien har dermed gitt oss en mulighet til å gjøre noe med kultur som +bare har vært mulig for enkeltpersoner i små grupper, isolert fra andre +grupper. Forestill deg en gammel mann som forteller en historie til en +samling med naboer i en liten landsby. Forestill deg så den samme +historiefortellingen utvidet til å nå over hele verden. +

+Yet all this is possible only if the activity is presumptively legal. In the +current regime of legal regulation, it is not. Forget file sharing for a +moment. Think about your favorite amazing sites on the Net. Web sites that +offer plot summaries from forgotten television shows; sites that catalog +cartoons from the 1960s; sites that mix images and sound to criticize +politicians or businesses; sites that gather newspaper articles on remote +topics of science or culture. There is a vast amount of creative work spread +across the Internet. But as the law is currently crafted, this work is +presumptively illegal. +

+That presumption will increasingly chill creativity, as the examples of +extreme penalties for vague infringements continue to proliferate. It is +impossible to get a clear sense of what's allowed and what's not, and at the +same time, the penalties for crossing the line are astonishingly harsh. The +four students who were threatened by the RIAA ( Jesse Jordan of chapter 3 +was just one) were threatened with a $98 billion lawsuit for building search +engines that permitted songs to be copied. Yet World-Com—which +defrauded investors of $11 billion, resulting in a loss to investors in +market capitalization of over $200 billion—received a fine of a mere +$750 million.[157] And under legislation +being pushed in Congress right now, a doctor who negligently removes the +wrong leg in an operation would be liable for no more than $250,000 in +damages for pain and suffering.[158] Can +common sense recognize the absurdity in a world where the maximum fine for +downloading two songs off the Internet is more than the fine for a doctor's +negligently butchering a patient? +

+The consequence of this legal uncertainty, tied to these extremely high +penalties, is that an extraordinary amount of creativity will either never +be exercised, or never be exercised in the open. We drive this creative +process underground by branding the modern-day Walt Disneys "pirates." We +make it impossible for businesses to rely upon a public domain, because the +boundaries of the public domain are designed to be unclear. It never pays to +do anything except pay for the right to create, and hence only those who can +pay are allowed to create. As was the case in the Soviet Union, though for +very different reasons, we will begin to see a world of underground +art—not because the message is necessarily political, or because the +subject is controversial, but because the very act of creating the art is +legally fraught. Already, exhibits of "illegal art" tour the United +States.[159] In what does their "illegality" +consist? In the act of mixing the culture around us with an expression that +is critical or reflective. +

+Part of the reason for this fear of illegality has to do with the changing +law. I described that change in detail in chapter 10. But an even bigger +part has to do with the increasing ease with which infractions can be +tracked. As users of file-sharing systems discovered in 2002, it is a +trivial matter for copyright owners to get courts to order Internet service +providers to reveal who has what content. It is as if your cassette tape +player transmitted a list of the songs that you played in the privacy of +your own home that anyone could tune into for whatever reason they chose. +

+Never in our history has a painter had to worry about whether his painting +infringed on someone else's work; but the modern-day painter, using the +tools of Photoshop, sharing content on the Web, must worry all the +time. Images are all around, but the only safe images to use in the act of +creation are those purchased from Corbis or another image farm. And in +purchasing, censoring happens. There is a free market in pencils; we needn't +worry about its effect on creativity. But there is a highly regulated, +monopolized market in cultural icons; the right to cultivate and transform +them is not similarly free. +

+Lawyers rarely see this because lawyers are rarely empirical. As I described +in chapter 7, in response to the story about documentary filmmaker Jon Else, +I have been lectured again and again by lawyers who insist Else's use was +fair use, and hence I am wrong to say that the law regulates such a use. +

+ + + +But fair use in America simply means the right to hire a lawyer to defend +your right to create. And as lawyers love to forget, our system for +defending rights such as fair use is astonishingly bad—in practically +every context, but especially here. It costs too much, it delivers too +slowly, and what it delivers often has little connection to the justice +underlying the claim. The legal system may be tolerable for the very rich. +For everyone else, it is an embarrassment to a tradition that prides itself +on the rule of law. +

+Judges and lawyers can tell themselves that fair use provides adequate +"breathing room" between regulation by the law and the access the law should +allow. But it is a measure of how out of touch our legal system has become +that anyone actually believes this. The rules that publishers impose upon +writers, the rules that film distributors impose upon filmmakers, the rules +that newspapers impose upon journalists— these are the real laws +governing creativity. And these rules have little relationship to the "law" +with which judges comfort themselves. +

+For in a world that threatens $150,000 for a single willful infringement of +a copyright, and which demands tens of thousands of dollars to even defend +against a copyright infringement claim, and which would never return to the +wrongfully accused defendant anything of the costs she suffered to defend +her right to speak—in that world, the astonishingly broad regulations +that pass under the name "copyright" silence speech and creativity. And in +that world, it takes a studied blindness for people to continue to believe +they live in a culture that is free. +

+As Jed Horovitz, the businessman behind Video Pipeline, said to me, +

+ +We're losing [creative] opportunities right and left. Creative people are +being forced not to express themselves. Thoughts are not being +expressed. And while a lot of stuff may [still] be created, it still won't +get distributed. Even if the stuff gets made . . . you're not going to get +it distributed in the mainstream media unless you've got a little note from +a lawyer saying, "This has been cleared." You're not even going to get it on +PBS without that kind of permission. That's the point at which they control +it. +

Constraining Innovators

+The story of the last section was a crunchy-lefty story—creativity +quashed, artists who can't speak, yada yada yada. Maybe that doesn't get you +going. Maybe you think there's enough weird art out there, and enough +expression that is critical of what seems to be just about everything. And +if you think that, you might think there's little in this story to worry +you. +

+But there's an aspect of this story that is not lefty in any sense. Indeed, +it is an aspect that could be written by the most extreme promarket +ideologue. And if you're one of these sorts (and a special one at that, 188 +pages into a book like this), then you can see this other aspect by +substituting "free market" every place I've spoken of "free culture." The +point is the same, even if the interests affecting culture are more +fundamental. +

+The charge I've been making about the regulation of culture is the same +charge free marketers make about regulating markets. Everyone, of course, +concedes that some regulation of markets is necessary—at a minimum, we +need rules of property and contract, and courts to enforce both. Likewise, +in this culture debate, everyone concedes that at least some framework of +copyright is also required. But both perspectives vehemently insist that +just because some regulation is good, it doesn't follow that more regulation +is better. And both perspectives are constantly attuned to the ways in which +regulation simply enables the powerful industries of today to protect +themselves against the competitors of tomorrow. +

+ +This is the single most dramatic effect of the shift in regulatory strategy +that I described in chapter 10. The consequence of this massive threat of +liability tied to the murky boundaries of copyright law is that innovators +who want to innovate in this space can safely innovate only if they have the +sign-off from last generation's dominant industries. That lesson has been +taught through a series of cases that were designed and executed to teach +venture capitalists a lesson. That lesson—what former Napster CEO Hank +Barry calls a "nuclear pall" that has fallen over the Valley—has been +learned. +

+Consider one example to make the point, a story whose beginning I told in +The Future of Ideas and which has progressed in a way that even I (pessimist +extraordinaire) would never have predicted. +

+In 1997, Michael Roberts launched a company called MP3.com. MP3.com was +keen to remake the music business. Their goal was not just to facilitate new +ways to get access to content. Their goal was also to facilitate new ways to +create content. Unlike the major labels, MP3.com offered creators a venue to +distribute their creativity, without demanding an exclusive engagement from +the creators. +

+To make this system work, however, MP3.com needed a reliable way to +recommend music to its users. The idea behind this alternative was to +leverage the revealed preferences of music listeners to recommend new +artists. If you like Lyle Lovett, you're likely to enjoy Bonnie Raitt. And +so on. +

+This idea required a simple way to gather data about user preferences. +MP3.com came up with an extraordinarily clever way to gather this preference +data. In January 2000, the company launched a service called +my.mp3.com. Using software provided by MP3.com, a user would sign into an +account and then insert into her computer a CD. The software would identify +the CD, and then give the user access to that content. So, for example, if +you inserted a CD by Jill Sobule, then wherever you were—at work or at +home—you could get access to that music once you signed into your +account. The system was therefore a kind of music-lockbox. +

+ +No doubt some could use this system to illegally copy content. But that +opportunity existed with or without MP3.com. The aim of the my.mp3.com +service was to give users access to their own content, and as a by-product, +by seeing the content they already owned, to discover the kind of content +the users liked. +

+To make this system function, however, MP3.com needed to copy 50,000 CDs to +a server. (In principle, it could have been the user who uploaded the music, +but that would have taken a great deal of time, and would have produced a +product of questionable quality.) It therefore purchased 50,000 CDs from a +store, and started the process of making copies of those CDs. Again, it +would not serve the content from those copies to anyone except those who +authenticated that they had a copy of the CD they wanted to access. So while +this was 50,000 copies, it was 50,000 copies directed at giving customers +something they had already bought. +

+Nine days after MP3.com launched its service, the five major labels, headed +by the RIAA, brought a lawsuit against MP3.com. MP3.com settled with four of +the five. Nine months later, a federal judge found MP3.com to have been +guilty of willful infringement with respect to the fifth. Applying the law +as it is, the judge imposed a fine against MP3.com of $118 million. MP3.com +then settled with the remaining plaintiff, Vivendi Universal, paying over +$54 million. Vivendi purchased MP3.com just about a year later. +

+Den delen av historien har jeg fortalt før. Nå kommer konklusjonen. +

+After Vivendi purchased MP3.com, Vivendi turned around and filed a +malpractice lawsuit against the lawyers who had advised it that they had a +good faith claim that the service they wanted to offer would be considered +legal under copyright law. This lawsuit alleged that it should have been +obvious that the courts would find this behavior illegal; therefore, this +lawsuit sought to punish any lawyer who had dared to suggest that the law +was less restrictive than the labels demanded. +

+ +Den åpenbare hensikten med dette søksmålet (som ble avsluttet med et forlik +for et uspesifisert beløp like etter at saken ikke lenger fikk +pressedekning), var å sende en melding som ikke kan misforstås til advokater +som gir råd til klienter på dette området: Det er ikke bare dine klienter +som får lide hvis innholdsindustrien retter sine våpen mot dem. Det får +også du. Så de av dere som tror loven burde være mindre restriktiv bør +innse at et slikt syn på loven vil koste deg og ditt firma dyrt. +

+This strategy is not just limited to the lawyers. In April 2003, Universal +and EMI brought a lawsuit against Hummer Winblad, the venture capital firm +(VC) that had funded Napster at a certain stage of its development, its +cofounder ( John Hummer), and general partner (Hank Barry).[160] The claim here, as well, was that the VC should +have recognized the right of the content industry to control how the +industry should develop. They should be held personally liable for funding a +company whose business turned out to be beyond the law. Here again, the aim +of the lawsuit is transparent: Any VC now recognizes that if you fund a +company whose business is not approved of by the dinosaurs, you are at risk +not just in the marketplace, but in the courtroom as well. Your investment +buys you not only a company, it also buys you a lawsuit. So extreme has the +environment become that even car manufacturers are afraid of technologies +that touch content. In an article in Business 2.0, Rafe Needleman describes +a discussion with BMW: +

+I asked why, with all the storage capacity and computer power in the car, +there was no way to play MP3 files. I was told that BMW engineers in Germany +had rigged a new vehicle to play MP3s via the car's built-in sound system, +but that the company's marketing and legal departments weren't comfortable +with pushing this forward for release stateside. Even today, no new cars are +sold in the United States with bona fide MP3 players. . . . [161] +

+Dette er verden til mafiaen—fylt med "penger eller livet"-trusler, som +ikke er regulert av domstolene men av trusler som loven gir +rettighetsinnehaver mulighet til å komme med. Det er et system som åpenbart +og nødvendigvis vil kvele ny innovasjon. Det er vanskelig nok å starte et +selskap. Det blir helt umulig hvis selskapet er stadig truet av søksmål. +

+ + + +The point is not that businesses should have a right to start illegal +enterprises. The point is the definition of "illegal." The law is a mess of +uncertainty. We have no good way to know how it should apply to new +technologies. Yet by reversing our tradition of judicial deference, and by +embracing the astonishingly high penalties that copyright law imposes, that +uncertainty now yields a reality which is far more conservative than is +right. If the law imposed the death penalty for parking tickets, we'd not +only have fewer parking tickets, we'd also have much less driving. The same +principle applies to innovation. If innovation is constantly checked by this +uncertain and unlimited liability, we will have much less vibrant innovation +and much less creativity. +

+The point is directly parallel to the crunchy-lefty point about fair +use. Whatever the "real" law is, realism about the effect of law in both +contexts is the same. This wildly punitive system of regulation will +systematically stifle creativity and innovation. It will protect some +industries and some creators, but it will harm industry and creativity +generally. Free market and free culture depend upon vibrant competition. +Yet the effect of the law today is to stifle just this kind of competition. +The effect is to produce an overregulated culture, just as the effect of too +much control in the market is to produce an overregulatedregulated market. +

+ +The building of a permission culture, rather than a free culture, is the +first important way in which the changes I have described will burden +innovation. A permission culture means a lawyer's culture—a culture in +which the ability to create requires a call to your lawyer. Again, I am not +antilawyer, at least when they're kept in their proper place. I am certainly +not antilaw. But our profession has lost the sense of its limits. And +leaders in our profession have lost an appreciation of the high costs that +our profession imposes upon others. The inefficiency of the law is an +embarrassment to our tradition. And while I believe our profession should +therefore do everything it can to make the law more efficient, it should at +least do everything it can to limit the reach of the law where the law is +not doing any good. The transaction costs buried within a permission culture +are enough to bury a wide range of creativity. Someone needs to do a lot of +justifying to justify that result. The uncertainty of the law is one burden +on innovation. There is a second burden that operates more directly. This is +the effort by many in the content industry to use the law to directly +regulate the technology of the Internet so that it better protects their +content. +

+The motivation for this response is obvious. The Internet enables the +efficient spread of content. That efficiency is a feature of the Internet's +design. But from the perspective of the content industry, this feature is a +"bug." The efficient spread of content means that content distributors have +a harder time controlling the distribution of content. One obvious response +to this efficiency is thus to make the Internet less efficient. If the +Internet enables "piracy," then, this response says, we should break the +kneecaps of the Internet. +

+The examples of this form of legislation are many. At the urging of the +content industry, some in Congress have threatened legislation that would +require computers to determine whether the content they access is protected +or not, and to disable the spread of protected content.[162] Congress has already launched proceedings to +explore a mandatory "broadcast flag" that would be required on any device +capable of transmitting digital video (i.e., a computer), and that would +disable the copying of any content that is marked with a broadcast +flag. Other members of Congress have proposed immunizing content providers +from liability for technology they might deploy that would hunt down +copyright violators and disable their machines.[163] + +

+ +In one sense, these solutions seem sensible. If the problem is the code, why +not regulate the code to remove the problem. But any regulation of technical +infrastructure will always be tuned to the particular technology of the +day. It will impose significant burdens and costs on the technology, but +will likely be eclipsed by advances around exactly those requirements. +

+In March 2002, a broad coalition of technology companies, led by Intel, +tried to get Congress to see the harm that such legislation would +impose.[164] Their argument was obviously +not that copyright should not be protected. Instead, they argued, any +protection should not do more harm than good. +

+There is one more obvious way in which this war has harmed +innovation—again, a story that will be quite familiar to the free +market crowd. +

+Copyright may be property, but like all property, it is also a form of +regulation. It is a regulation that benefits some and harms others. When +done right, it benefits creators and harms leeches. When done wrong, it is +regulation the powerful use to defeat competitors. +

+As I described in chapter 10, despite this feature of copyright as +regulation, and subject to important qualifications outlined by Jessica +Litman in her book Digital Copyright,[165] +overall this history of copyright is not bad. As chapter 10 details, when +new technologies have come along, Congress has struck a balance to assure +that the new is protected from the old. Compulsory, or statutory, licenses +have been one part of that strategy. Free use (as in the case of the VCR) +has been another. +

+But that pattern of deference to new technologies has now changed with the +rise of the Internet. Rather than striking a balance between the claims of a +new technology and the legitimate rights of content creators, both the +courts and Congress have imposed legal restrictions that will have the +effect of smothering the new to benefit the old. +

+The response by the courts has been fairly universal.[166] It has been mirrored in the responses threatened +and actually implemented by Congress. I won't catalog all of those responses +here.[167] But there is one example that +captures the flavor of them all. This is the story of the demise of Internet +radio. +

+ + + +As I described in chapter 4, when a radio station plays a song, the +recording artist doesn't get paid for that "radio performance" unless he or +she is also the composer. So, for example if Marilyn Monroe had recorded a +version of "Happy Birthday"—to memorialize her famous performance +before President Kennedy at Madison Square Garden— then whenever that +recording was played on the radio, the current copyright owners of "Happy +Birthday" would get some money, whereas Marilyn Monroe would not. +

+The reasoning behind this balance struck by Congress makes some sense. The +justification was that radio was a kind of advertising. The recording artist +thus benefited because by playing her music, the radio station was making it +more likely that her records would be purchased. Thus, the recording artist +got something, even if only indirectly. Probably this reasoning had less to +do with the result than with the power of radio stations: Their lobbyists +were quite good at stopping any efforts to get Congress to require +compensation to the recording artists. +

+Enter Internet radio. Like regular radio, Internet radio is a technology to +stream content from a broadcaster to a listener. The broadcast travels +across the Internet, not across the ether of radio spectrum. Thus, I can +"tune in" to an Internet radio station in Berlin while sitting in San +Francisco, even though there's no way for me to tune in to a regular radio +station much beyond the San Francisco metropolitan area. +

+This feature of the architecture of Internet radio means that there are +potentially an unlimited number of radio stations that a user could tune in +to using her computer, whereas under the existing architecture for broadcast +radio, there is an obvious limit to the number of broadcasters and clear +broadcast frequencies. Internet radio could therefore be more competitive +than regular radio; it could provide a wider range of selections. And +because the potential audience for Internet radio is the whole world, niche +stations could easily develop and market their content to a relatively large +number of users worldwide. According to some estimates, more than eighty +million users worldwide have tuned in to this new form of radio. +

+ + + +Internet radio is thus to radio what FM was to AM. It is an improvement +potentially vastly more significant than the FM improvement over AM, since +not only is the technology better, so, too, is the competition. Indeed, +there is a direct parallel between the fight to establish FM radio and the +fight to protect Internet radio. As one author describes Howard Armstrong's +struggle to enable FM radio, +

+An almost unlimited number of FM stations was possible in the shortwaves, +thus ending the unnatural restrictions imposed on radio in the crowded +longwaves. If FM were freely developed, the number of stations would be +limited only by economics and competition rather than by technical +restrictions. . . . Armstrong likened the situation that had grown up in +radio to that following the invention of the printing press, when +governments and ruling interests attempted to control this new instrument of +mass communications by imposing restrictive licenses on it. This tyranny was +broken only when it became possible for men freely to acquire printing +presses and freely to run them. FM in this sense was as great an invention +as the printing presses, for it gave radio the opportunity to strike off its +shackles.[168] +

+This potential for FM radio was never realized—not because Armstrong +was wrong about the technology, but because he underestimated the power of +"vested interests, habits, customs and legislation"[169] to retard the growth of this competing technology. +

+Now the very same claim could be made about Internet radio. For again, there +is no technical limitation that could restrict the number of Internet radio +stations. The only restrictions on Internet radio are those imposed by the +law. Copyright law is one such law. So the first question we should ask is, +what copyright rules would govern Internet radio? +

+ +But here the power of the lobbyists is reversed. Internet radio is a new +industry. The recording artists, on the other hand, have a very powerful +lobby, the RIAA. Thus when Congress considered the phenomenon of Internet +radio in 1995, the lobbyists had primed Congress to adopt a different rule +for Internet radio than the rule that applies to terrestrial radio. While +terrestrial radio does not have to pay our hypothetical Marilyn Monroe when +it plays her hypothetical recording of "Happy Birthday" on the air, Internet +radio does. Not only is the law not neutral toward Internet radio—the +law actually burdens Internet radio more than it burdens terrestrial radio. +

+This financial burden is not slight. As Harvard law professor William Fisher +estimates, if an Internet radio station distributed adfree popular music to +(on average) ten thousand listeners, twenty-four hours a day, the total +artist fees that radio station would owe would be over $1 million a +year.[170] A regular radio station +broadcasting the same content would pay no equivalent fee. +

+The burden is not financial only. Under the original rules that were +proposed, an Internet radio station (but not a terrestrial radio station) +would have to collect the following data from every listening transaction: +

  1. +name of the service; +

  2. +channel of the program (AM/FM stations use station ID); +

  3. +type of program (archived/looped/live); +

  4. +date of transmission; +

  5. +time of transmission; +

  6. +time zone of origination of transmission; +

  7. +numeric designation of the place of the sound recording within the program; +

  8. +duration of transmission (to nearest second); +

  9. +sound recording title; +

  10. +ISRC code of the recording; +

  11. +release year of the album per copyright notice and in the case of +compilation albums, the release year of the album and copy- right date of +the track; +

  12. +featured recording artist; +

  13. +retail album title; +

  14. +recording label; +

  15. +UPC code of the retail album; +

  16. +catalog number; +

  17. +copyright owner information; +

  18. +musical genre of the channel or program (station format); +

  19. +name of the service or entity; +

  20. +channel or program; +

  21. +date and time that the user logged in (in the user's time zone); +

  22. +date and time that the user logged out (in the user's time zone); +

  23. +time zone where the signal was received (user); +

  24. +Unique User identifier; +

  25. +the country in which the user received the transmissions. +

+The Librarian of Congress eventually suspended these reporting requirements, +pending further study. And he also changed the original rates set by the +arbitration panel charged with setting rates. But the basic difference +between Internet radio and terrestrial radio remains: Internet radio has to +pay a type of copyright fee that terrestrial radio does not. +

+Why? What justifies this difference? Was there any study of the economic +consequences from Internet radio that would justify these differences? Was +the motive to protect artists against piracy? +

+In a rare bit of candor, one RIAA expert admitted what seemed obvious to +everyone at the time. As Alex Alben, vice president for Public Policy at +Real Networks, told me, +

+ +The RIAA, which was representing the record labels, presented some testimony +about what they thought a willing buyer would pay to a willing seller, and +it was much higher. It was ten times higher than what radio stations pay to +perform the same songs for the same period of time. And so the attorneys +representing the webcasters asked the RIAA, . . . "How do you come up with a +rate that's so much higher? Why is it worth more than radio? Because here we +have hundreds of thousands of webcasters who want to pay, and that should +establish the market rate, and if you set the rate so high, you're going to +drive the small webcasters out of business. . . ." +

+And the RIAA experts said, "Well, we don't really model this as an industry +with thousands of webcasters, we think it should be an industry with, you +know, five or seven big players who can pay a high rate and it's a stable, +predictable market." (Emphasis added.) +

+Translation: The aim is to use the law to eliminate competition, so that +this platform of potentially immense competition, which would cause the +diversity and range of content available to explode, would not cause pain to +the dinosaurs of old. There is no one, on either the right or the left, who +should endorse this use of the law. And yet there is practically no one, on +either the right or the left, who is doing anything effective to prevent it. +

Corrupting Citizens

+Overregulation stifles creativity. It smothers innovation. It gives +dinosaurs a veto over the future. It wastes the extraordinary opportunity +for a democratic creativity that digital technology enables. +

+In addition to these important harms, there is one more that was important +to our forebears, but seems forgotten today. Overregulation corrupts +citizens and weakens the rule of law. +

+ +The war that is being waged today is a war of prohibition. As with every war +of prohibition, it is targeted against the behavior of a very large number +of citizens. According to The New York Times, 43 million Americans +downloaded music in May 2002.[171] According +to the RIAA, the behavior of those 43 million Americans is a felony. We thus +have a set of rules that transform 20 percent of America into criminals. As +the RIAA launches lawsuits against not only the Napsters and Kazaas of the +world, but against students building search engines, and increasingly +against ordinary users downloading content, the technologies for sharing +will advance to further protect and hide illegal use. It is an arms race or +a civil war, with the extremes of one side inviting a more extreme response +by the other. +

+The content industry's tactics exploit the failings of the American legal +system. When the RIAA brought suit against Jesse Jordan, it knew that in +Jordan it had found a scapegoat, not a defendant. The threat of having to +pay either all the money in the world in damages ($15,000,000) or almost all +the money in the world to defend against paying all the money in the world +in damages ($250,000 in legal fees) led Jordan to choose to pay all the +money he had in the world ($12,000) to make the suit go away. The same +strategy animates the RIAA's suits against individual users. In September +2003, the RIAA sued 261 individuals—including a twelve-year-old girl +living in public housing and a seventy-year-old man who had no idea what +file sharing was.[172] As these scapegoats +discovered, it will always cost more to defend against these suits than it +would cost to simply settle. (The twelve year old, for example, like Jesse +Jordan, paid her life savings of $2,000 to settle the case.) Our law is an +awful system for defending rights. It is an embarrassment to our +tradition. And the consequence of our law as it is, is that those with the +power can use the law to quash any rights they oppose. +

+Wars of prohibition are nothing new in America. This one is just something +more extreme than anything we've seen before. We experimented with alcohol +prohibition, at a time when the per capita consumption of alcohol was 1.5 +gallons per capita per year. The war against drinking initially reduced that +consumption to just 30 percent of its preprohibition levels, but by the end +of prohibition, consumption was up to 70 percent of the preprohibition +level. Americans were drinking just about as much, but now, a vast number +were criminals.[173] We have launched a war +on drugs aimed at reducing the consumption of regulated narcotics that 7 +percent (or 16 million) Americans now use.[174] That is a drop from the high (so to speak) in 1979 of 14 percent of +the population. We regulate automobiles to the point where the vast majority +of Americans violate the law every day. We run such a complex tax system +that a majority of cash businesses regularly cheat.[175] We pride ourselves on our "free society," but an +endless array of ordinary behavior is regulated within our society. And as a +result, a huge proportion of Americans regularly violate at least some law. +

+This state of affairs is not without consequence. It is a particularly +salient issue for teachers like me, whose job it is to teach law students +about the importance of "ethics." As my colleague Charlie Nesson told a +class at Stanford, each year law schools admit thousands of students who +have illegally downloaded music, illegally consumed alcohol and sometimes +drugs, illegally worked without paying taxes, illegally driven cars. These +are kids for whom behaving illegally is increasingly the norm. And then we, +as law professors, are supposed to teach them how to behave +ethically—how to say no to bribes, or keep client funds separate, or +honor a demand to disclose a document that will mean that your case is +over. Generations of Americans—more significantly in some parts of +America than in others, but still, everywhere in America today—can't +live their lives both normally and legally, since "normally" entails a +certain degree of illegality. +

+The response to this general illegality is either to enforce the law more +severely or to change the law. We, as a society, have to learn how to make +that choice more rationally. Whether a law makes sense depends, in part, at +least, upon whether the costs of the law, both intended and collateral, +outweigh the benefits. If the costs, intended and collateral, do outweigh +the benefits, then the law ought to be changed. Alternatively, if the costs +of the existing system are much greater than the costs of an alternative, +then we have a good reason to consider the alternative. +

+ + + +My point is not the idiotic one: Just because people violate a law, we +should therefore repeal it. Obviously, we could reduce murder statistics +dramatically by legalizing murder on Wednesdays and Fridays. But that +wouldn't make any sense, since murder is wrong every day of the week. A +society is right to ban murder always and everywhere. +

+My point is instead one that democracies understood for generations, but +that we recently have learned to forget. The rule of law depends upon people +obeying the law. The more often, and more repeatedly, we as citizens +experience violating the law, the less we respect the law. Obviously, in +most cases, the important issue is the law, not respect for the law. I don't +care whether the rapist respects the law or not; I want to catch and +incarcerate the rapist. But I do care whether my students respect the +law. And I do care if the rules of law sow increasing disrespect because of +the extreme of regulation they impose. Twenty million Americans have come +of age since the Internet introduced this different idea of "sharing." We +need to be able to call these twenty million Americans "citizens," not +"felons." +

+When at least forty-three million citizens download content from the +Internet, and when they use tools to combine that content in ways +unauthorized by copyright holders, the first question we should be asking is +not how best to involve the FBI. The first question should be whether this +particular prohibition is really necessary in order to achieve the proper +ends that copyright law serves. Is there another way to assure that artists +get paid without transforming forty-three million Americans into felons? +Does it make sense if there are other ways to assure that artists get paid +without transforming America into a nation of felons? +

+This abstract point can be made more clear with a particular example. +

+ +We all own CDs. Many of us still own phonograph records. These pieces of +plastic encode music that in a certain sense we have bought. The law +protects our right to buy and sell that plastic: It is not a copyright +infringement for me to sell all my classical records at a used record store +and buy jazz records to replace them. That "use" of the recordings is free. +

+But as the MP3 craze has demonstrated, there is another use of phonograph +records that is effectively free. Because these recordings were made without +copy-protection technologies, I am "free" to copy, or "rip," music from my +records onto a computer hard disk. Indeed, Apple Corporation went so far as +to suggest that "freedom" was a right: In a series of commercials, Apple +endorsed the "Rip, Mix, Burn" capacities of digital technologies. +

+This "use" of my records is certainly valuable. I have begun a large process +at home of ripping all of my and my wife's CDs, and storing them in one +archive. Then, using Apple's iTunes, or a wonderful program called +Andromeda, we can build different play lists of our music: Bach, Baroque, +Love Songs, Love Songs of Significant Others—the potential is +endless. And by reducing the costs of mixing play lists, these technologies +help build a creativity with play lists that is itself independently +valuable. Compilations of songs are creative and meaningful in their own +right. +

+This use is enabled by unprotected media—either CDs or records. But +unprotected media also enable file sharing. File sharing threatens (or so +the content industry believes) the ability of creators to earn a fair return +from their creativity. And thus, many are beginning to experiment with +technologies to eliminate unprotected media. These technologies, for +example, would enable CDs that could not be ripped. Or they might enable spy +programs to identify ripped content on people's machines. +

+ +If these technologies took off, then the building of large archives of your +own music would become quite difficult. You might hang in hacker circles, +and get technology to disable the technologies that protect the +content. Trading in those technologies is illegal, but maybe that doesn't +bother you much. In any case, for the vast majority of people, these +protection technologies would effectively destroy the archiving use of +CDs. The technology, in other words, would force us all back to the world +where we either listened to music by manipulating pieces of plastic or were +part of a massively complex "digital rights management" system. +

+If the only way to assure that artists get paid were the elimination of the +ability to freely move content, then these technologies to interfere with +the freedom to move content would be justifiable. But what if there were +another way to assure that artists are paid, without locking down any +content? What if, in other words, a different system could assure +compensation to artists while also preserving the freedom to move content +easily? +

+My point just now is not to prove that there is such a system. I offer a +version of such a system in the last chapter of this book. For now, the only +point is the relatively uncontroversial one: If a different system achieved +the same legitimate objectives that the existing copyright system achieved, +but left consumers and creators much more free, then we'd have a very good +reason to pursue this alternative—namely, freedom. The choice, in +other words, would not be between property and piracy; the choice would be +between different property systems and the freedoms each allowed. +

+I believe there is a way to assure that artists are paid without turning +forty-three million Americans into felons. But the salient feature of this +alternative is that it would lead to a very different market for producing +and distributing creativity. The dominant few, who today control the vast +majority of the distribution of content in the world, would no longer +exercise this extreme of control. Rather, they would go the way of the +horse-drawn buggy. +

+Except that this generation's buggy manufacturers have already saddled +Congress, and are riding the law to protect themselves against this new form +of competition. For them the choice is between fortythree million Americans +as criminals and their own survival. +

+It is understandable why they choose as they do. It is not understandable +why we as a democracy continue to choose as we do. Jack Valenti is charming; +but not so charming as to justify giving up a tradition as deep and +important as our tradition of free culture. There's one more aspect to this +corruption that is particularly important to civil liberties, and follows +directly from any war of prohibition. As Electronic Frontier Foundation +attorney Fred von Lohmann describes, this is the "collateral damage" that +"arises whenever you turn a very large percentage of the population into +criminals." This is the collateral damage to civil liberties generally. + +

+"Hvis du kan behandle noen som en antatt lovbryter," forklarer von Lohmann, + +

+then all of a sudden a lot of basic civil liberty protections evaporate to +one degree or another. . . . If you're a copyright infringer, how can you +hope to have any privacy rights? If you're a copyright infringer, how can +you hope to be secure against seizures of your computer? How can you hope to +continue to receive Internet access? . . . Our sensibilities change as soon +as we think, "Oh, well, but that person's a criminal, a lawbreaker." Well, +what this campaign against file sharing has done is turn a remarkable +percentage of the American Internet-using population into "lawbreakers." +

+And the consequence of this transformation of the American public into +criminals is that it becomes trivial, as a matter of due process, to +effectively erase much of the privacy most would presume. +

+Users of the Internet began to see this generally in 2003 as the RIAA +launched its campaign to force Internet service providers to turn over the +names of customers who the RIAA believed were violating copyright +law. Verizon fought that demand and lost. With a simple request to a judge, +and without any notice to the customer at all, the identity of an Internet +user is revealed. +

+ +The RIAA then expanded this campaign, by announcing a general strategy to +sue individual users of the Internet who are alleged to have downloaded +copyrighted music from file-sharing systems. But as we've seen, the +potential damages from these suits are astronomical: If a family's computer +is used to download a single CD's worth of music, the family could be liable +for $2 million in damages. That didn't stop the RIAA from suing a number of +these families, just as they had sued Jesse Jordan.[176] + +

+Even this understates the espionage that is being waged by the RIAA. A +report from CNN late last summer described a strategy the RIAA had adopted +to track Napster users.[177] Using a +sophisticated hashing algorithm, the RIAA took what is in effect a +fingerprint of every song in the Napster catalog. Any copy of one of those +MP3s will have the same "fingerprint." +

+So imagine the following not-implausible scenario: Imagine a friend gives a +CD to your daughter—a collection of songs just like the cassettes you +used to make as a kid. You don't know, and neither does your daughter, where +these songs came from. But she copies these songs onto her computer. She +then takes her computer to college and connects it to a college network, and +if the college network is "cooperating" with the RIAA's espionage, and she +hasn't properly protected her content from the network (do you know how to +do that yourself ?), then the RIAA will be able to identify your daughter as +a "criminal." And under the rules that universities are beginning to +deploy,[178] your daughter can lose the +right to use the university's computer network. She can, in some cases, be +expelled. +

+Now, of course, she'll have the right to defend herself. You can hire a +lawyer for her (at $300 per hour, if you're lucky), and she can plead that +she didn't know anything about the source of the songs or that they came +from Napster. And it may well be that the university believes her. But the +university might not believe her. It might treat this "contraband" as +presumptive of guilt. And as any number of college students have already +learned, our presumptions about innocence disappear in the middle of wars of +prohibition. This war is no different. Says von Lohmann, +

+So when we're talking about numbers like forty to sixty million Americans +that are essentially copyright infringers, you create a situation where the +civil liberties of those people are very much in peril in a general +matter. [I don't] think [there is any] analog where you could randomly +choose any person off the street and be confident that they were committing +an unlawful act that could put them on the hook for potential felony +liability or hundreds of millions of dollars of civil liability. Certainly +we all speed, but speeding isn't the kind of an act for which we routinely +forfeit civil liberties. Some people use drugs, and I think that's the +closest analog, [but] many have noted that the war against drugs has eroded +all of our civil liberties because it's treated so many Americans as +criminals. Well, I think it's fair to say that file sharing is an order of +magnitude larger number of Americans than drug use. . . . If forty to sixty +million Americans have become lawbreakers, then we're really on a slippery +slope to lose a lot of civil liberties for all forty to sixty million of +them. +

+When forty to sixty million Americans are considered "criminals" under the +law, and when the law could achieve the same objective— securing +rights to authors—without these millions being considered "criminals," +who is the villain? Americans or the law? Which is American, a constant war +on our own people or a concerted effort through our democracy to change our +law? +



[154] + + +H. G. Wells, "The Country of the Blind" (1904, 1911). See H. G. Wells, The +Country of the Blind and Other Stories, Michael Sherborne, ed. (New York: +Oxford University Press, 1996). +

[155] + +For an excellent summary, see the report prepared by GartnerG2 and the +Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School, "Copyright +and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World," 27 June 2003, available at +link #33. Reps. John +Conyers Jr. (D-Mich.) and Howard L. Berman (D-Calif.) have introduced a bill +that would treat unauthorized on-line copying as a felony offense with +punishments ranging as high as five years imprisonment; see Jon Healey, +"House Bill Aims to Up Stakes on Piracy," Los Angeles Times, 17 July 2003, +available at link +#34. Civil penalties are currently set at $150,000 per copied +song. For a recent (and unsuccessful) legal challenge to the RIAA's demand +that an ISP reveal the identity of a user accused of sharing more than 600 +songs through a family computer, see RIAA v. Verizon Internet Services (In +re. Verizon Internet Services), 240 F. Supp. 2d 24 (D.D.C. 2003). Such a +user could face liability ranging as high as $90 million. Such astronomical +figures furnish the RIAA with a powerful arsenal in its prosecution of file +sharers. Settlements ranging from $12,000 to $17,500 for four students +accused of heavy file sharing on university networks must have seemed a mere +pittance next to the $98 billion the RIAA could seek should the matter +proceed to court. See Elizabeth Young, "Downloading Could Lead to Fines," +redandblack.com, August 2003, available at link #35. For an example of the +RIAA's targeting of student file sharing, and of the subpoenas issued to +universities to reveal student file-sharer identities, see James Collins, +"RIAA Steps Up Bid to Force BC, MIT to Name Students," Boston Globe, 8 +August 2003, D3, available at link #36. +

[156] + +WIPO and the DMCA One Year Later: Assessing Consumer Access to Digital +Entertainment on the Internet and Other Media: Hearing Before the +Subcommittee on Telecommunications, Trade, and Consumer Protection, House +Committee on Commerce, 106th Cong. 29 (1999) (statement of Peter Harter, +vice president, Global Public Policy and Standards, EMusic.com), available +in LEXIS, Federal Document Clearing House Congressional Testimony File. +

[157] + +See Lynne W. Jeter, Disconnected: Deceit and Betrayal at WorldCom (Hoboken, +N.J.: John Wiley & Sons, 2003), 176, 204; for details of the settlement, +see MCI press release, "MCI Wins U.S. District Court Approval for SEC +Settlement" (7 July 2003), available at link #37. +

[158] + The bill, modeled after California's tort reform model, was passed in the +House of Representatives but defeated in a Senate vote in July 2003. For an +overview, see Tanya Albert, "Measure Stalls in Senate: `We'll Be Back,' Say +Tort Reformers," amednews.com, 28 July 2003, available at link #38, and "Senate Turns Back +Malpractice Caps," CBSNews.com, 9 July 2003, available at link #39. President Bush has +continued to urge tort reform in recent months. +

[159] + +See Danit Lidor, "Artists Just Wanna Be Free," Wired, 7 July 2003, available +at link #40. For an +overview of the exhibition, see link #41. +

[160] + +See Joseph Menn, "Universal, EMI Sue Napster Investor," Los Angeles Times, +23 April 2003. For a parallel argument about the effects on innovation in +the distribution of music, see Janelle Brown, "The Music Revolution Will Not +Be Digitized," Salon.com, 1 June 2001, available at link #42. See also Jon Healey, +"Online Music Services Besieged," Los Angeles Times, 28 May 2001. +

[161] + +Rafe Needleman, "Driving in Cars with MP3s," Business 2.0, 16. juni 2003, +tilgjengelig via link +#43. Jeg er Dr. Mohammad Al-Ubaydli takknemlig mot for dette +eksemplet. +

[162] + +"Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster World," GartnerG2 and the +Berkman Center for Internet and Society at Harvard Law School (2003), +33–35, available at link +#44. +

[163] + +GartnerG2, 26–27. +

[164] + +See David McGuire, "Tech Execs Square Off Over Piracy," Newsbytes, February +2002 (Entertainment). +

[165] + +Jessica Litman, Digital Copyright (Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books, 2001). +

[166] + +The only circuit court exception is found in Recording Industry Association +of America (RIAA) v. Diamond Multimedia Systems, 180 F. 3d 1072 (9th +Cir. 1999). There the court of appeals for the Ninth Circuit reasoned that +makers of a portable MP3 player were not liable for contributory copyright +infringement for a device that is unable to record or redistribute music (a +device whose only copying function is to render portable a music file +already stored on a user's hard drive). At the district court level, the +only exception is found in Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer Studios, Inc. v. Grokster, +Ltd., 259 F. Supp. 2d 1029 (C.D. Cal., 2003), where the court found the +link between the distributor and any given user's conduct too attenuated to +make the distributor liable for contributory or vicarious infringement +liability. +

[167] + +For example, in July 2002, Representative Howard Berman introduced the +Peer-to-Peer Piracy Prevention Act (H.R. 5211), which would immunize +copyright holders from liability for damage done to computers when the +copyright holders use technology to stop copyright infringement. In August +2002, Representative Billy Tauzin introduced a bill to mandate that +technologies capable of rebroadcasting digital copies of films broadcast on +TV (i.e., computers) respect a "broadcast flag" that would disable copying +of that content. And in March of the same year, Senator Fritz Hollings +introduced the Consumer Broadband and Digital Television Promotion Act, +which mandated copyright protection technology in all digital media +devices. See GartnerG2, "Copyright and Digital Media in a Post-Napster +World," 27 June 2003, 33–34, available at link #44. +

[168] + + +Lessing, 239. +

[169] + + +Ibid., 229. +

[170] + +This example was derived from fees set by the original Copyright Arbitration +Royalty Panel (CARP) proceedings, and is drawn from an example offered by +Professor William Fisher. Conference Proceedings, iLaw (Stanford), 3 July +2003, on file with author. Professors Fisher and Zittrain submitted +testimony in the CARP proceeding that was ultimately rejected. See Jonathan +Zittrain, Digital Performance Right in Sound Recordings and Ephemeral +Recordings, Docket No. 2000-9, CARP DTRA 1 and 2, available at link #45. For an excellent +analysis making a similar point, see Randal C. Picker, "Copyright as Entry +Policy: The Case of Digital Distribution," Antitrust Bulletin (Summer/Fall +2002): 461: "This was not confusion, these are just old-fashioned entry +barriers. Analog radio stations are protected from digital entrants, +reducing entry in radio and diversity. Yes, this is done in the name of +getting royalties to copyright holders, but, absent the play of powerful +interests, that could have been done in a media-neutral way." +

[171] + +Mike Graziano and Lee Rainie, "The Music Downloading Deluge," Pew Internet +and American Life Project (24 April 2001), available at link #46. The Pew Internet and +American Life Project reported that 37 million Americans had downloaded +music files from the Internet by early 2001. +

[172] + + +Alex Pham, "The Labels Strike Back: N.Y. Girl Settles RIAA Case," Los +Angeles Times, 10 September 2003, Business. +

[173] + + +Jeffrey A. Miron and Jeffrey Zwiebel, "Alcohol Consumption During +Prohibition," American Economic Review 81, no. 2 (1991): 242. +

[174] + + +National Drug Control Policy: Hearing Before the House Government Reform +Committee, 108th Cong., 1st sess. (5 March 2003) (statement of John +P. Walters, director of National Drug Control Policy). +

[175] + + +See James Andreoni, Brian Erard, and Jonathon Feinstein, "Tax Compliance," +Journal of Economic Literature 36 (1998): 818 (survey of compliance +literature). +

[176] + + +See Frank Ahrens, "RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single Mother in +Calif., 12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants," Washington Post, 10 +September 2003, E1; Chris Cobbs, "Worried Parents Pull Plug on File +`Stealing'; With the Music Industry Cracking Down on File Swapping, Parents +are Yanking Software from Home PCs to Avoid Being Sued," Orlando Sentinel +Tribune, 30 August 2003, C1; Jefferson Graham, "Recording Industry Sues +Parents," USA Today, 15 September 2003, 4D; John Schwartz, "She Says She's +No Music Pirate. No Snoop Fan, Either," New York Times, 25 September 2003, +C1; Margo Varadi, "Is Brianna a Criminal?" Toronto Star, 18 September 2003, +P7. +

[177] + + +See "Revealed: How RIAA Tracks Downloaders: Music Industry Discloses Some +Methods Used," CNN.com, available at link #47. +

[178] + + +See Jeff Adler, "Cambridge: On Campus, Pirates Are Not Penitent," Boston +Globe, 18 May 2003, City Weekly, 1; Frank Ahrens, "Four Students Sued over +Music Sites; Industry Group Targets File Sharing at Colleges," Washington +Post, 4 April 2003, E1; Elizabeth Armstrong, "Students `Rip, Mix, Burn' at +Their Own Risk," Christian Science Monitor, 2 September 2003, 20; Robert +Becker and Angela Rozas, "Music Pirate Hunt Turns to Loyola; Two Students +Names Are Handed Over; Lawsuit Possible," Chicago Tribune, 16 July 2003, 1C; +Beth Cox, "RIAA Trains Antipiracy Guns on Universities," Internet News, 30 +January 2003, available at link +#48; Benny Evangelista, "Download Warning 101: Freshman Orientation +This Fall to Include Record Industry Warnings Against File Sharing," San +Francisco Chronicle, 11 August 2003, E11; "Raid, Letters Are Weapons at +Universities," USA Today, 26 September 2000, 3D. +

Kapittel 5. Maktfordeling

+Så her er bildet: Du står på siden av veien. Bilen din er på brann. Du er +sint og opprørt fordi du delvis bidro til å starte brannen. Nå vet du ikke +hvordan du slokker den. Ved siden av deg er en bøtte, fylt med +bensin. bensin vil selvfølgelig ikke slukke brannen. +

+Mens du tenker over situasjonen, kommer noen andre forbi. I panikk griper +hun bøtta, og før du har hatt sjansen til å be henne stoppe—eller før +hun forstår hvorfor hun bør stoppe—er bøtten i svevet. Bensinen er på +tur mot den brennende bilen. Og brannen som bensinen vil tenne vil straks +sette fyr på alt i omgivelsene. +

+A war about copyright rages all around—and we're all focusing on the +wrong thing. No doubt, current technologies threaten existing businesses. +No doubt they may threaten artists. But technologies change. The industry +and technologists have plenty of ways to use technology to protect +themselves against the current threats of the Internet. This is a fire that +if let alone would burn itself out. +

+ + +Yet policy makers are not willing to leave this fire to itself. Primed with +plenty of lobbyists' money, they are keen to intervene to eliminate the +problem they perceive. But the problem they perceive is not the real threat +this culture faces. For while we watch this small fire in the corner, there +is a massive change in the way culture is made that is happening all around. +

+Somehow we have to find a way to turn attention to this more important and +fundamental issue. Somehow we have to find a way to avoid pouring gasoline +onto this fire. +

+We have not found that way yet. Instead, we seem trapped in a simpler, +binary view. However much many people push to frame this debate more +broadly, it is the simple, binary view that remains. We rubberneck to look +at the fire when we should be keeping our eyes on the road. +

+This challenge has been my life these last few years. It has also been my +failure. In the two chapters that follow, I describe one small brace of +efforts, so far failed, to find a way to refocus this debate. We must +understand these failures if we're to understand what success will require. +

Kapittel tretten: Eldred

+In 1995, a father was frustrated that his daughters didn't seem to like +Hawthorne. No doubt there was more than one such father, but at least one +did something about it. Eric Eldred, a retired computer programmer living in +New Hampshire, decided to put Hawthorne on the Web. An electronic version, +Eldred thought, with links to pictures and explanatory text, would make this +nineteenth-century author's work come alive. +

+It didn't work—at least for his daughters. They didn't find Hawthorne +any more interesting than before. But Eldred's experiment gave birth to a +hobby, and his hobby begat a cause: Eldred would build a library of public +domain works by scanning these works and making them available for free. +

+ +Eldred's library was not simply a copy of certain public domain works, +though even a copy would have been of great value to people across the world +who can't get access to printed versions of these works. Instead, Eldred was +producing derivative works from these public domain works. Just as Disney +turned Grimm into stories more accessible to the twentieth century, Eldred +transformed Hawthorne, and many others, into a form more +accessible—technically accessible—today. +

+Eldred's freedom to do this with Hawthorne's work grew from the same source +as Disney's. Hawthorne's Scarlet Letter had passed into the public domain in +1907. It was free for anyone to take without the permission of the Hawthorne +estate or anyone else. Some, such as Dover Press and Penguin Classics, take +works from the public domain and produce printed editions, which they sell +in bookstores across the country. Others, such as Disney, take these stories +and turn them into animated cartoons, sometimes successfully (Cinderella), +sometimes not (The Hunchback of Notre Dame, Treasure Planet). These are all +commercial publications of public domain works. +

+The Internet created the possibility of noncommercial publications of public +domain works. Eldred's is just one example. There are literally thousands of +others. Hundreds of thousands from across the world have discovered this +platform of expression and now use it to share works that are, by law, free +for the taking. This has produced what we might call the "noncommercial +publishing industry," which before the Internet was limited to people with +large egos or with political or social causes. But with the Internet, it +includes a wide range of individuals and groups dedicated to spreading +culture generally.[179] +

+As I said, Eldred lives in New Hampshire. In 1998, Robert Frost's collection +of poems New Hampshire was slated to pass into the public domain. Eldred +wanted to post that collection in his free public library. But Congress got +in the way. As I described in chapter 10, in 1998, for the eleventh time in +forty years, Congress extended the terms of existing copyrights—this +time by twenty years. Eldred would not be free to add any works more recent +than 1923 to his collection until 2019. Indeed, no copyrighted work would +pass into the public domain until that year (and not even then, if Congress +extends the term again). By contrast, in the same period, more than 1 +million patents will pass into the public domain. +

+ + +This was the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act (CTEA), enacted in +memory of the congressman and former musician Sonny Bono, who, his widow, +Mary Bono, says, believed that "copyrights should be forever."[180] + +

+Eldred decided to fight this law. He first resolved to fight it through +civil disobedience. In a series of interviews, Eldred announced that he +would publish as planned, CTEA notwithstanding. But because of a second law +passed in 1998, the NET (No Electronic Theft) Act, his act of publishing +would make Eldred a felon—whether or not anyone complained. This was a +dangerous strategy for a disabled programmer to undertake. +

+It was here that I became involved in Eldred's battle. I was a +constitutional scholar whose first passion was constitutional +interpretation. And though constitutional law courses never focus upon the +Progress Clause of the Constitution, it had always struck me as importantly +different. As you know, the Constitution says, +

+Congress has the power to promote the Progress of Science . . . by securing +for limited Times to Authors . . . exclusive Right to their +. . . Writings. . . . +

+As I've described, this clause is unique within the power-granting clause of +Article I, section 8 of our Constitution. Every other clause granting power +to Congress simply says Congress has the power to do something—for +example, to regulate "commerce among the several states" or "declare War." +But here, the "something" is something quite specific—to "promote +. . . Progress"—through means that are also specific— by +"securing" "exclusive Rights" (i.e., copyrights) "for limited Times." +

+In the past forty years, Congress has gotten into the practice of extending +existing terms of copyright protection. What puzzled me about this was, if +Congress has the power to extend existing terms, then the Constitution's +requirement that terms be "limited" will have no practical effect. If every +time a copyright is about to expire, Congress has the power to extend its +term, then Congress can achieve what the Constitution plainly +forbids—perpetual terms "on the installment plan," as Professor Peter +Jaszi so nicely put it. +

+As an academic, my first response was to hit the books. I remember sitting +late at the office, scouring on-line databases for any serious consideration +of the question. No one had ever challenged Congress's practice of extending +existing terms. That failure may in part be why Congress seemed so +untroubled in its habit. That, and the fact that the practice had become so +lucrative for Congress. Congress knows that copyright owners will be willing +to pay a great deal of money to see their copyright terms extended. And so +Congress is quite happy to keep this gravy train going. +

+For this is the core of the corruption in our present system of +government. "Corruption" not in the sense that representatives are bribed. +Rather, "corruption" in the sense that the system induces the beneficiaries +of Congress's acts to raise and give money to Congress to induce it to +act. There's only so much time; there's only so much Congress can do. Why +not limit its actions to those things it must do—and those things that +pay? Extending copyright terms pays. +

+If that's not obvious to you, consider the following: Say you're one of the +very few lucky copyright owners whose copyright continues to make money one +hundred years after it was created. The Estate of Robert Frost is a good +example. Frost died in 1963. His poetry continues to be extraordinarily +valuable. Thus the Robert Frost estate benefits greatly from any extension +of copyright, since no publisher would pay the estate any money if the poems +Frost wrote could be published by anyone for free. +

+So imagine the Robert Frost estate is earning $100,000 a year from three of +Frost's poems. And imagine the copyright for those poems is about to +expire. You sit on the board of the Robert Frost estate. Your financial +adviser comes to your board meeting with a very grim report: +

+ +"Next year," the adviser announces, "our copyrights in works A, B, and C +will expire. That means that after next year, we will no longer be receiving +the annual royalty check of $100,000 from the publishers of those works. +

+"There's a proposal in Congress, however," she continues, "that could change +this. A few congressmen are floating a bill to extend the terms of copyright +by twenty years. That bill would be extraordinarily valuable to us. So we +should hope this bill passes." +

+"Hope?" a fellow board member says. "Can't we be doing something about it?" +

+"Well, obviously, yes," the adviser responds. "We could contribute to the +campaigns of a number of representatives to try to assure that they support +the bill." +

+You hate politics. You hate contributing to campaigns. So you want to know +whether this disgusting practice is worth it. "How much would we get if this +extension were passed?" you ask the adviser. "How much is it worth?" +

+"Well," the adviser says, "if you're confident that you will continue to get +at least $100,000 a year from these copyrights, and you use the `discount +rate' that we use to evaluate estate investments (6 percent), then this law +would be worth $1,146,000 to the estate." +

+You're a bit shocked by the number, but you quickly come to the correct +conclusion: +

+"So you're saying it would be worth it for us to pay more than $1,000,000 in +campaign contributions if we were confident those contributions would assure +that the bill was passed?" +

+"Absolutely," the adviser responds. "It is worth it to you to contribute up +to the `present value' of the income you expect from these copyrights. Which +for us means over $1,000,000." +

+ +You quickly get the point—you as the member of the board and, I trust, +you the reader. Each time copyrights are about to expire, every beneficiary +in the position of the Robert Frost estate faces the same choice: If they +can contribute to get a law passed to extend copyrights, they will benefit +greatly from that extension. And so each time copyrights are about to +expire, there is a massive amount of lobbying to get the copyright term +extended. +

+Thus a congressional perpetual motion machine: So long as legislation can be +bought (albeit indirectly), there will be all the incentive in the world to +buy further extensions of copyright. +

+In the lobbying that led to the passage of the Sonny Bono Copyright Term +Extension Act, this "theory" about incentives was proved real. Ten of the +thirteen original sponsors of the act in the House received the maximum +contribution from Disney's political action committee; in the Senate, eight +of the twelve sponsors received contributions.[181] The RIAA and the MPAA are estimated to have spent over $1.5 million +lobbying in the 1998 election cycle. They paid out more than $200,000 in +campaign contributions.[182] Disney is +estimated to have contributed more than $800,000 to reelection campaigns in +the cycle.[183] + +

+Constitutional law is not oblivious to the obvious. Or at least, it need not +be. So when I was considering Eldred's complaint, this reality about the +never-ending incentives to increase the copyright term was central to my +thinking. In my view, a pragmatic court committed to interpreting and +applying the Constitution of our framers would see that if Congress has the +power to extend existing terms, then there would be no effective +constitutional requirement that terms be "limited." If they could extend it +once, they would extend it again and again and again. +

+ +It was also my judgment that this Supreme Court would not allow Congress to +extend existing terms. As anyone close to the Supreme Court's work knows, +this Court has increasingly restricted the power of Congress when it has +viewed Congress's actions as exceeding the power granted to it by the +Constitution. Among constitutional scholars, the most famous example of this +trend was the Supreme Court's decision in 1995 to strike down a law that +banned the possession of guns near schools. +

+Since 1937, the Supreme Court had interpreted Congress's granted powers very +broadly; so, while the Constitution grants Congress the power to regulate +only "commerce among the several states" (aka "interstate commerce"), the +Supreme Court had interpreted that power to include the power to regulate +any activity that merely affected interstate commerce. +

+As the economy grew, this standard increasingly meant that there was no +limit to Congress's power to regulate, since just about every activity, when +considered on a national scale, affects interstate commerce. A Constitution +designed to limit Congress's power was instead interpreted to impose no +limit. +

+The Supreme Court, under Chief Justice Rehnquist's command, changed that in +United States v. Lopez. The government had argued that possessing guns near +schools affected interstate commerce. Guns near schools increase crime, +crime lowers property values, and so on. In the oral argument, the Chief +Justice asked the government whether there was any activity that would not +affect interstate commerce under the reasoning the government advanced. The +government said there was not; if Congress says an activity affects +interstate commerce, then that activity affects interstate commerce. The +Supreme Court, the government said, was not in the position to second-guess +Congress. +

+"We pause to consider the implications of the government's arguments," the +Chief Justice wrote.[184] If anything +Congress says is interstate commerce must therefore be considered interstate +commerce, then there would be no limit to Congress's power. The decision in +Lopez was reaffirmed five years later in United States +v. Morrison.[185] + +

+ +If a principle were at work here, then it should apply to the Progress +Clause as much as the Commerce Clause.[186] +And if it is applied to the Progress Clause, the principle should yield the +conclusion that Congress can't extend an existing term. If Congress could +extend an existing term, then there would be no "stopping point" to +Congress's power over terms, though the Constitution expressly states that +there is such a limit. Thus, the same principle applied to the power to +grant copyrights should entail that Congress is not allowed to extend the +term of existing copyrights. +

+If, that is, the principle announced in Lopez stood for a principle. Many +believed the decision in Lopez stood for politics—a conservative +Supreme Court, which believed in states' rights, using its power over +Congress to advance its own personal political preferences. But I rejected +that view of the Supreme Court's decision. Indeed, shortly after the +decision, I wrote an article demonstrating the "fidelity" in such an +interpretation of the Constitution. The idea that the Supreme Court decides +cases based upon its politics struck me as extraordinarily boring. I was +not going to devote my life to teaching constitutional law if these nine +Justices were going to be petty politicians. +

+Now let's pause for a moment to make sure we understand what the argument in +Eldred was not about. By insisting on the Constitution's limits to +copyright, obviously Eldred was not endorsing piracy. Indeed, in an obvious +sense, he was fighting a kind of piracy—piracy of the public +domain. When Robert Frost wrote his work and when Walt Disney created Mickey +Mouse, the maximum copyright term was just fifty-six years. Because of +interim changes, Frost and Disney had already enjoyed a seventy-five-year +monopoly for their work. They had gotten the benefit of the bargain that the +Constitution envisions: In exchange for a monopoly protected for fifty-six +years, they created new work. But now these entities were using their +power—expressed through the power of lobbyists' money—to get +another twenty-year dollop of monopoly. That twenty-year dollop would be +taken from the public domain. Eric Eldred was fighting a piracy that affects +us all. +

+Some people view the public domain with contempt. In their brief before the +Supreme Court, the Nashville Songwriters Association wrote that the public +domain is nothing more than "legal piracy."[187] But it is not piracy when the law allows it; and in our +constitutional system, our law requires it. Some may not like the +Constitution's requirements, but that doesn't make the Constitution a +pirate's charter. +

+As we've seen, our constitutional system requires limits on copyright as a +way to assure that copyright holders do not too heavily influence the +development and distribution of our culture. Yet, as Eric Eldred discovered, +we have set up a system that assures that copyright terms will be repeatedly +extended, and extended, and extended. We have created the perfect storm for +the public domain. Copyrights have not expired, and will not expire, so long +as Congress is free to be bought to extend them again. +

+It is valuable copyrights that are responsible for terms being extended. +Mickey Mouse and "Rhapsody in Blue." These works are too valuable for +copyright owners to ignore. But the real harm to our society from copyright +extensions is not that Mickey Mouse remains Disney's. Forget Mickey +Mouse. Forget Robert Frost. Forget all the works from the 1920s and 1930s +that have continuing commercial value. The real harm of term extension comes +not from these famous works. The real harm is to the works that are not +famous, not commercially exploited, and no longer available as a result. +

+If you look at the work created in the first twenty years (1923 to 1942) +affected by the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act, 2 percent of that +work has any continuing commercial value. It was the copyright holders for +that 2 percent who pushed the CTEA through. But the law and its effect were +not limited to that 2 percent. The law extended the terms of copyright +generally.[188] + +

+ +Think practically about the consequence of this extension—practically, +as a businessperson, and not as a lawyer eager for more legal work. In 1930, +10,047 books were published. In 2000, 174 of those books were still in +print. Let's say you were Brewster Kahle, and you wanted to make available +to the world in your iArchive project the remaining 9,873. What would you +have to do? +

+Well, first, you'd have to determine which of the 9,873 books were still +under copyright. That requires going to a library (these data are not +on-line) and paging through tomes of books, cross-checking the titles and +authors of the 9,873 books with the copyright registration and renewal +records for works published in 1930. That will produce a list of books still +under copyright. +

+Then for the books still under copyright, you would need to locate the +current copyright owners. How would you do that? +

+Most people think that there must be a list of these copyright owners +somewhere. Practical people think this way. How could there be thousands and +thousands of government monopolies without there being at least a list? +

+But there is no list. There may be a name from 1930, and then in 1959, of +the person who registered the copyright. But just think practically about +how impossibly difficult it would be to track down thousands of such +records—especially since the person who registered is not necessarily +the current owner. And we're just talking about 1930! +

+"But there isn't a list of who owns property generally," the apologists for +the system respond. "Why should there be a list of copyright owners?" +

+Well, actually, if you think about it, there are plenty of lists of who owns +what property. Think about deeds on houses, or titles to cars. And where +there isn't a list, the code of real space is pretty good at suggesting who +the owner of a bit of property is. (A swing set in your backyard is probably +yours.) So formally or informally, we have a pretty good way to know who +owns what tangible property. +

+ +So: You walk down a street and see a house. You can know who owns the house +by looking it up in the courthouse registry. If you see a car, there is +ordinarily a license plate that will link the owner to the car. If you see a +bunch of children's toys sitting on the front lawn of a house, it's fairly +easy to determine who owns the toys. And if you happen to see a baseball +lying in a gutter on the side of the road, look around for a second for some +kids playing ball. If you don't see any kids, then okay: Here's a bit of +property whose owner we can't easily determine. It is the exception that +proves the rule: that we ordinarily know quite well who owns what property. +

+Compare this story to intangible property. You go into a library. The +library owns the books. But who owns the copyrights? As I've already +described, there's no list of copyright owners. There are authors' names, of +course, but their copyrights could have been assigned, or passed down in an +estate like Grandma's old jewelry. To know who owns what, you would have to +hire a private detective. The bottom line: The owner cannot easily be +located. And in a regime like ours, in which it is a felony to use such +property without the property owner's permission, the property isn't going +to be used. +

+The consequence with respect to old books is that they won't be digitized, +and hence will simply rot away on shelves. But the consequence for other +creative works is much more dire. +

+Consider the story of Michael Agee, chairman of Hal Roach Studios, which +owns the copyrights for the Laurel and Hardy films. Agee is a direct +beneficiary of the Bono Act. The Laurel and Hardy films were made between +1921 and 1951. Only one of these films, The Lucky Dog, is currently out of +copyright. But for the CTEA, films made after 1923 would have begun entering +the public domain. Because Agee controls the exclusive rights for these +popular films, he makes a great deal of money. According to one estimate, +"Roach has sold about 60,000 videocassettes and 50,000 DVDs of the duo's +silent films."[189] +

+Yet Agee opposed the CTEA. His reasons demonstrate a rare virtue in this +culture: selflessness. He argued in a brief before the Supreme Court that +the Sonny Bono Copyright Term Extension Act will, if left standing, destroy +a whole generation of American film. +

+ +His argument is straightforward. A tiny fraction of this work has any +continuing commercial value. The rest—to the extent it survives at +all—sits in vaults gathering dust. It may be that some of this work +not now commercially valuable will be deemed to be valuable by the owners of +the vaults. For this to occur, however, the commercial benefit from the work +must exceed the costs of making the work available for distribution. +

+We can't know the benefits, but we do know a lot about the costs. For most +of the history of film, the costs of restoring film were very high; digital +technology has lowered these costs substantially. While it cost more than +$10,000 to restore a ninety-minute black-and-white film in 1993, it can now +cost as little as $100 to digitize one hour of mm film.[190] + +

+Restoration technology is not the only cost, nor the most important. +Lawyers, too, are a cost, and increasingly, a very important one. In +addition to preserving the film, a distributor needs to secure the rights. +And to secure the rights for a film that is under copyright, you need to +locate the copyright owner. +

+Or more accurately, owners. As we've seen, there isn't only a single +copyright associated with a film; there are many. There isn't a single +person whom you can contact about those copyrights; there are as many as can +hold the rights, which turns out to be an extremely large number. Thus the +costs of clearing the rights to these films is exceptionally high. +

+"But can't you just restore the film, distribute it, and then pay the +copyright owner when she shows up?" Sure, if you want to commit a +felony. And even if you're not worried about committing a felony, when she +does show up, she'll have the right to sue you for all the profits you have +made. So, if you're successful, you can be fairly confident you'll be +getting a call from someone's lawyer. And if you're not successful, you +won't make enough to cover the costs of your own lawyer. Either way, you +have to talk to a lawyer. And as is too often the case, saying you have to +talk to a lawyer is the same as saying you won't make any money. +

+ +For some films, the benefit of releasing the film may well exceed these +costs. But for the vast majority of them, there is no way the benefit would +outweigh the legal costs. Thus, for the vast majority of old films, Agee +argued, the film will not be restored and distributed until the copyright +expires. +

+But by the time the copyright for these films expires, the film will have +expired. These films were produced on nitrate-based stock, and nitrate stock +dissolves over time. They will be gone, and the metal canisters in which +they are now stored will be filled with nothing more than dust. +

+Of all the creative work produced by humans anywhere, a tiny fraction has +continuing commercial value. For that tiny fraction, the copyright is a +crucially important legal device. For that tiny fraction, the copyright +creates incentives to produce and distribute the creative work. For that +tiny fraction, the copyright acts as an "engine of free expression." +

+But even for that tiny fraction, the actual time during which the creative +work has a commercial life is extremely short. As I've indicated, most books +go out of print within one year. The same is true of music and +film. Commercial culture is sharklike. It must keep moving. And when a +creative work falls out of favor with the commercial distributors, the +commercial life ends. +

+Yet that doesn't mean the life of the creative work ends. We don't keep +libraries of books in order to compete with Barnes & Noble, and we don't +have archives of films because we expect people to choose between spending +Friday night watching new movies and spending Friday night watching a 1930 +news documentary. The noncommercial life of culture is important and +valuable—for entertainment but also, and more importantly, for +knowledge. To understand who we are, and where we came from, and how we have +made the mistakes that we have, we need to have access to this history. +

+ +Copyrights in this context do not drive an engine of free expression. In +this context, there is no need for an exclusive right. Copyrights in this +context do no good. +

+Yet, for most of our history, they also did little harm. For most of our +history, when a work ended its commercial life, there was no +copyright-related use that would be inhibited by an exclusive right. When a +book went out of print, you could not buy it from a publisher. But you +could still buy it from a used book store, and when a used book store sells +it, in America, at least, there is no need to pay the copyright owner +anything. Thus, the ordinary use of a book after its commercial life ended +was a use that was independent of copyright law. +

+The same was effectively true of film. Because the costs of restoring a +film—the real economic costs, not the lawyer costs—were so high, +it was never at all feasible to preserve or restore film. Like the remains +of a great dinner, when it's over, it's over. Once a film passed out of its +commercial life, it may have been archived for a bit, but that was the end +of its life so long as the market didn't have more to offer. +

+In other words, though copyright has been relatively short for most of our +history, long copyrights wouldn't have mattered for the works that lost +their commercial value. Long copyrights for these works would not have +interfered with anything. +

+But this situation has now changed. +

+One crucially important consequence of the emergence of digital technologies +is to enable the archive that Brewster Kahle dreams of. Digital +technologies now make it possible to preserve and give access to all sorts +of knowledge. Once a book goes out of print, we can now imagine digitizing +it and making it available to everyone, forever. Once a film goes out of +distribution, we could digitize it and make it available to everyone, +forever. Digital technologies give new life to copyrighted material after it +passes out of its commercial life. It is now possible to preserve and assure +universal access to this knowledge and culture, whereas before it was not. +

+ + +And now copyright law does get in the way. Every step of producing this +digital archive of our culture infringes on the exclusive right of +copyright. To digitize a book is to copy it. To do that requires permission +of the copyright owner. The same with music, film, or any other aspect of +our culture protected by copyright. The effort to make these things +available to history, or to researchers, or to those who just want to +explore, is now inhibited by a set of rules that were written for a +radically different context. +

+Here is the core of the harm that comes from extending terms: Now that +technology enables us to rebuild the library of Alexandria, the law gets in +the way. And it doesn't get in the way for any useful copyright purpose, for +the purpose of copyright is to enable the commercial market that spreads +culture. No, we are talking about culture after it has lived its commercial +life. In this context, copyright is serving no purpose at all related to the +spread of knowledge. In this context, copyright is not an engine of free +expression. Copyright is a brake. +

+You may well ask, "But if digital technologies lower the costs for Brewster +Kahle, then they will lower the costs for Random House, too. So won't +Random House do as well as Brewster Kahle in spreading culture widely?" +

+Maybe. Someday. But there is absolutely no evidence to suggest that +publishers would be as complete as libraries. If Barnes & Noble offered +to lend books from its stores for a low price, would that eliminate the need +for libraries? Only if you think that the only role of a library is to serve +what "the market" would demand. But if you think the role of a library is +bigger than this—if you think its role is to archive culture, whether +there's a demand for any particular bit of that culture or not—then we +can't count on the commercial market to do our library work for us. +

+I would be the first to agree that it should do as much as it can: We should +rely upon the market as much as possible to spread and enable culture. My +message is absolutely not antimarket. But where we see the market is not +doing the job, then we should allow nonmarket forces the freedom to fill the +gaps. As one researcher calculated for American culture, 94 percent of the +films, books, and music produced between and 1946 is not commercially +available. However much you love the commercial market, if access is a +value, then 6 percent is a failure to provide that value.[191] + +

+In January 1999, we filed a lawsuit on Eric Eldred's behalf in federal +district court in Washington, D.C., asking the court to declare the Sonny +Bono Copyright Term Extension Act unconstitutional. The two central claims +that we made were (1) that extending existing terms violated the +Constitution's "limited Times" requirement, and (2) that extending terms by +another twenty years violated the First Amendment. +

+The district court dismissed our claims without even hearing an argument. A +panel of the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit also dismissed our +claims, though after hearing an extensive argument. But that decision at +least had a dissent, by one of the most conservative judges on that +court. That dissent gave our claims life. +

+Judge David Sentelle said the CTEA violated the requirement that copyrights +be for "limited Times" only. His argument was as elegant as it was simple: +If Congress can extend existing terms, then there is no "stopping point" to +Congress's power under the Copyright Clause. The power to extend existing +terms means Congress is not required to grant terms that are "limited." +Thus, Judge Sentelle argued, the court had to interpret the term "limited +Times" to give it meaning. And the best interpretation, Judge Sentelle +argued, would be to deny Congress the power to extend existing terms. +

+We asked the Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit as a whole to hear the +case. Cases are ordinarily heard in panels of three, except for important +cases or cases that raise issues specific to the circuit as a whole, where +the court will sit "en banc" to hear the case. +

+ +The Court of Appeals rejected our request to hear the case en banc. This +time, Judge Sentelle was joined by the most liberal member of the +D.C. Circuit, Judge David Tatel. Both the most conservative and the most +liberal judges in the D.C. Circuit believed Congress had overstepped its +bounds. +

+It was here that most expected Eldred v. Ashcroft would die, for the Supreme +Court rarely reviews any decision by a court of appeals. (It hears about one +hundred cases a year, out of more than five thousand appeals.) And it +practically never reviews a decision that upholds a statute when no other +court has yet reviewed the statute. +

+But in February 2002, the Supreme Court surprised the world by granting our +petition to review the D.C. Circuit opinion. Argument was set for October of +2002. The summer would be spent writing briefs and preparing for argument. +

+It is over a year later as I write these words. It is still astonishingly +hard. If you know anything at all about this story, you know that we lost +the appeal. And if you know something more than just the minimum, you +probably think there was no way this case could have been won. After our +defeat, I received literally thousands of missives by well-wishers and +supporters, thanking me for my work on behalf of this noble but doomed +cause. And none from this pile was more significant to me than the e-mail +from my client, Eric Eldred. +

+Men min klient og disse vennene tok feil. Denne saken kunne vært vunnet. Det +burde ha vært vunnet. Og uansett hvor hardt jeg prøver å fortelle den +historien til meg selv, kan jeg aldri unnslippe troen på at det er min feil +at vi ikke vant. +

+ +Feil ble gjort tidlig, skjønt den ble først åpenbart på slutten. Vår sak +hadde støtte hos en ekstraordinær advokat, Geoffrey Stewart, helt fra +starten, og hos advokatfirmaet hadde han flyttet til, Jones, Day, Reavis og +Pogue. Jones Day mottok mye press fra sine opphavsrettsbeskyttende klienter +på grunn av sin støtte til oss. De ignorert dette presset (noe veldig få +advokatfirmaer noen sinne ville gjøre), og ga alt de hadde gjennom hele +saken. +

+Det var tre viktige advokater på saken fra Jones DaY. Geoff Stewart var den +først, men siden ble Dan Bromberg og Don Ayer ganske involvert. Bromberg og +Ayer spesielt hadde en felles oppfatning om hvordan denne saken ville bli +vunnet: vi ville bare vinne, fortalte de gjentatte ganger til meg, hvis vi +få problemet til å virke "viktig" for Høyesterett. Det måtte synes som om +dramatisk skade ble gjort til ytringsfriheten og fri kultur, ellers ville de +aldri stemt mot "de mektigste mediaselskapene i verden". +

+I hate this view of the law. Of course I thought the Sonny Bono Act was a +dramatic harm to free speech and free culture. Of course I still think it +is. But the idea that the Supreme Court decides the law based on how +important they believe the issues are is just wrong. It might be "right" as +in "true," I thought, but it is "wrong" as in "it just shouldn't be that +way." As I believed that any faithful interpretation of what the framers of +our Constitution did would yield the conclusion that the CTEA was +unconstitutional, and as I believed that any faithful interpretation of what +the First Amendment means would yield the conclusion that the power to +extend existing copyright terms is unconstitutional, I was not persuaded +that we had to sell our case like soap. Just as a law that bans the +swastika is unconstitutional not because the Court likes Nazis but because +such a law would violate the Constitution, so too, in my view, would the +Court decide whether Congress's law was constitutional based on the +Constitution, not based on whether they liked the values that the framers +put in the Constitution. +

+In any case, I thought, the Court must already see the danger and the harm +caused by this sort of law. Why else would they grant review? There was no +reason to hear the case in the Supreme Court if they weren't convinced that +this regulation was harmful. So in my view, we didn't need to persuade them +that this law was bad, we needed to show why it was unconstitutional. +

+ +There was one way, however, in which I felt politics would matter and in +which I thought a response was appropriate. I was convinced that the Court +would not hear our arguments if it thought these were just the arguments of +a group of lefty loons. This Supreme Court was not about to launch into a +new field of judicial review if it seemed that this field of review was +simply the preference of a small political minority. Although my focus in +the case was not to demonstrate how bad the Sonny Bono Act was but to +demonstrate that it was unconstitutional, my hope was to make this argument +against a background of briefs that covered the full range of political +views. To show that this claim against the CTEA was grounded in law and not +politics, then, we tried to gather the widest range of credible +critics—credible not because they were rich and famous, but because +they, in the aggregate, demonstrated that this law was unconstitutional +regardless of one's politics. +

+The first step happened all by itself. Phyllis Schlafly's organization, +Eagle Forum, had been an opponent of the CTEA from the very beginning. +Mrs. Schlafly viewed the CTEA as a sellout by Congress. In November 1998, +she wrote a stinging editorial attacking the Republican Congress for +allowing the law to pass. As she wrote, "Do you sometimes wonder why bills +that create a financial windfall to narrow special interests slide easily +through the intricate legislative process, while bills that benefit the +general public seem to get bogged down?" The answer, as the editorial +documented, was the power of money. Schlafly enumerated Disney's +contributions to the key players on the committees. It was money, not +justice, that gave Mickey Mouse twenty more years in Disney's control, +Schlafly argued. +

+In the Court of Appeals, Eagle Forum was eager to file a brief supporting +our position. Their brief made the argument that became the core claim in +the Supreme Court: If Congress can extend the term of existing copyrights, +there is no limit to Congress's power to set terms. That strong +conservative argument persuaded a strong conservative judge, Judge Sentelle. +

+In the Supreme Court, the briefs on our side were about as diverse as it +gets. They included an extraordinary historical brief by the Free Software +Foundation (home of the GNU project that made GNU/ Linux possible). They +included a powerful brief about the costs of uncertainty by Intel. There +were two law professors' briefs, one by copyright scholars and one by First +Amendment scholars. There was an exhaustive and uncontroverted brief by the +world's experts in the history of the Progress Clause. And of course, there +was a new brief by Eagle Forum, repeating and strengthening its arguments. + +

+Those briefs framed a legal argument. Then to support the legal argument, +there were a number of powerful briefs by libraries and archives, including +the Internet Archive, the American Association of Law Libraries, and the +National Writers Union. +

+But two briefs captured the policy argument best. One made the argument I've +already described: A brief by Hal Roach Studios argued that unless the law +was struck, a whole generation of American film would disappear. The other +made the economic argument absolutely clear. +

+This economists' brief was signed by seventeen economists, including five +Nobel Prize winners, including Ronald Coase, James Buchanan, Milton +Friedman, Kenneth Arrow, and George Akerlof. The economists, as the list of +Nobel winners demonstrates, spanned the political spectrum. Their +conclusions were powerful: There was no plausible claim that extending the +terms of existing copyrights would do anything to increase incentives to +create. Such extensions were nothing more than "rent-seeking"—the +fancy term economists use to describe special-interest legislation gone +wild. +

+The same effort at balance was reflected in the legal team we gathered to +write our briefs in the case. The Jones Day lawyers had been with us from +the start. But when the case got to the Supreme Court, we added three +lawyers to help us frame this argument to this Court: Alan Morrison, a +lawyer from Public Citizen, a Washington group that had made constitutional +history with a series of seminal victories in the Supreme Court defending +individual rights; my colleague and dean, Kathleen Sullivan, who had argued +many cases in the Court, and who had advised us early on about a First +Amendment strategy; and finally, former solicitor general Charles Fried. + +

+Fried was a special victory for our side. Every other former solicitor +general was hired by the other side to defend Congress's power to give media +companies the special favor of extended copyright terms. Fried was the only +one who turned down that lucrative assignment to stand up for something he +believed in. He had been Ronald Reagan's chief lawyer in the Supreme +Court. He had helped craft the line of cases that limited Congress's power +in the context of the Commerce Clause. And while he had argued many +positions in the Supreme Court that I personally disagreed with, his joining +the cause was a vote of confidence in our argument. +

+The government, in defending the statute, had its collection of friends, as +well. Significantly, however, none of these "friends" included historians or +economists. The briefs on the other side of the case were written +exclusively by major media companies, congressmen, and copyright holders. +

+The media companies were not surprising. They had the most to gain from the +law. The congressmen were not surprising either—they were defending +their power and, indirectly, the gravy train of contributions such power +induced. And of course it was not surprising that the copyright holders +would defend the idea that they should continue to have the right to control +who did what with content they wanted to control. +

+Dr. Seuss's representatives, for example, argued that it was better for the +Dr. Seuss estate to control what happened to Dr. Seuss's work— better +than allowing it to fall into the public domain—because if this +creativity were in the public domain, then people could use it to "glorify +drugs or to create pornography."[192] That +was also the motive of the Gershwin estate, which defended its "protection" +of the work of George Gershwin. They refuse, for example, to license Porgy +and Bess to anyone who refuses to use African Americans in the +cast.[193] That's their view of how this +part of American culture should be controlled, and they wanted this law to +help them effect that control. +

+This argument made clear a theme that is rarely noticed in this debate. +When Congress decides to extend the term of existing copyrights, Congress is +making a choice about which speakers it will favor. Famous and beloved +copyright owners, such as the Gershwin estate and Dr. Seuss, come to +Congress and say, "Give us twenty years to control the speech about these +icons of American culture. We'll do better with them than anyone else." +Congress of course likes to reward the popular and famous by giving them +what they want. But when Congress gives people an exclusive right to speak +in a certain way, that's just what the First Amendment is traditionally +meant to block. +

+We argued as much in a final brief. Not only would upholding the CTEA mean +that there was no limit to the power of Congress to extend +copyrights—extensions that would further concentrate the market; it +would also mean that there was no limit to Congress's power to play +favorites, through copyright, with who has the right to speak. Between +February and October, there was little I did beyond preparing for this +case. Early on, as I said, I set the strategy. +

+The Supreme Court was divided into two important camps. One camp we called +"the Conservatives." The other we called "the Rest." The Conservatives +included Chief Justice Rehnquist, Justice O'Connor, Justice Scalia, Justice +Kennedy, and Justice Thomas. These five had been the most consistent in +limiting Congress's power. They were the five who had supported the +Lopez/Morrison line of cases that said that an enumerated power had to be +interpreted to assure that Congress's powers had limits. +

+ +The Rest were the four Justices who had strongly opposed limits on +Congress's power. These four—Justice Stevens, Justice Souter, Justice +Ginsburg, and Justice Breyer—had repeatedly argued that the +Constitution gives Congress broad discretion to decide how best to implement +its powers. In case after case, these justices had argued that the Court's +role should be one of deference. Though the votes of these four justices +were the votes that I personally had most consistently agreed with, they +were also the votes that we were least likely to get. +

+In particular, the least likely was Justice Ginsburg's. In addition to her +general view about deference to Congress (except where issues of gender are +involved), she had been particularly deferential in the context of +intellectual property protections. She and her daughter (an excellent and +well-known intellectual property scholar) were cut from the same +intellectual property cloth. We expected she would agree with the writings +of her daughter: that Congress had the power in this context to do as it +wished, even if what Congress wished made little sense. +

+Close behind Justice Ginsburg were two justices whom we also viewed as +unlikely allies, though possible surprises. Justice Souter strongly favored +deference to Congress, as did Justice Breyer. But both were also very +sensitive to free speech concerns. And as we strongly believed, there was a +very important free speech argument against these retrospective extensions. +

+The only vote we could be confident about was that of Justice +Stevens. History will record Justice Stevens as one of the greatest judges +on this Court. His votes are consistently eclectic, which just means that no +simple ideology explains where he will stand. But he had consistently argued +for limits in the context of intellectual property generally. We were fairly +confident he would recognize limits here. +

+This analysis of "the Rest" showed most clearly where our focus had to be: +on the Conservatives. To win this case, we had to crack open these five and +get at least a majority to go our way. Thus, the single overriding argument +that animated our claim rested on the Conservatives' most important +jurisprudential innovation—the argument that Judge Sentelle had relied +upon in the Court of Appeals, that Congress's power must be interpreted so +that its enumerated powers have limits. +

+ +This then was the core of our strategy—a strategy for which I am +responsible. We would get the Court to see that just as with the Lopez case, +under the government's argument here, Congress would always have unlimited +power to extend existing terms. If anything was plain about Congress's power +under the Progress Clause, it was that this power was supposed to be +"limited." Our aim would be to get the Court to reconcile Eldred with Lopez: +If Congress's power to regulate commerce was limited, then so, too, must +Congress's power to regulate copyright be limited. +

+The argument on the government's side came down to this: Congress has done +it before. It should be allowed to do it again. The government claimed that +from the very beginning, Congress has been extending the term of existing +copyrights. So, the government argued, the Court should not now say that +practice is unconstitutional. +

+There was some truth to the government's claim, but not much. We certainly +agreed that Congress had extended existing terms in and in 1909. And of +course, in 1962, Congress began extending existing terms +regularly—eleven times in forty years. +

+ +But this "consistency" should be kept in perspective. Congress extended +existing terms once in the first hundred years of the Republic. It then +extended existing terms once again in the next fifty. Those rare extensions +are in contrast to the now regular practice of extending existing +terms. Whatever restraint Congress had had in the past, that restraint was +now gone. Congress was now in a cycle of extensions; there was no reason to +expect that cycle would end. This Court had not hesitated to intervene where +Congress was in a similar cycle of extension. There was no reason it +couldn't intervene here. Oral argument was scheduled for the first week in +October. I arrived in D.C. two weeks before the argument. During those two +weeks, I was repeatedly "mooted" by lawyers who had volunteered to help in +the case. Such "moots" are basically practice rounds, where wannabe justices +fire questions at wannabe winners. +

+I was convinced that to win, I had to keep the Court focused on a single +point: that if this extension is permitted, then there is no limit to the +power to set terms. Going with the government would mean that terms would be +effectively unlimited; going with us would give Congress a clear line to +follow: Don't extend existing terms. The moots were an effective practice; I +found ways to take every question back to this central idea. +

+One moot was before the lawyers at Jones Day. Don Ayer was the skeptic. He +had served in the Reagan Justice Department with Solicitor General Charles +Fried. He had argued many cases before the Supreme Court. And in his review +of the moot, he let his concern speak: +

+"I'm just afraid that unless they really see the harm, they won't be willing +to upset this practice that the government says has been a consistent +practice for two hundred years. You have to make them see the +harm—passionately get them to see the harm. For if they don't see +that, then we haven't any chance of winning." +

+ +He may have argued many cases before this Court, I thought, but he didn't +understand its soul. As a clerk, I had seen the Justices do the right +thing—not because of politics but because it was right. As a law +professor, I had spent my life teaching my students that this Court does the +right thing—not because of politics but because it is right. As I +listened to Ayer's plea for passion in pressing politics, I understood his +point, and I rejected it. Our argument was right. That was enough. Let the +politicians learn to see that it was also good. The night before the +argument, a line of people began to form in front of the Supreme Court. The +case had become a focus of the press and of the movement to free +culture. Hundreds stood in line for the chance to see the +proceedings. Scores spent the night on the Supreme Court steps so that they +would be assured a seat. +

+Not everyone has to wait in line. People who know the Justices can ask for +seats they control. (I asked Justice Scalia's chambers for seats for my +parents, for example.) Members of the Supreme Court bar can get a seat in a +special section reserved for them. And senators and congressmen have a +special place where they get to sit, too. And finally, of course, the press +has a gallery, as do clerks working for the Justices on the Court. As we +entered that morning, there was no place that was not taken. This was an +argument about intellectual property law, yet the halls were filled. As I +walked in to take my seat at the front of the Court, I saw my parents +sitting on the left. As I sat down at the table, I saw Jack Valenti sitting +in the special section ordinarily reserved for family of the Justices. +

+When the Chief Justice called me to begin my argument, I began where I +intended to stay: on the question of the limits on Congress's power. This +was a case about enumerated powers, I said, and whether those enumerated +powers had any limit. +

+Justice O'Connor stopped me within one minute of my opening. The history +was bothering her. +

+justice o'connor: Congress has extended the term so often through the years, +and if you are right, don't we run the risk of upsetting previous extensions +of time? I mean, this seems to be a practice that began with the very first +act. +

+She was quite willing to concede "that this flies directly in the face of +what the framers had in mind." But my response again and again was to +emphasize limits on Congress's power. +

+ +mr. lessig: Well, if it flies in the face of what the framers had in mind, +then the question is, is there a way of interpreting their words that gives +effect to what they had in mind, and the answer is yes. +

+There were two points in this argument when I should have seen where the +Court was going. The first was a question by Justice Kennedy, who observed, +

+justice kennedy: Well, I suppose implicit in the argument that the '76 act, +too, should have been declared void, and that we might leave it alone +because of the disruption, is that for all these years the act has impeded +progress in science and the useful arts. I just don't see any empirical +evidence for that. +

+Here follows my clear mistake. Like a professor correcting a student, I +answered, +

+mr. lessig: Justice, we are not making an empirical claim at all. Nothing +in our Copyright Clause claim hangs upon the empirical assertion about +impeding progress. Our only argument is this is a structural limit necessary +to assure that what would be an effectively perpetual term not be permitted +under the copyright laws. +

+That was a correct answer, but it wasn't the right answer. The right answer +was instead that there was an obvious and profound harm. Any number of +briefs had been written about it. He wanted to hear it. And here was the +place Don Ayer's advice should have mattered. This was a softball; my answer +was a swing and a miss. +

+The second came from the Chief, for whom the whole case had been +crafted. For the Chief Justice had crafted the Lopez ruling, and we hoped +that he would see this case as its second cousin. +

+ +It was clear a second into his question that he wasn't at all sympathetic. +To him, we were a bunch of anarchists. As he asked: + + +

+chief justice: Well, but you want more than that. You want the right to copy +verbatim other people's books, don't you? +

+mr. lessig: We want the right to copy verbatim works that should be in the +public domain and would be in the public domain but for a statute that +cannot be justified under ordinary First Amendment analysis or under a +proper reading of the limits built into the Copyright Clause. +

+Things went better for us when the government gave its argument; for now the +Court picked up on the core of our claim. As Justice Scalia asked Solicitor +General Olson, +

+justice scalia: You say that the functional equivalent of an unlimited time +would be a violation [of the Constitution], but that's precisely the +argument that's being made by petitioners here, that a limited time which is +extendable is the functional equivalent of an unlimited time. +

+When Olson was finished, it was my turn to give a closing rebuttal. Olson's +flailing had revived my anger. But my anger still was directed to the +academic, not the practical. The government was arguing as if this were the +first case ever to consider limits on Congress's Copyright and Patent Clause +power. Ever the professor and not the advocate, I closed by pointing out the +long history of the Court imposing limits on Congress's power in the name of +the Copyright and Patent Clause— indeed, the very first case striking +a law of Congress as exceeding a specific enumerated power was based upon +the Copyright and Patent Clause. All true. But it wasn't going to move the +Court to my side. +

+ +As I left the court that day, I knew there were a hundred points I wished I +could remake. There were a hundred questions I wished I had answered +differently. But one way of thinking about this case left me optimistic. +

+The government had been asked over and over again, what is the limit? Over +and over again, it had answered there is no limit. This was precisely the +answer I wanted the Court to hear. For I could not imagine how the Court +could understand that the government believed Congress's power was unlimited +under the terms of the Copyright Clause, and sustain the government's +argument. The solicitor general had made my argument for me. No matter how +often I tried, I could not understand how the Court could find that +Congress's power under the Commerce Clause was limited, but under the +Copyright Clause, unlimited. In those rare moments when I let myself believe +that we may have prevailed, it was because I felt this Court—in +particular, the Conservatives—would feel itself constrained by the +rule of law that it had established elsewhere. +

+The morning of January 15, 2003, I was five minutes late to the office and +missed the 7:00 A.M. call from the Supreme Court clerk. Listening to the +message, I could tell in an instant that she had bad news to report.The +Supreme Court had affirmed the decision of the Court of Appeals. Seven +justices had voted in the majority. There were two dissents. +

+A few seconds later, the opinions arrived by e-mail. I took the phone off +the hook, posted an announcement to our blog, and sat down to see where I +had been wrong in my reasoning. +

+My reasoning. Here was a case that pitted all the money in the world against +reasoning. And here was the last naïve law professor, scouring the pages, +looking for reasoning. +

+I first scoured the opinion, looking for how the Court would distinguish the +principle in this case from the principle in Lopez. The argument was nowhere +to be found. The case was not even cited. The argument that was the core +argument of our case did not even appear in the Court's opinion. +

+ + + +Justice Ginsburg simply ignored the enumerated powers argument. Consistent +with her view that Congress's power was not limited generally, she had found +Congress's power not limited here. +

+Her opinion was perfectly reasonable—for her, and for Justice +Souter. Neither believes in Lopez. It would be too much to expect them to +write an opinion that recognized, much less explained, the doctrine they had +worked so hard to defeat. +

+But as I realized what had happened, I couldn't quite believe what I was +reading. I had said there was no way this Court could reconcile limited +powers with the Commerce Clause and unlimited powers with the Progress +Clause. It had never even occurred to me that they could reconcile the two +simply by not addressing the argument. There was no inconsistency because +they would not talk about the two together. There was therefore no +principle that followed from the Lopez case: In that context, Congress's +power would be limited, but in this context it would not. +

+Yet by what right did they get to choose which of the framers' values they +would respect? By what right did they—the silent five—get to +select the part of the Constitution they would enforce based on the values +they thought important? We were right back to the argument that I said I +hated at the start: I had failed to convince them that the issue here was +important, and I had failed to recognize that however much I might hate a +system in which the Court gets to pick the constitutional values that it +will respect, that is the system we have. +

+Justices Breyer and Stevens wrote very strong dissents. Stevens's opinion +was crafted internal to the law: He argued that the tradition of +intellectual property law should not support this unjustified extension of +terms. He based his argument on a parallel analysis that had governed in the +context of patents (so had we). But the rest of the Court discounted the +parallel—without explaining how the very same words in the Progress +Clause could come to mean totally different things depending upon whether +the words were about patents or copyrights. The Court let Justice Stevens's +charge go unanswered. +

+ + +Justice Breyer's opinion, perhaps the best opinion he has ever written, was +external to the Constitution. He argued that the term of copyrights has +become so long as to be effectively unlimited. We had said that under the +current term, a copyright gave an author 99.8 percent of the value of a +perpetual term. Breyer said we were wrong, that the actual number was +99.9997 percent of a perpetual term. Either way, the point was clear: If the +Constitution said a term had to be "limited," and the existing term was so +long as to be effectively unlimited, then it was unconstitutional. +

+These two justices understood all the arguments we had made. But because +neither believed in the Lopez case, neither was willing to push it as a +reason to reject this extension. The case was decided without anyone having +addressed the argument that we had carried from Judge Sentelle. It was +Hamlet without the Prince. +

+Defeat brings depression. They say it is a sign of health when depression +gives way to anger. My anger came quickly, but it didn't cure the +depression. This anger was of two sorts. +

+It was first anger with the five "Conservatives." It would have been one +thing for them to have explained why the principle of Lopez didn't apply in +this case. That wouldn't have been a very convincing argument, I don't +believe, having read it made by others, and having tried to make it +myself. But it at least would have been an act of integrity. These justices +in particular have repeatedly said that the proper mode of interpreting the +Constitution is "originalism"—to first understand the framers' text, +interpreted in their context, in light of the structure of the +Constitution. That method had produced Lopez and many other "originalist" +rulings. Where was their "originalism" now? +

+ +Here, they had joined an opinion that never once tried to explain what the +framers had meant by crafting the Progress Clause as they did; they joined +an opinion that never once tried to explain how the structure of that clause +would affect the interpretation of Congress's power. And they joined an +opinion that didn't even try to explain why this grant of power could be +unlimited, whereas the Commerce Clause would be limited. In short, they had +joined an opinion that did not apply to, and was inconsistent with, their +own method for interpreting the Constitution. This opinion may well have +yielded a result that they liked. It did not produce a reason that was +consistent with their own principles. +

+My anger with the Conservatives quickly yielded to anger with myself. For I +had let a view of the law that I liked interfere with a view of the law as +it is. +

+Most lawyers, and most law professors, have little patience for idealism +about courts in general and this Supreme Court in particular. Most have a +much more pragmatic view. When Don Ayer said that this case would be won +based on whether I could convince the Justices that the framers' values were +important, I fought the idea, because I didn't want to believe that that is +how this Court decides. I insisted on arguing this case as if it were a +simple application of a set of principles. I had an argument that followed +in logic. I didn't need to waste my time showing it should also follow in +popularity. +

+ +As I read back over the transcript from that argument in October, I can see +a hundred places where the answers could have taken the conversation in +different directions, where the truth about the harm that this unchecked +power will cause could have been made clear to this Court. Justice Kennedy +in good faith wanted to be shown. I, idiotically, corrected his +question. Justice Souter in good faith wanted to be shown the First +Amendment harms. I, like a math teacher, reframed the question to make the +logical point. I had shown them how they could strike this law of Congress +if they wanted to. There were a hundred places where I could have helped +them want to, yet my stubbornness, my refusal to give in, stopped me. I have +stood before hundreds of audiences trying to persuade; I have used passion +in that effort to persuade; but I refused to stand before this audience and +try to persuade with the passion I had used elsewhere. It was not the basis +on which a court should decide the issue. +

+Would it have been different if I had argued it differently? Would it have +been different if Don Ayer had argued it? Or Charles Fried? Or Kathleen +Sullivan? +

+My friends huddled around me to insist it would not. The Court was not +ready, my friends insisted. This was a loss that was destined. It would take +a great deal more to show our society why our framers were right. And when +we do that, we will be able to show that Court. +

+Maybe, but I doubt it. These Justices have no financial interest in doing +anything except the right thing. They are not lobbied. They have little +reason to resist doing right. I can't help but think that if I had stepped +down from this pretty picture of dispassionate justice, I could have +persuaded. +

+And even if I couldn't, then that doesn't excuse what happened in +January. For at the start of this case, one of America's leading +intellectual property professors stated publicly that my bringing this case +was a mistake. "The Court is not ready," Peter Jaszi said; this issue should +not be raised until it is. +

+ +After the argument and after the decision, Peter said to me, and publicly, +that he was wrong. But if indeed that Court could not have been persuaded, +then that is all the evidence that's needed to know that here again Peter +was right. Either I was not ready to argue this case in a way that would do +some good or they were not ready to hear this case in a way that would do +some good. Either way, the decision to bring this case—a decision I +had made four years before—was wrong. While the reaction to the Sonny +Bono Act itself was almost unanimously negative, the reaction to the Court's +decision was mixed. No one, at least in the press, tried to say that +extending the term of copyright was a good idea. We had won that battle over +ideas. Where the decision was praised, it was praised by papers that had +been skeptical of the Court's activism in other cases. Deference was a good +thing, even if it left standing a silly law. But where the decision was +attacked, it was attacked because it left standing a silly and harmful +law. The New York Times wrote in its editorial, +

+In effect, the Supreme Court's decision makes it likely that we are seeing +the beginning of the end of public domain and the birth of copyright +perpetuity. The public domain has been a grand experiment, one that should +not be allowed to die. The ability to draw freely on the entire creative +output of humanity is one of the reasons we live in a time of such fruitful +creative ferment. +

+The best responses were in the cartoons. There was a gaggle of hilarious +images—of Mickey in jail and the like. The best, from my view of the +case, was Ruben Bolling's, reproduced on the next page. The "powerful and +wealthy" line is a bit unfair. But the punch in the face felt exactly like +that. +

+The image that will always stick in my head is that evoked by the quote from +The New York Times. That "grand experiment" we call the "public domain" is +over? When I can make light of it, I think, "Honey, I shrunk the +Constitution." But I can rarely make light of it. We had in our Constitution +a commitment to free culture. In the case that I fathered, the Supreme Court +effectively renounced that commitment. A better lawyer would have made them +see differently. +

Kapittel fjorten: Eldred II

+The day Eldred was decided, fate would have it that I was to travel to +Washington, D.C. (The day the rehearing petition in Eldred was +denied—meaning the case was really finally over—fate would have +it that I was giving a speech to technologists at Disney World.) This was a +particularly long flight to my least favorite city. The drive into the city +from Dulles was delayed because of traffic, so I opened up my computer and +wrote an op-ed piece. +

+It was an act of contrition. During the whole of the flight from San +Francisco to Washington, I had heard over and over again in my head the same +advice from Don Ayer: You need to make them see why it is important. And +alternating with that command was the question of Justice Kennedy: "For all +these years the act has impeded progress in science and the useful arts. I +just don't see any empirical evidence for that." And so, having failed in +the argument of constitutional principle, finally, I turned to an argument +of politics. +

+ +The New York Times published the piece. In it, I proposed a simple fix: +Fifty years after a work has been published, the copyright owner would be +required to register the work and pay a small fee. If he paid the fee, he +got the benefit of the full term of copyright. If he did not, the work +passed into the public domain. +

+We called this the Eldred Act, but that was just to give it a name. Eric +Eldred was kind enough to let his name be used once again, but as he said +early on, it won't get passed unless it has another name. +

+Or another two names. For depending upon your perspective, this is either +the "Public Domain Enhancement Act" or the "Copyright Term Deregulation +Act." Either way, the essence of the idea is clear and obvious: Remove +copyright where it is doing nothing except blocking access and the spread of +knowledge. Leave it for as long as Congress allows for those works where its +worth is at least $1. But for everything else, let the content go. +

+The reaction to this idea was amazingly strong. Steve Forbes endorsed it in +an editorial. I received an avalanche of e-mail and letters expressing +support. When you focus the issue on lost creativity, people can see the +copyright system makes no sense. As a good Republican might say, here +government regulation is simply getting in the way of innovation and +creativity. And as a good Democrat might say, here the government is +blocking access and the spread of knowledge for no good reason. Indeed, +there is no real difference between Democrats and Republicans on this +issue. Anyone can recognize the stupid harm of the present system. +

+Indeed, many recognized the obvious benefit of the registration +requirement. For one of the hardest things about the current system for +people who want to license content is that there is no obvious place to look +for the current copyright owners. Since registration is not required, since +marking content is not required, since no formality at all is required, it +is often impossibly hard to locate copyright owners to ask permission to use +or license their work. This system would lower these costs, by establishing +at least one registry where copyright owners could be identified. +

+ +As I described in chapter 10, formalities in copyright law were removed in +1976, when Congress followed the Europeans by abandoning any formal +requirement before a copyright is granted.[194] The Europeans are said to view copyright as a "natural right." +Natural rights don't need forms to exist. Traditions, like the +Anglo-American tradition that required copyright owners to follow form if +their rights were to be protected, did not, the Europeans thought, properly +respect the dignity of the author. My right as a creator turns on my +creativity, not upon the special favor of the government. +

+That's great rhetoric. It sounds wonderfully romantic. But it is absurd +copyright policy. It is absurd especially for authors, because a world +without formalities harms the creator. The ability to spread "Walt Disney +creativity" is destroyed when there is no simple way to know what's +protected and what's not. +

+The fight against formalities achieved its first real victory in Berlin in +1908. International copyright lawyers amended the Berne Convention in 1908, +to require copyright terms of life plus fifty years, as well as the +abolition of copyright formalities. The formalities were hated because the +stories of inadvertent loss were increasingly common. It was as if a Charles +Dickens character ran all copyright offices, and the failure to dot an i or +cross a t resulted in the loss of widows' only income. +

+These complaints were real and sensible. And the strictness of the +formalities, especially in the United States, was absurd. The law should +always have ways of forgiving innocent mistakes. There is no reason +copyright law couldn't, as well. Rather than abandoning formalities totally, +the response in Berlin should have been to embrace a more equitable system +of registration. +

+Even that would have been resisted, however, because registration in the +nineteenth and twentieth centuries was still expensive. It was also a +hassle. The abolishment of formalities promised not only to save the +starving widows, but also to lighten an unnecessary regulatory burden +imposed upon creators. +

+ +In addition to the practical complaint of authors in 1908, there was a moral +claim as well. There was no reason that creative property should be a +second-class form of property. If a carpenter builds a table, his rights +over the table don't depend upon filing a form with the government. He has +a property right over the table "naturally," and he can assert that right +against anyone who would steal the table, whether or not he has informed the +government of his ownership of the table. +

+This argument is correct, but its implications are misleading. For the +argument in favor of formalities does not depend upon creative property +being second-class property. The argument in favor of formalities turns upon +the special problems that creative property presents. The law of +formalities responds to the special physics of creative property, to assure +that it can be efficiently and fairly spread. +

+No one thinks, for example, that land is second-class property just because +you have to register a deed with a court if your sale of land is to be +effective. And few would think a car is second-class property just because +you must register the car with the state and tag it with a license. In both +of those cases, everyone sees that there is an important reason to secure +registration—both because it makes the markets more efficient and +because it better secures the rights of the owner. Without a registration +system for land, landowners would perpetually have to guard their +property. With registration, they can simply point the police to a +deed. Without a registration system for cars, auto theft would be much +easier. With a registration system, the thief has a high burden to sell a +stolen car. A slight burden is placed on the property owner, but those +burdens produce a much better system of protection for property generally. +

+It is similarly special physics that makes formalities important in +copyright law. Unlike a carpenter's table, there's nothing in nature that +makes it relatively obvious who might own a particular bit of creative +property. A recording of Lyle Lovett's latest album can exist in a billion +places without anything necessarily linking it back to a particular +owner. And like a car, there's no way to buy and sell creative property with +confidence unless there is some simple way to authenticate who is the author +and what rights he has. Simple transactions are destroyed in a world without +formalities. Complex, expensive, lawyer transactions take their place. + +

+This was the understanding of the problem with the Sonny Bono Act that we +tried to demonstrate to the Court. This was the part it didn't "get." +Because we live in a system without formalities, there is no way easily to +build upon or use culture from our past. If copyright terms were, as Justice +Story said they would be, "short," then this wouldn't matter much. For +fourteen years, under the framers' system, a work would be presumptively +controlled. After fourteen years, it would be presumptively uncontrolled. +

+But now that copyrights can be just about a century long, the inability to +know what is protected and what is not protected becomes a huge and obvious +burden on the creative process. If the only way a library can offer an +Internet exhibit about the New Deal is to hire a lawyer to clear the rights +to every image and sound, then the copyright system is burdening creativity +in a way that has never been seen before because there are no formalities. +

+The Eldred Act was designed to respond to exactly this problem. If it is +worth $1 to you, then register your work and you can get the longer +term. Others will know how to contact you and, therefore, how to get your +permission if they want to use your work. And you will get the benefit of an +extended copyright term. +

+If it isn't worth it to you to register to get the benefit of an extended +term, then it shouldn't be worth it for the government to defend your +monopoly over that work either. The work should pass into the public domain +where anyone can copy it, or build archives with it, or create a movie based +on it. It should become free if it is not worth $1 to you. +

+Noen bekymrer seg over byrden på forfattere. Gjør ikke byrden med å +registrere verket at beløpet $1 egentlig er misvisende? Er ikke +ekstraarbeidet verdt mer enn $1? Er ikke dette det virkelige problemet med +registrering? +

+ +It is. The hassle is terrible. The system that exists now is awful. I +completely agree that the Copyright Office has done a terrible job (no doubt +because they are terribly funded) in enabling simple and cheap +registrations. Any real solution to the problem of formalities must address +the real problem of governments standing at the core of any system of +formalities. In this book, I offer such a solution. That solution +essentially remakes the Copyright Office. For now, assume it was Amazon that +ran the registration system. Assume it was one-click registration. The +Eldred Act would propose a simple, one-click registration fifty years after +a work was published. Based upon historical data, that system would move up +to 98 percent of commercial work, commercial work that no longer had a +commercial life, into the public domain within fifty years. What do you +think? +

+Da Steve Forbes støttet idéen, begynte enkelte i Washington å følge +med. Mange kontaktet meg med tips til representanter som kan være villig til +å introdusere en Eldred-lov. og jeg hadde noen få som foreslo direkte at de +kan være villige til å ta det første skrittet. +

+En representant, Zoe Lofgren fra California, gikk så langt som å få +lovforslaget utarbeidet. Utkastet løste noen problemer med internasjonal +lov. Det påla de enklest mulige forutsetninger på innehaverne av +opphavsretter. I mai 2003 så det ut som om loven skulle være introdusert. +16. mai, postet jeg på Eldred Act-bloggen, "vi er nære". Det oppstod en +generell reaksjon i blogg-samfunnet om at noe godt kunne skje her. + +

+But at this stage, the lobbyists began to intervene. Jack Valenti and the +MPAA general counsel came to the congresswoman's office to give the view of +the MPAA. Aided by his lawyer, as Valenti told me, Valenti informed the +congresswoman that the MPAA would oppose the Eldred Act. The reasons are +embarrassingly thin. More importantly, their thinness shows something clear +about what this debate is really about. +

+ +The MPAA argued first that Congress had "firmly rejected the central concept +in the proposed bill"—that copyrights be renewed. That was true, but +irrelevant, as Congress's "firm rejection" had occurred long before the +Internet made subsequent uses much more likely. Second, they argued that +the proposal would harm poor copyright owners—apparently those who +could not afford the $1 fee. Third, they argued that Congress had determined +that extending a copyright term would encourage restoration work. Maybe in +the case of the small percentage of work covered by copyright law that is +still commercially valuable, but again this was irrelevant, as the proposal +would not cut off the extended term unless the $1 fee was not paid. Fourth, +the MPAA argued that the bill would impose "enormous" costs, since a +registration system is not free. True enough, but those costs are certainly +less than the costs of clearing the rights for a copyright whose owner is +not known. Fifth, they worried about the risks if the copyright to a story +underlying a film were to pass into the public domain. But what risk is +that? If it is in the public domain, then the film is a valid derivative +use. +

+Finally, the MPAA argued that existing law enabled copyright owners to do +this if they wanted. But the whole point is that there are thousands of +copyright owners who don't even know they have a copyright to give. Whether +they are free to give away their copyright or not—a controversial +claim in any case—unless they know about a copyright, they're not +likely to. +

+At the beginning of this book, I told two stories about the law reacting to +changes in technology. In the one, common sense prevailed. In the other, +common sense was delayed. The difference between the two stories was the +power of the opposition—the power of the side that fought to defend +the status quo. In both cases, a new technology threatened old +interests. But in only one case did those interest's have the power to +protect themselves against this new competitive threat. +

+Jeg brukte disse to tilfellene som en måte å ramme inn krigen som denne +boken har handlet om. For her er det også en ny teknologi som tvinger loven +til å reagere. Og her bør vi også spørre, er loven i tråd med eller i strid +med sunn fornuft. Hvis sunn fornuft støtter loven, hva forklarer denne +sunne fornuften? +

+ + + +When the issue is piracy, it is right for the law to back the copyright +owners. The commercial piracy that I described is wrong and harmful, and the +law should work to eliminate it. When the issue is p2p sharing, it is easy +to understand why the law backs the owners still: Much of this sharing is +wrong, even if much is harmless. When the issue is copyright terms for the +Mickey Mouses of the world, it is possible still to understand why the law +favors Hollywood: Most people don't recognize the reasons for limiting +copyright terms; it is thus still possible to see good faith within the +resistance. +

+But when the copyright owners oppose a proposal such as the Eldred Act, +then, finally, there is an example that lays bare the naked selfinterest +driving this war. This act would free an extraordinary range of content that +is otherwise unused. It wouldn't interfere with any copyright owner's desire +to exercise continued control over his content. It would simply liberate +what Kevin Kelly calls the "Dark Content" that fills archives around the +world. So when the warriors oppose a change like this, we should ask one +simple question: +

+Hva ønsker denne industrien egentlig? +

+With very little effort, the warriors could protect their content. So the +effort to block something like the Eldred Act is not really about protecting +their content. The effort to block the Eldred Act is an effort to assure +that nothing more passes into the public domain. It is another step to +assure that the public domain will never compete, that there will be no use +of content that is not commercially controlled, and that there will be no +commercial use of content that doesn't require their permission first. +

+The opposition to the Eldred Act reveals how extreme the other side is. The +most powerful and sexy and well loved of lobbies really has as its aim not +the protection of "property" but the rejection of a tradition. Their aim is +not simply to protect what is theirs. Their aim is to assure that all there +is is what is theirs. +

+ +It is not hard to understand why the warriors take this view. It is not hard +to see why it would benefit them if the competition of the public domain +tied to the Internet could somehow be quashed. Just as RCA feared the +competition of FM, they fear the competition of a public domain connected to +a public that now has the means to create with it and to share its own +creation. +

+What is hard to understand is why the public takes this view. It is as if +the law made airplanes trespassers. The MPAA stands with the Causbys and +demands that their remote and useless property rights be respected, so that +these remote and forgotten copyright holders might block the progress of +others. +

+All this seems to follow easily from this untroubled acceptance of the +"property" in intellectual property. Common sense supports it, and so long +as it does, the assaults will rain down upon the technologies of the +Internet. The consequence will be an increasing "permission society." The +past can be cultivated only if you can identify the owner and gain +permission to build upon his work. The future will be controlled by this +dead (and often unfindable) hand of the past. +



[179] + + +There's a parallel here with pornography that is a bit hard to describe, but +it's a strong one. One phenomenon that the Internet created was a world of +noncommercial pornographers—people who were distributing porn but were +not making money directly or indirectly from that distribution. Such a +class didn't exist before the Internet came into being because the costs of +distributing porn were so high. Yet this new class of distributors got +special attention in the Supreme Court, when the Court struck down the +Communications Decency Act of 1996. It was partly because of the burden on +noncommercial speakers that the statute was found to exceed Congress's +power. The same point could have been made about noncommercial publishers +after the advent of the Internet. The Eric Eldreds of the world before the +Internet were extremely few. Yet one would think it at least as important to +protect the Eldreds of the world as to protect noncommercial pornographers.

[180] + + +The full text is: "Sonny [Bono] wanted the term of copyright protection to +last forever. I am informed by staff that such a change would violate the +Constitution. I invite all of you to work with me to strengthen our +copyright laws in all of the ways available to us. As you know, there is +also Jack Valenti's proposal for a term to last forever less one +day. Perhaps the Committee may look at that next Congress," 144 +Cong. Rec. H9946, 9951-2 (October 7, 1998). +

[181] + +Associated Press, "Disney Lobbying for Copyright Extension No Mickey Mouse +Effort; Congress OKs Bill Granting Creators 20 More Years," Chicago Tribune, +17. oktober 1998, 22. +

[182] + +Se Nick Brown, "Fair Use No More?: Copyright in the Information Age," +tilgjengelig fra link +#49. +

[183] + +Alan K. Ota, "Disney in Washington: The Mouse That Roars," Congressional +Quarterly This Week, 8. august 1990, tilgjengelig fra link #50. +

[184] + +United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 564 (1995). +

[185] + +United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000). +

[186] + +If it is a principle about enumerated powers, then the principle carries +from one enumerated power to another. The animating point in the context of +the Commerce Clause was that the interpretation offered by the government +would allow the government unending power to regulate commerce—the +limitation to interstate commerce notwithstanding. The same point is true in +the context of the Copyright Clause. Here, too, the government's +interpretation would allow the government unending power to regulate +copyrights—the limitation to "limited times" notwithstanding. +

[187] + +Brief of the Nashville Songwriters Association, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 +U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01-618), n.10, available at link #51. +

[188] + +The figure of 2 percent is an extrapolation from the study by the +Congressional Research Service, in light of the estimated renewal +ranges. See Brief of Petitioners, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 7, available at link #52. +

[189] + + +See David G. Savage, "High Court Scene of Showdown on Copyright Law," Los +Angeles Times, 6 October 2002; David Streitfeld, "Classic Movies, Songs, +Books at Stake; Supreme Court Hears Arguments Today on Striking Down +Copyright Extension," Orlando Sentinel Tribune, 9 October 2002. +

[190] + +Brief of Hal Roach Studios and Michael Agee as Amicus Curiae Supporting the +Petitoners, Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186 (2003) (No. 01- 618), 12. See +also Brief of Amicus Curiae filed on behalf of Petitioners by the Internet +Archive, Eldred v. Ashcroft, available at link #53. +

[191] + + +Jason Schultz, "The Myth of the 1976 Copyright `Chaos' Theory," 20 December +2002, tilgjengelig fra link +#54. +

[192] + + +Brief of Amici Dr. Seuss Enterprise et al., Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. +(2003) (No. 01-618), 19. +

[193] + + +Dinitia Smith, "Immortal Words, Immortal Royalties? Even Mickey Mouse Joins +the Fray," New York Times, 28 March 1998, B7. +

[194] + + +Until the 1908 Berlin Act of the Berne Convention, national copyright +legislation sometimes made protection depend upon compliance with +formalities such as registration, deposit, and affixation of notice of the +author's claim of copyright. However, starting with the 1908 act, every text +of the Convention has provided that "the enjoyment and the exercise" of +rights guaranteed by the Convention "shall not be subject to any formality." +The prohibition against formalities is presently embodied in Article 5(2) of +the Paris Text of the Berne Convention. Many countries continue to impose +some form of deposit or registration requirement, albeit not as a condition +of copyright. French law, for example, requires the deposit of copies of +works in national repositories, principally the National Museum. Copies of +books published in the United Kingdom must be deposited in the British +Library. The German Copyright Act provides for a Registrar of Authors where +the author's true name can be filed in the case of anonymous or pseudonymous +works. Paul Goldstein, International Intellectual Property Law, Cases and +Materials (New York: Foundation Press, 2001), 153–54.

Kapittel 6. Konklusjon

+Det er mer enn trettifem millioner mennesker over hele verden med +AIDS-viruset. Tjuefem millioner av dem bor i Afrika sør for Sahara. Sytten +millioner har allerede dødd. Sytten millioner afrikanere er prosentvis +proporsjonalt med syv millioner amerikanere. Viktigere er det at dette er +17 millioner afrikanere. +

+Det finnes ingen kur for AIDS, men det finnes medisiner som kan hemme +sykdommens utvikling. Disse antiretrovirale terapiene er fortsatt +eksperimentelle, men de har hatt en dramatisk effekt allerede. I USA øker +AIDS-pasienter som regelmessig tar en cocktail av disse medisinene sin +levealder med ti til tjue år. For noen gjøre medisinene sykdommen nesten +usynlig. +

+Disse medisinene er dyre. Da de ble først introdusert i USA, kostet de +mellom $10 000 og $15 000 pr. person hvert år. I dag koster noen av dem $25 +000 pr. år. Med disse prisene har, selvfølgelig, ingen afrikansk stat råd +til medisinen for det store flertall av sine innbyggere: $15 000 er tredve +ganger brutto nasjonalprodukt pr. innbygger i Zimbabwe. Med slike priser er +disse medisinene fullstendig utilgjengelig.[195] +

+ + +Disse prisene er ikke høye fordi ingrediensene til medisinene er dyre. +Disse prisene er høye fordi medisinene er beskyttet av patenter. +Farmasiselskapene som produserer disse livreddende blandingene nyter minst +tjue års monopol på sine oppfinnelser. De bruker denne monopolmakten til å +hente ut så mye de kan fra markedet. Ved hjelp av denne makten holder de +prisene høye. +

+Det er mange som er skeptiske til patenter, spesielt patenter på +medisiner. Det er ikke jeg. Faktisk av alle forskningsområder som kan være +støttet av patenter, er forskning på medisiner, etter min mening, det +klareste tilfelle der patenter er nødvendig. Patenter gir et farmasøytiske +firma en viss forsikring om at hvis det lykkes i å finne opp et nytt +medikament som kan behandle en sykdom, vil det kunne tjene tilbake +investeringen og mer til. Dette ber sosialt et ekstremt verdifullt +insentiv. Jeg er den siste personen som vil argumentere for at loven skal +avskaffe dette, i det minste uten andre endringer. +

+Men det er én ting å støtte patenter, selv patenter på medisiner. Det er en +annen ting å avgjøre hvordan en best skal håndtere en krise. Og i det +afrikanske ledere begynte å erkjenne ødeleggelsen AIDS brakte, begynte de å +se etter måter å importere HIV-medisiner til kostnader betydelig under +markedspris. +

+I 1997 forsøkte Sør-Afrika seg på en tilnærming. Landet vedtok en lov som +tillot import av patenterte medisiner som hadde blitt produsert og solgt i +en annen nasjons marked med godkjenning fra patenteieren. For eksempel, +hvis medisinen var solgt i India, så kunne den bli importert inn til Afrika +fra India. Dette kalles "parallellimport" og er generelt tillatt i +internasjonal handelslovgivning, og spesifikt tillatt i den europeiske +union.[196] +

+Men USA var imot lovendringen. Og de nøyde seg ikke med å være imot. Som +International Intellectual Property Association karakteriserte det, +"Myndighetene i USA presset Sør-Afrika . . . til å ikke tillate tvungen +lisensiering eller parallellimport"[197] +Gjennom kontoret til USAs handelsrepresentant (USTR), ba myndighetene +Sør-Afrika om å endre loven—og for å legge press bak den +forespørselen, listet USTR i 1998 opp Sør-Afrika som et land som burde +vurderes for handelsrestriksjoner. Samme år gikk mer enn førti +farmasiselskaper til retten for å utfordre myndighetenes handlinger. USA +fikk selskap av andre myndigheter fra EU. Deres påstand, og påstanden til +farmasiselskapene, var at Sør-Afrika brøt sine internasjonale forpliktelser +ved å distriminere mot en bestemt type patenter—farmasøytiske +patenter. Kravet fra disse myndighetene, med USA i spissen, var at +Sør-Afrika skulle respektere disse patentene på samme måte som alle andre +patenter, uavhengig av eventuell effekt på behandlingen av AIDS i +Sør-Afrika.[198] +

+Vi bør sette intervensjonen til USA i sammenheng. Det er ingen tvil om at +patenter ikke er den viktigste årsaken til at Afrikanere ikke har tilgang +til medisiner. Fattigdom og den totale mangel på effektivt helsevesen betyr +mer. Men uansett om patenter er en viktigste grunnen eller ikke, så har +prisen på medisiner en effekt på etterspørselen, og patenter påvirker +prisen. Så uansett, massiv eller marginal, så var det en effekt av våre +myndigheters intervensjon for å stoppe flyten av medisiner inn til Afrika. +

+Ved å stoppe flyten av HIV-behandling til Afrika, sikret ikke myndighetene i +USA medisiner til USA borgere. Dette er ikke som hvete (hvis de spise det så +kan ikke vi spise det). Det som USA i effekt intervenerte for å stoppe, var +flyten av kunnskap: Informasjon om hvordan en kan ta kjemikalier som finnes +i Afrika og gjøre disse kjemikaliene om til medisiner som kan redde 15 til +30 millioner liv. +

+Intervensjonen fra USA ville heller ikke beskytte fortjenesten til +medisinselskapene i USA— i hvert fall ikke betydelig. Det var jo ikke +slik at disse landene hadde mulighet til å kjøpe medisinene til de prisene +som medisinselskapene forlangte. Igjen var afrikanerne for fattige til å ha +råd til disse medisinene til de tilbudte prisene. Å blokkere for +parallellimport av disse medisinene ville ikke øke salget til de amerikanske +selskapene betydelig. +

+I stedet var argumentet til fordel for restriksjoner på denne flyten av +informasjon, som var nødvendig for å redde millioner av liv, et argument om +eiendoms ukrenkelighet.[199] Det var på +grunn av at "intellektuell eiendom" ville bli krenket at disse medisinene +ikke skulle flomme inn til Afrika. Det var prinsippet om viktigheten av +"intellektuell eiendom" som fikk disse myndighetsaktørene til å intervenere +mot Sør-Afrikas mottiltak mot AIDS. +

+La oss ta et skritt tilbake for et øyeblikk. En gang om tredve år vil våre +barn se tilbake på oss og spørre, hvordan kunne vi la dette skje? Hvordan +kunne vi tillate å gjennomføre en politikk hvis direkte kostnad var få 15 +til 30 millioner afrikanere til å dø raskere, og hvis eneste virkelige +fordel var å opprettholde "ukrenkeligheten" til en idé? Hva slags +berettigelse kan noen sinne eksistere for en politikk som resulterer i så +mange døde? Hva slags galskap er det egentlig som tillater at så mange dør +for slik en abstraksjon? +

+Noen skylder på farmasiselskapene. Det gjør ikke jeg. De er selskaper, og +deres ledere er lovpålagt å tjene penger for selskapene. De presser på for +en bestemt patentpolitikk, ikke på grunn av idealer, men fordi det er dette +som gjør at de tjener mest penger. Og dette gjør kun at de tjener mest +penger på grunn av en slags korrupsjon i vårt politiske system— en +korrupsjon som farmasiselskapene helt klart ikke er ansvarlige for. +

+Denne korrupsjonen er våre egne politikeres manglende integritet. For +medisinprodusentene ville elske—sier de selv, og jeg tror dem — +å selge sine medisiner så billig som de kan til land i Afrika og andre +steder. Det er utfordringer de må løse å sikre at medisinene ikke kommer +tilbake til USA, men dette er bare teknologiske utfordring. De kan bli +overvunnet. +

+ +Et annet problem kan derimot ikke løses. Det er frykten for at en politiker +som skal vise seg og kaller inn lederne hos medisinprodusentene til høring i +senatet eller representantenes hus og spør, "hvordan har det seg at du kan +selge HIV-medisinen i Afrika for bare $1 pr. pille, mens samme pille koster +en amerikansker $1500?" Da det ikke finnes et "kjapt svar" på det +spørsmålet, ville effekten bli regulering av priser i Amerika. +Medisinprodusentene unngård dermed denne spiralen ved å sikre at det første +steget ikke tas. De forsterker idéen om at eierrettigheter skal være +ukrenkelige. De legger seg på en rasjonell strategi i en irrasjonell +omgivelse, med den utilsiktede konsekvens at kanskje millioner dør. Og den +rasjonelle strategien rammes dermed inn ved hjel av dette +ideal—helligheten til en idé som kalles "immaterielle rettigheter". +

+Så når du konfronteres av ditt barns sunne fornuft, hva vil du si? Når den +sunne fornuften hos en generasjon endelig gjør opprør mot hva vi har gjort, +hvordan vil vi rettferdiggjøre det? Hva er argumentet? +

+En fornuftig patentpolitikk kunne gå god for og gi sterk støtte til +patentsystemet uten å måtte nå alle overalt på nøyaktig samme måte. På samme +måte som en fornuftig opphavsrettspolitikk kunne gå god for og gi sterk +støtte til et opphavsretts-system uten å måtte regulere spredningen av +kultur perfekt og for alltid. En fornuftig patentpolitikk kunne gå god for +og gi sterk støtte til et patentsystem uten å måtte blokkere spredning av +medisiner til et land som uansett ikke er rikt nok til å ha råd til +markedsprisen. En fornuftig politikk kan en dermed si kunne være en +balansert politikk. For det meste av vår historie har både opphavsrett- og +patentpolitikken i denne forstand vært balansert. +

+ +Men vi som kultur har mistet denne følelsen for balanse. Vi har mistet det +kritiske blikket som hjelper oss til å se forkjellen mellom sannhet og +ekstremisme. En slags eiendomsfundamentalisme, uten grunnlag i vår +tradisjon, hersker nå i vår kultur—sært, og med konsekvenser mer +alvorlig for spredningen av idéer og kultur enn nesten enhver annen politisk +enkeltavgjørelse vi som demokrati kan fatte. En enkel idé blender oss, og +under dekke av mørket skjer mye som de fleste av oss ville avvist hvis vi +hadde fulgt med. Så ukritisk aksepterer vi idéen om eierskap til idéer at +vi ikke engang legger merke til hvor uhyrlig det er å nekte tilgang til +idéer for et folk som dør uten dem. Så ukritisk aksepterer vi idéen om +eiendom til kulturen at vi ikke engang stiller spørsmål ved når kontrollen +over denne eiendommen fjerner vår evne, som folk, til å utvikle vår kultur +demokratisk. Blindhet blir vår sunne fornuft, og utfordringen for enhver +som vil gjenvinne retten til å dyrke vår kultur er å finne en måte å få +denne sunne fornuften til å åpne sine øyne. +

+Så langt sover sunn fornuft. Det er intet opprør. Sunn fornuft ser ennå +ikke hva det er å gjøre opprør mot. Ekstremismen som nå domunerer denne +debatten resonerer med idéer som virker naturlige, og resonansen er +forsterket av våre moderne RCA-ene. De fører en frenetisk krig for å +bekjempe "piratvirksomhet" og knuser kreativitetskultur. De forsvarer idéen +om "kreativt eierskap", mens de endrer ekte skapere til moderne +leilendinger. De blir fornermet av idéen om at rettigheter skulle være +balanserte, selv om hver av hovedaktørene i denne innholdskrigen selv hadde +fordeler av et mer balansert ideal. Hykleriet rår. Men i en by som +Washington blir ikke hykleriet en gang lakt merke til. Mektige lobbyister, +kompliserte problemer og MTV-oppmerksomhetsspenn gir en "perfekt storm" for +fri kultur. +

+I august 2003 brøt en kamp ut i USA om en avgjørelse fra World Intellectual +Property Organiation om å avlyse et møte.[200] På forespørsel fra en lang rekke med interresenter hadde WIPO +bestemt å avholde et møte for å diskutere "åpne og sammarbeidende prosjekter +for å skape goder for felleskapet". Disse prosjektene som hadde lyktes i å +produsere goder for fellesskapet uten å basere seg eksklusivt på bruken av +proprietære immaterielle rettigheter. Eksempler inkluderer internettet og +verdensveven, begge som ble utviklet på grunnlag av protokoller i +allemannseie. Det hadde med en begynnende trend for å støtte åpne +akademiske tidsskrifter, og inkluderte Public Library of Science-prosjektet +som jeg beskriver i etterordet. Det inkluderte et prosjekt for a utvikle +enkeltnukleotidforskjeller (SNPs), som er antatt å få stor betydning i +biomedisinsk forskning. (Dette ideelle prosjektet besto av et konsortium av +Wellcome Trust og farmasøytiske og teknologiske selskaper, inkludert +Amersham Biosciences, AstraZeneca, Aventis, Bayer, Bristol-Myers Squibb, +Hoffmann-La Roche, Glaxo-SmithKline, IBM, Motorola, Novartis, Pfizer, og +Searle.) Det inkluderte Globalt posisjonssystem (GPS) som Ronald Reagen +frigjorde tidlig på 1980-tallet. Og det inkluderte "åpen kildekode og fri +programvare". +

+Formålet med møtet var å vurdere denne rekken av prosjekter fra et felles +perspektiv: at ingen av disse prosjektene hadde som grunnlag immateriell +ekstremisme. I stedet, hos alle disse, ble immaterielle rettigheter +balansert med avtaler om å holde tilgang åpen, eller for å legge +begrensninger på hvordan proprietære krav kan bli brukt. +

+Dermed var, fra perspektivet i denne boken, denne konferansen +ideell.[201] Prosjektene innenfor temaet var +både kommersielle og ikkekommersielle verker. De involverte i hovedsak +vitenskapet, men fra mange perspektiver. Og WIPO var et ideelt sted for +denne diskusjonen, siden WIPO var den fremstående internasjonale aktør som +drev med immaterielle rettighetsspørsmål. +

+ +Faktisk fikk jeg en gang offentlig kjeft for å ikke anerkjenne dette faktum +om WIPO. I februar 2003 leverte jeg et hovedinnlegg på en forberedende +konferanse for World Summit on the Information Society (WSIS). På en +pressekonferanse før innlegget, ble jeg spurt hva jeg skulle snakke om. Jeg +svarte at jeg skulle snakke litt om viktigheten av balanse rundt +immaterielle verdier for utviklingen av informasjonssamfunnet. Ordstyreren +på arrangementet avbrøt meg da brått for å informere meg og journalistene +tilstede at ingen spørsmål rundt immaterielle verdier ville bli diskutert av +WSIS, da slike spørsmål kun skulle diskuteres i WIPO. I innlegget jeg hadde +forberedt var temaet om immaterielle verdier en forholdvis liten del av det +hele. Men etter denne forbløffende uttalelsen, gjorde jeg immaterielle +verdier til hovedfokus for mitt innlegg. Det var ikke mulig å snakke om et +"informasjonssamfunn" uten at en også snakket om andelen av informasjon og +kultur som ikke er vernet av opphavsretten. Mitt innlegg gjorde ikke min +overivrige moderator veldig glad. Og hun hadde uten tvil rett i at omfanget +til vern av immaterielle rettigheter normalt hørte inn under WIPO. Men +etter mitt syn, kunne det ikke bli for mye diskusjon om hvor mye +immaterielle rettigheter som trengs, siden etter mitt syn, hadde selve ideen +om en balanse rundt immaterielle rettigheter hadde gått tapt. +

+Så uansett om WSIS kan diskutere balanse i intellektuell eiendom eller ikke, +så hadde jeg trodd det var tatt for gitt at WIPO kunne og burde. Og dermed +møtet om "åpne og samarbeidende prosjekter for å skape fellesgoder" virker å +passe perfekt for WIPOs agenda. +

+Men det er ett prosjekt i listen som er svært kontroversielt, i hvert fall +blant lobbyister. Dette prosjektet er "åpen kildekode og fri +programvare". Microsoft spesielt er skeptisk til diskusjon om emnet. Fra +deres perspektiv, ville en konferanse for å diskutere åpen kildekode og fri +programvare være som en konferanse for å diskutere Apples operativsystem. +Både åpen kildekode og fri programvare konkurrerer med Microsofts +programvare. Og internasjonalt har mange myndigheter begynt å utforske krav +om at de skal bruke åpen kildekode eller fri programvare, i stedet for +"proprietær programvare," til sine egne interne behov. +

+Jeg mener ikke å gå inn i den debatten her. Det er viktig kun for å gjøre +det klart at skillet ikke er mellom kommersiell og ikke-kommersiell +programvare. Det er mange viktige selskaper som er fundamentalt avhengig av +fri programvare, der IBM er den mest fremtredende. IBM har i stadig større +grad skiftet sitt fokus til GNU/Linux-operativsystemet, det mest berømte +biten av "fri programvare"—og IBM er helt klart en kommernsiell +aktør. Dermed er det å støtte "fri programvare" ikke å motsette seg +kommersielle aktører. Det er i stedet å støtte en måte å drive +programvareutvikling som er forskjellig fra Microsofts.[202] +

+ +Mer viktig for våre formål, er at å støtte "åpen kildekode og fri +programvare" ikke er å motsette seg opphasvrett. "Åpen kildekode og fri +programvare" er ikke programvare uten opphavsrettslig vern. Istedet, på +samme måte som programvare fra Microsoft, insisterer opphavsrettsinnehaverne +av fri programvare ganske sterkt at vilkårene i deres programvarelisens blir +respektert av de som tar i bruk fri programvare. Vilkårene i den lisensen +er uten tvil forskjellig fra vilkårene i en proprietær programvarelisens. +For eksempel krever fri programvare lisensiert med den generelle offentlige +lisensen (GPL), at kildekoden for programvare gjøres tilgjengelig for alle +som endrer og redistribuerer programvaren. Men dette kravet er kun +effektivt hvis opphavsrett råder over programvare. Hvis opphavsretten ikke +råder over programvare, så kunne ikke fri programvare pålegge slike krav på +de som tar i bruk programvaren. Den er dermed like avhengig av +opphavsrettsloven som Microsoft. +

+Det er dermed forståelig at Microsoft, som utviklere av proprietær +programvare, gikk imot et slikt WIPO-møte, og like fullt forståelig at de +bruker sine lobbyister til å få USAs myndigheter til å gå imot møtet. Og +ganske riktig, det er akkurat dette som i følge rapporter hadde skjedd. I +følge Jonathan Krim i Washington Post, lyktes Microsofts lobbyister i å få +USAs myndigheter til å legge ned veto mot et slikt møte.[203] Og uten støtte fra USA ble møtet avlyst. +

+Jeg klandrer ikke Microsoft for å gjøre det de kan for å fremme sine egne +interesser i samsvar med loven. Og lobbyvirksomhet mot myndighetene er +åpenbart i samsvar med loven. Det er ikke noe overraskende her med deres +lobbyvirksomhet, og ikke veldig overraskende at den mektigste +programvareprodusenten i USA har lyktes med sin lobbyvirksomhet. +

+Det som var overraskende var USAs regjerings begrunnelse for å være imot +møtet. Igjen, siterert av krim, forklarte Lois Boland, direktør for +internasjonale forbindelser ved USAs patent og varemerkekontor, at +"programvare med åpen kildekode går imot til formålet til WIPO, som er å +fremme immatterielle rettigheter.". Hun skal i følge sitatet ha sagt, "Å +holde et møte som har som formål å fraskrive seg eller frafalle slike +rettigheter synes for oss å være i strid med formålene til WIPO." +

+Disse utsagnene er forbløffende på flere nivåer. +

+For det første er de ganske enkelt enkelt ikke riktige. Som jeg beskrev, er +det meste av åpen kildekode og fri programvare fundamentalt avhengig av den +immaterielle retten kalt "opphavsrett". Uten den vil begresningene definert +av disse lisensene ikke fungere. Dermed er det å si at de "går imot" +formålet om å fremme immaterielle rettigheter å avsløre en ekstraordinær +mangel på forståelse—den type feil som er tilgivelig hos en førsteårs +jusstudent, men pinlig fra en høyt plassert statstjenestemann som håndterer +utfordringer rundt immaterielle rettigheter. +

+For det andre, hvem har noen gang hevdet at WIPOs eksklusive mål var å +"fremme" immaterielle rettigheter maksimalt? Som jeg fikk kjeft om på den +forberedende konferansen til WSIS, skal WIPO vurdere ikke bare hvordan best +beskytte immaterielle rettigheter, men også hva som er den beste balansen +rundt immaterielle rettigheter. Som enhver økonom og advokat vet, er det +vanskelige spørsmålet i immaterielle rettighetsjuss å finne den balansen. +Men at det skulle være en grense, trodde jeg, var ubestridt. Man ønsker å +spørre Ms. boland om generelle medisiner (medisiner basert på medisiner med +patenter som er utløpt) i strid med WIPOs oppdrag? Svekker allemannseie +immaterielle rettigheter? Ville det vært bedre om internettets protokoller +hadde vært patentert? +

+For det tredje, selv om en tror at formålet med WIPO var å maksimere +immaterielle rettigheter, så innehas immaterielle rettigheter, i vår +tradisjon, av individer og selskaper. De får bestemme hva som skal gjøres +med disse rettighetene, igjen fordi det er de som eier rettigetene. Hvis de +ønsker å "frafalle" eller "frasi" seg sine rettigheter, så er det helt etter +boka i vår tradisjon. Når Bill Gates gir bort mer enn $20 milliarder til +gode formål, så er ikke det uforenelig med målene til eiendomssystemet. Det +er heller tvert i mot, akkurat hva eiendomssysstemet er ment å oppnå, at +individer har retten til å bestemme hva de vil gjøre med sin eiendom. + +

+ +Når Ms. Boland sier at det er noe galt med et møte "som har som sitt formål +å fraskrive eller frafalle slike rettigheter", så sier hun at WIPO har en +interesse i å påvirke valgene til enkeltpersoner som eier immaterielle +rettigheter. At på en eller annen WIPOs oppdrag bør være å stoppe individer +fra å "frakrive" eller "frafalle" seg sine immaterielle rettigheter. At +interessen til WIPO ikke bare er maksimale immaterielle rettigheter, men +også at de skal utøves på den mest ekstreme og restriktive mulig måten. +

+Det er en historie om akkurat et slikt eierskapssystem som er velkjent i den +anglo-amerikansk tradisjon. Det kalles "føydalisme". Under føydalismen var +eiendommer ikke bare kontrollert av et relativt lite antall individer og +aktører. Men det føydale systemet hadde en sterk interesse i å sikre at +landeier i systemet ikke svekke føydalismen ved å frigjøre folkene og +eiendomene som de kontrollerte til det frie markedet. Føydalismen var +avhengig av maksimal kontroll og konsentrasjon. Det sloss mot enhver frihet +som kunne forstyrre denne kontrollen. +

+Som Peter Drahos og John Braithwaite beskriver, dette er nøyaktig det valget +vi nå gjør om immaterielle rettigheter.[204] +Vi kommer til å få et informasjonssamfunn. Så mye er sikkert. Vårt eneste +valg nå er hvorvidt dette informasjonssamfunnet skal være fritt eller +føydalt. Trenden er mot det føydale. +

+Da denne bataljen brøt ut, blogget jeg om dette. En heftig debatt brøt ut i +kommentarfeltet. Ms. Boland hadde en rekke støttespillere som forsøkte å +vise hvorfor hennes kommentarer ga mening. Men det var spesielt en +kommentar som gjorde meg trist. En anonym kommentator skrev, +

+ +George, du misforstår Lessig: Han snakker bare om verden slik den burde være +("målet til WIPO, og målet til enhver regjering, bør være å fremme den +riktige balansen for immaterielle rettigheter, ikke bare å fremme +immaterielle rettigheter"), ikke som den er. Hvis vi snakket om verden slik +den er, så har naturligvis Boland ikke sagt noe galt. Men i verden slik +Lessig vil at den skal være, er det åpenbart at hun har sagt noe galt. En +må alltid være oppmerksom på forskjellen mellom Lessigs og vår verden. +

+Jeg gikk glipp av ironien først gangen jeg leste den. Jeg lese den raskt og +trodde forfatteren støttet idéen om at det våre myndigheter burde gjøre var +å søke balanse. (Min kritikk av Ms Boland, selvfølgelig, var ikke om +hvorvidt hun søkte balanse eller ikke; min kritikk var at hennes kommentarer +avslørte en feil kun en førsteårs jussstudent burde kunne gjøre. Jeg har +noen illusjon om ekstremismen hos våre myndigheter, uansett om de er +republikanere eller demokrater. Min eneste tilsynelatende illusjon er +hvorvidt våre myndigheter bør snakke sant eller ikke.) +

+Det var dermot åpenbart at den som postet meldingen ikke støttet idéen. I +stedet latterliggjorde forfatteren selve idéen om at i den virkelig verden +skulle "målet" til myndighetene være "å fremme den riktige balanse" for +immaterielle rettigheter. Det var åpenbart tåpelig for ham. Og det +avslørte åpenbart, trodde han, min egen tåpelige utopisme. "Typisk for en +akademiker", kunne forfatteren like gjerne ha fortsatt. +

+Jeg forstår kritikken av akademisk utopisme. Jeg mener også at utopisme er +tåpelig, og jeg vil være blant de første til å gjøre narr av de aburde +urealisistiske idealer til akademikere gjennom historien (og ikke bare i +vårt eget lands historie). +

+Men når det har blitt dumt å anta at rollen til våre myndigheter bør være å +"oppnå balanse", da kan du regne meg blant de dumme, for det betyr at dette +faktisk har blitt ganske seriøst. Hvis det bør være åpenbart for alle at +myndighetene ikke søker å oppnå balanse, at myndighetene ganske enkelt et +verktøy for de mektigste lobbyistene, at ideen om å forvente bedre av +myndighetene er absurd, at ideen om å kreve at myndighetene snakker sant og +ikke lyver bare er naiv, hva har da vi, det mektigste demokratiet i verden, +blitt? +

+ +Det kan være galskap å forvente at en mektig myndigshetsperson skal si +sannheten. Det kan være galskap å tro at myndighetenes politikk skal gjøre +mer enn å tjene de mektigste interesser. Det kan være galskap å argumentere +for å bevare en tradisjon som har vært en del av vår tradisjon for +mesteparten av vår historie—fri kultur. +

+Hvis dette er galskap, så la det være mer gærninger. Snart. Det finnes +øyeblikk av håp i denne kampen. Og øyeblikk som overrasker. Da FCC vurderte +mindre strenge eierskapregler, som ville ytterligere konsentrere +mediaeierskap, dannet det seg en en ekstraordinær koalisjon på tvers av +partiene for å bekjempe endringen. For kanskje første gang i historien +organiserte interesser så forskjellige som NRA, ACLU, moveon.org, William +Safire, Ted Turner og Codepink Women for Piece seg for å protestere på denne +endringen i FCC-reglene. Så mange som 700 000 brev ble sendt til FCC med +krav om flere høringer og et annet resultat. +

+Disse protestene stoppet ikke FCC, men like etter stemte en bred koalisjon i +senatet for å reversere avgjørelsen i FCC. De fientlige høringene som ledet +til avstemmingen avslørte hvor mektig denne bevegelsen hadde blitt. Det var +ingen betydnigsfull støtte for FCCs avgjørelse, mens det var bred og +vedvarende støtte for å bekjempe ytterligere konsentrasjon i media. +

+Men selv denne bevegelsen går glipp av en viktig brikke i puslespillet. Å +være stor er ikke ille i seg selv. Frihet er ikke truet bare på grunn av at +noen blir veldig rik, eller på grunn av at det bare er en håndfull store +aktører. Den dårlige kvaliteten til Big Macs eller Quartar Punders betyr +ikke at du ikke kan få en god hamburger andre steder. +

+Faren med mediakonsentrasjon kommer ikke fra selve konsentrasjonen, men +kommer fra føydalismen som denne konsentrasjonen fører til når den kobles +til endringer i opphavsretten. Det er ikke kun at det er noen mektige +selskaper som styrer en stadig voksende andel av mediene. Det er at denne +konsentrasjonen kan påkalle en like oppsvulmet rekke +rettigheter—eiendomsrettigheter i en historisk ekstrem form—som +gjør størrelsen ille. +

+Det er derfor betydningsfullt at så mange vil kjempe for å kreve konkurranse +og økt mangfold. Likevel, hvis kampanjen blir forstått til å kun gjelde +størrelse, så er ikke det veldig overraskende. Vi amerikanere har en lang +historie med å slåss mot "stort", klokt eller ikke. At vi kan være motivert +til å slåss mot "store" igjen ikke noe nytt. +

+Det ville vært noe nytt, og noe veldig viktig, hvis like mange kan være med +på en kampanje for å bekjempe økende ekstremisme bygget inn i idéen om +"intellektuell eiendom". Ikke fordi balanse er fremmed for vår +tradisjon. Jeg agumenterer for at balanse er vår tradisjon. Men fordi evnen +til å tenke kritisk på omfanget av alt som kalles "eiendom" ikke er lenger +er godt trent i denne tradisjonen. +

+Hvis vi var Akilles, så ville dette være vår hæl. Dette ville være stedet +for våre tragedie. +

+Mens jeg skriver disse avsluttende ordene, er nyhetene fylt med historier om +at RIAA saksøker nesten tre hundre individer.[205] Eminem har nettopp blitt saksøkt for å ha "samplet" noen andres +musikk.[206] Historien om hvordan Bob Dylan +har "stjålet" fra en japansk forfatter har nettopp gått verden +over.[207] En på innsiden i +Hollywood—som insisterer på at han må forbli anonym—rapporterer +"en utrolig samtale med disse studiofolkene. De har fantastisk [gammelt] +innhold som de ville elske å bruke, men det kan de ikke på grunn av at de +først må klarere rettighetene. De har hauger med ungdommer som kunne gjøre +fantastiske ting med innholdet, men det vil først kreve hauger med advokater +for å klarere det først". Kongressrepresentanter snakker om å gi datavirus +politimyndighet for å ta ned datamaskiner som antas å bryte loven. +Universiteter truer med å utvise ungdommer som bruker en datamaskin for å +dele innhold. +

+ +I mens på andre siden av atlanteren har BBC nettopp annonsert at de vil +bygge opp et "kreativt arkiv" som britiske borgere kan laste ned BBC-innhold +fra, og rippe, mikse og brenne det ut.[208] +Og i Brasil har kulturministeren, Gilberto Gil, i seg selv en folkehelt i +brasiliansk musikk, slått seg sammen med Creative Commons for å gi ut +innhold og frie lisenser i dette latinamerikanske landet.[209] Jeg har fortalt en mørk historie. Sannheten mer +mer blandet. En teknologi har gitt oss mer frihet. Sakte begynner noen å +forstå at denne friheten trenger ikke å bety anarki. Vi kan få med oss fri +kultur inn i det tjueførste århundre, uten at artister taper og uten at +potensialet for digital teknologi blir knust. Det vil kreve omtanke, og +viktigere, det vil kreve at noen omforme RCAene av i dag til Causbyere. +

+ +Sunn fornuft må gjøre opprør. Den må handle for å frigjøre kulturen. Og +snart, hvis dette potensialet skal noen gang bli realisert. + + + +



[195] + +Commission on Intellectual Property Rights, "Final Report: Integrating +Intellectual Property Rights and Development Policy" (London, 2002), +tilgjengelig fra link +#55. I følge en pressemelding fra verdens helseorganisasjon sendt ut +9. juli 2002, mottar kun 320 000 av de 6 millioner som trenger medisiner i +utviklingsland dem de trenger—og halvparten av dem er i Brasil. +

[196] + +Se Peter Drahos og John Braithwaite, Information Feudalism: Who Owns the +Knowledge Economy? (New York: The New Press, 2003), 37. +

[197] + +International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), Patent Protection and +Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan Africa, a Report Prepared +for the World Intellectual Property Organization (Washington, D.C., 2000), +14, available at link +#56. For a firsthand account of the struggle over South Africa, see +Hearing Before the Subcommittee on Criminal Justice, Drug Policy, and Human +Resources, House Committee on Government Reform, H. Rep., 1st sess., +Ser. No. 106-126 (22 July 1999), 150–57 (statement of James Love). +

[198] + + +International Intellectual Property Institute (IIPI), Patent Protection and +Access to HIV/AIDS Pharmaceuticals in Sub-Saharan Africa, en rapport +forberedt for the World Intellectual Property Organization (Washington, +D.C., 2000), 15.

[199] + + + +See Sabin Russell, "New Crusade to Lower AIDS Drug Costs: Africa's Needs at +Odds with Firms' Profit Motive," San Francisco Chronicle, 24 May 1999, A1, +available at link #57 +("compulsory licenses and gray markets pose a threat to the entire system of +intellectual property protection"); Robert Weissman, "AIDS and Developing +Countries: Democratizing Access to Essential Medicines," Foreign Policy in +Focus 4:23 (August 1999), available at link #58 (describing +U.S. policy); John A. Harrelson, "TRIPS, Pharmaceutical Patents, and the +HIV/AIDS Crisis: Finding the Proper Balance Between Intellectual Property +Rights and Compassion, a Synopsis," Widener Law Symposium Journal (Spring +2001): 175. + +

[200] + +Jonathan Krim, "The Quiet War over Open-Source," Washington Post, august +2003, E1, tilgjengelig fra link +#59; William New, "Global Group's Shift on `Open Source' Meeting +Spurs Stir," National Journal's Technology Daily, 19. august 2003, +tilgjengelig fra link +#60; William New, "U.S. Official Opposes `Open Source' Talks at +WIPO," National Journal's Technology Daily, 19. august 2003, tilgjengelig +fra link #61. +

[201] + +Jeg bør nevne at jeg var en av folkene som ba WIPO om dette møtet. +

[202] + + +Microsofts posisjon om åpen kildekode og fri programvare er mer +sofistikert. De har flere ganger forklart at de har ikke noe problem med +programvare som er "åpen kildekode" eller programvare som er allemannseie. +Microsofts prinsipielle motstand er mot "fri programvare" lisensiert med en +"copyleft"-lisens, som betyr at lisensen krever at de som lisensierer skal +adoptere same vilkår for ethvert avledet verk. Se Bradford L. Smith, "The +Future of Software: Enabling the Marketplace to Decide," Government Policy +Toward Open Source Software (Washington, D.C.: AEI-Brookings Joint Center +for Regulatory Studies, American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy +Research, 2002), 69, tilgjengelig fra link #62. Se også Craig Mundie, +Microsoft senior vice president, The Commercial Software Model, diskusjon +ved New York University Stern School of Business (3. mai 2001), tilgjengelig +fra link #63. +

[203] + + +Krim, "The Quiet War over Open-Source," tilgjengelig fra link #64. +

[204] + +Se Drahos og Braithwaite, Information Feudalism, 210–20. +

[205] + + +John Borland, "RIAA Sues 261 File Swappers," CNET News.com, september 2003, +tilgjengelig fra link +#65; Paul R. La Monica, "Music Industry Sues Swappers," CNN/Money, 8 +september 2003, tilgjengelig fra link #66; Soni Sangha og Phyllis +Furman sammen med Robert Gearty, "Sued for a Song, N.Y.C. 12-Yr-Old Among +261 Cited as Sharers," New York Daily News, 9. september 2003, 3; Frank +Ahrens, "RIAA's Lawsuits Meet Surprised Targets; Single Mother in Calif., +12-Year-Old Girl in N.Y. Among Defendants," Washington Post, 10. september +2003, E1; Katie Dean, "Schoolgirl Settles with RIAA," Wired News, +10. september 2003, tilgjengelig fra link #67. +

[206] + + +Jon Wiederhorn, "Eminem Gets Sued . . . by a Little Old Lady," mtv.com, +17. september 2003, tilgjengelig fra link #68. +

[207] + + + +Kenji Hall, Associated Press, "Japanese Book May Be Inspiration for Dylan +Songs," Kansascity.com, 9. juli 2003, tilgjengelig fra link #69. + +

[208] + +"BBC Plans to Open Up Its Archive to the Public," pressemelding fra BBC, +24. august 2003, tilgjengelig fra link #70. +

[209] + + +"Creative Commons and Brazil," Creative Commons Weblog, 6. august 2003, +tilgjengelig fra link +#71. +

Kapittel 7. Etterord

+ + + +I hvert fall noen av de som har lest helt hit vil være enig med meg om at +noe må gjøres for å endre retningen vi holder. Balansen i denne boken +kartlegger hva som kan gjøres. +

+I divide this map into two parts: that which anyone can do now, and that +which requires the help of lawmakers. If there is one lesson that we can +draw from the history of remaking common sense, it is that it requires +remaking how many people think about the very same issue. +

+That means this movement must begin in the streets. It must recruit a +significant number of parents, teachers, librarians, creators, authors, +musicians, filmmakers, scientists—all to tell this story in their own +words, and to tell their neighbors why this battle is so important. +

+Once this movement has its effect in the streets, it has some hope of having +an effect in Washington. We are still a democracy. What people think +matters. Not as much as it should, at least when an RCA stands opposed, but +still, it matters. And thus, in the second part below, I sketch changes that +Congress could make to better secure a free culture. +

Oss, nå

+Common sense is with the copyright warriors because the debate so far has +been framed at the extremes—as a grand either/or: either property or +anarchy, either total control or artists won't be paid. If that really is +the choice, then the warriors should win. +

+The mistake here is the error of the excluded middle. There are extremes in +this debate, but the extremes are not all that there is. There are those who +believe in maximal copyright—"All Rights Reserved"— and those +who reject copyright—"No Rights Reserved." The "All Rights Reserved" +sorts believe that you should ask permission before you "use" a copyrighted +work in any way. The "No Rights Reserved" sorts believe you should be able +to do with content as you wish, regardless of whether you have permission or +not. +

+ +When the Internet was first born, its initial architecture effectively +tilted in the "no rights reserved" direction. Content could be copied +perfectly and cheaply; rights could not easily be controlled. Thus, +regardless of anyone's desire, the effective regime of copyright under the +original design of the Internet was "no rights reserved." Content was +"taken" regardless of the rights. Any rights were effectively unprotected. +

+This initial character produced a reaction (opposite, but not quite equal) +by copyright owners. That reaction has been the topic of this book. Through +legislation, litigation, and changes to the network's design, copyright +holders have been able to change the essential character of the environment +of the original Internet. If the original architecture made the effective +default "no rights reserved," the future architecture will make the +effective default "all rights reserved." The architecture and law that +surround the Internet's design will increasingly produce an environment +where all use of content requires permission. The "cut and paste" world +that defines the Internet today will become a "get permission to cut and +paste" world that is a creator's nightmare. +

+What's needed is a way to say something in the middle—neither "all +rights reserved" nor "no rights reserved" but "some rights reserved"— +and thus a way to respect copyrights but enable creators to free content as +they see fit. In other words, we need a way to restore a set of freedoms +that we could just take for granted before. +

Gjenoppbygging av friheter som tidligere var antatt: Eksempler

+If you step back from the battle I've been describing here, you will +recognize this problem from other contexts. Think about privacy. Before the +Internet, most of us didn't have to worry much about data about our lives +that we broadcast to the world. If you walked into a bookstore and browsed +through some of the works of Karl Marx, you didn't need to worry about +explaining your browsing habits to your neighbors or boss. The "privacy" of +your browsing habits was assured. +

+Hva gjorde at det var sikret? +

+Well, if we think in terms of the modalities I described in chapter 10, your +privacy was assured because of an inefficient architecture for gathering +data and hence a market constraint (cost) on anyone who wanted to gather +that data. If you were a suspected spy for North Korea, working for the CIA, +no doubt your privacy would not be assured. But that's because the CIA +would (we hope) find it valuable enough to spend the thousands required to +track you. But for most of us (again, we can hope), spying doesn't pay. The +highly inefficient architecture of real space means we all enjoy a fairly +robust amount of privacy. That privacy is guaranteed to us by friction. Not +by law (there is no law protecting "privacy" in public places), and in many +places, not by norms (snooping and gossip are just fun), but instead, by the +costs that friction imposes on anyone who would want to spy. +

+Enter the Internet, where the cost of tracking browsing in particular has +become quite tiny. If you're a customer at Amazon, then as you browse the +pages, Amazon collects the data about what you've looked at. You know this +because at the side of the page, there's a list of "recently viewed" +pages. Now, because of the architecture of the Net and the function of +cookies on the Net, it is easier to collect the data than not. The friction +has disappeared, and hence any "privacy" protected by the friction +disappears, too. +

+Amazon, of course, is not the problem. But we might begin to worry about +libraries. If you're one of those crazy lefties who thinks that people +should have the "right" to browse in a library without the government +knowing which books you look at (I'm one of those lefties, too), then this +change in the technology of monitoring might concern you. If it becomes +simple to gather and sort who does what in electronic spaces, then the +friction-induced privacy of yesterday disappears. +

+ +It is this reality that explains the push of many to define "privacy" on the +Internet. It is the recognition that technology can remove what friction +before gave us that leads many to push for laws to do what friction +did.[210] And whether you're in favor of +those laws or not, it is the pattern that is important here. We must take +affirmative steps to secure a kind of freedom that was passively provided +before. A change in technology now forces those who believe in privacy to +affirmatively act where, before, privacy was given by default. +

+A similar story could be told about the birth of the free software +movement. When computers with software were first made available +commercially, the software—both the source code and the +binaries— was free. You couldn't run a program written for a Data +General machine on an IBM machine, so Data General and IBM didn't care much +about controlling their software. +

+Dette var verden Richard Stallman ble født inn i, og mens han var forsker +ved MIT, lærte han til å elske samfunnet som utviklet seg når en var fri til +å utforske og fikle med programvaren som kjørte på datamaskiner. Av den +smarte sorten selv, og en talentfull programmerer, begynte Stallman å basere +seg frihet til å legge til eller endre på andre personers arbeid. +

+In an academic setting, at least, that's not a terribly radical idea. In a +math department, anyone would be free to tinker with a proof that someone +offered. If you thought you had a better way to prove a theorem, you could +take what someone else did and change it. In a classics department, if you +believed a colleague's translation of a recently discovered text was flawed, +you were free to improve it. Thus, to Stallman, it seemed obvious that you +should be free to tinker with and improve the code that ran a machine. This, +too, was knowledge. Why shouldn't it be open for criticism like anything +else? +

+No one answered that question. Instead, the architecture of revenue for +computing changed. As it became possible to import programs from one system +to another, it became economically attractive (at least in the view of some) +to hide the code of your program. So, too, as companies started selling +peripherals for mainframe systems. If I could just take your printer driver +and copy it, then that would make it easier for me to sell a printer to the +market than it was for you. +

+ +Thus, the practice of proprietary code began to spread, and by the early +1980s, Stallman found himself surrounded by proprietary code. The world of +free software had been erased by a change in the economics of computing. And +as he believed, if he did nothing about it, then the freedom to change and +share software would be fundamentally weakened. +

+Therefore, in 1984, Stallman began a project to build a free operating +system, so that at least a strain of free software would survive. That was +the birth of the GNU project, into which Linus Torvalds's "Linux" kernel was +added to produce the GNU/Linux operating system. +

+Stallman's technique was to use copyright law to build a world of software +that must be kept free. Software licensed under the Free Software +Foundation's GPL cannot be modified and distributed unless the source code +for that software is made available as well. Thus, anyone building upon +GPL'd software would have to make their buildings free as well. This would +assure, Stallman believed, that an ecology of code would develop that +remained free for others to build upon. His fundamental goal was freedom; +innovative creative code was a byproduct. +

+Stallman was thus doing for software what privacy advocates now do for +privacy. He was seeking a way to rebuild a kind of freedom that was taken +for granted before. Through the affirmative use of licenses that bind +copyrighted code, Stallman was affirmatively reclaiming a space where free +software would survive. He was actively protecting what before had been +passively guaranteed. +

+Finally, consider a very recent example that more directly resonates with +the story of this book. This is the shift in the way academic and scientific +journals are produced. +

+ +As digital technologies develop, it is becoming obvious to many that +printing thousands of copies of journals every month and sending them to +libraries is perhaps not the most efficient way to distribute +knowledge. Instead, journals are increasingly becoming electronic, and +libraries and their users are given access to these electronic journals +through password-protected sites. Something similar to this has been +happening in law for almost thirty years: Lexis and Westlaw have had +electronic versions of case reports available to subscribers to their +service. Although a Supreme Court opinion is not copyrighted, and anyone is +free to go to a library and read it, Lexis and Westlaw are also free to +charge users for the privilege of gaining access to that Supreme Court +opinion through their respective services. +

+There's nothing wrong in general with this, and indeed, the ability to +charge for access to even public domain materials is a good incentive for +people to develop new and innovative ways to spread knowledge. The law has +agreed, which is why Lexis and Westlaw have been allowed to flourish. And if +there's nothing wrong with selling the public domain, then there could be +nothing wrong, in principle, with selling access to material that is not in +the public domain. +

+But what if the only way to get access to social and scientific data was +through proprietary services? What if no one had the ability to browse this +data except by paying for a subscription? +

+As many are beginning to notice, this is increasingly the reality with +scientific journals. When these journals were distributed in paper form, +libraries could make the journals available to anyone who had access to the +library. Thus, patients with cancer could become cancer experts because the +library gave them access. Or patients trying to understand the risks of a +certain treatment could research those risks by reading all available +articles about that treatment. This freedom was therefore a function of the +institution of libraries (norms) and the technology of paper journals +(architecture)—namely, that it was very hard to control access to a +paper journal. +

+As journals become electronic, however, the publishers are demanding that +libraries not give the general public access to the journals. This means +that the freedoms provided by print journals in public libraries begin to +disappear. Thus, as with privacy and with software, a changing technology +and market shrink a freedom taken for granted before. +

+This shrinking freedom has led many to take affirmative steps to restore the +freedom that has been lost. The Public Library of Science (PLoS), for +example, is a nonprofit corporation dedicated to making scientific research +available to anyone with a Web connection. Authors of scientific work submit +that work to the Public Library of Science. That work is then subject to +peer review. If accepted, the work is then deposited in a public, electronic +archive and made permanently available for free. PLoS also sells a print +version of its work, but the copyright for the print journal does not +inhibit the right of anyone to redistribute the work for free. +

+This is one of many such efforts to restore a freedom taken for granted +before, but now threatened by changing technology and markets. There's no +doubt that this alternative competes with the traditional publishers and +their efforts to make money from the exclusive distribution of content. But +competition in our tradition is presumptively a good—especially when +it helps spread knowledge and science. +

Gjenoppbyggeing av fri kultur: En idé

+The same strategy could be applied to culture, as a response to the +increasing control effected through law and technology. +

+Enter the Creative Commons. The Creative Commons is a nonprofit corporation +established in Massachusetts, but with its home at Stanford University. Its +aim is to build a layer of reasonable copyright on top of the extremes that +now reign. It does this by making it easy for people to build upon other +people's work, by making it simple for creators to express the freedom for +others to take and build upon their work. Simple tags, tied to +human-readable descriptions, tied to bulletproof licenses, make this +possible. +

+ +Simple—which means without a middleman, or without a lawyer. By +developing a free set of licenses that people can attach to their content, +Creative Commons aims to mark a range of content that can easily, and +reliably, be built upon. These tags are then linked to machine-readable +versions of the license that enable computers automatically to identify +content that can easily be shared. These three expressions together—a +legal license, a human-readable description, and machine-readable +tags—constitute a Creative Commons license. A Creative Commons license +constitutes a grant of freedom to anyone who accesses the license, and more +importantly, an expression of the ideal that the person associated with the +license believes in something different than the "All" or "No" +extremes. Content is marked with the CC mark, which does not mean that +copyright is waived, but that certain freedoms are given. +

+These freedoms are beyond the freedoms promised by fair use. Their precise +contours depend upon the choices the creator makes. The creator can choose a +license that permits any use, so long as attribution is given. She can +choose a license that permits only noncommercial use. She can choose a +license that permits any use so long as the same freedoms are given to other +uses ("share and share alike"). Or any use so long as no derivative use is +made. Or any use at all within developing nations. Or any sampling use, so +long as full copies are not made. Or lastly, any educational use. +

+These choices thus establish a range of freedoms beyond the default of +copyright law. They also enable freedoms that go beyond traditional fair +use. And most importantly, they express these freedoms in a way that +subsequent users can use and rely upon without the need to hire a +lawyer. Creative Commons thus aims to build a layer of content, governed by +a layer of reasonable copyright law, that others can build upon. Voluntary +choice of individuals and creators will make this content available. And +that content will in turn enable us to rebuild a public domain. +

+This is just one project among many within the Creative Commons. And of +course, Creative Commons is not the only organization pursuing such +freedoms. But the point that distinguishes the Creative Commons from many is +that we are not interested only in talking about a public domain or in +getting legislators to help build a public domain. Our aim is to build a +movement of consumers and producers of content ("content conducers," as +attorney Mia Garlick calls them) who help build the public domain and, by +their work, demonstrate the importance of the public domain to other +creativity. +

+The aim is not to fight the "All Rights Reserved" sorts. The aim is to +complement them. The problems that the law creates for us as a culture are +produced by insane and unintended consequences of laws written centuries +ago, applied to a technology that only Jefferson could have imagined. The +rules may well have made sense against a background of technologies from +centuries ago, but they do not make sense against the background of digital +technologies. New rules—with different freedoms, expressed in ways so +that humans without lawyers can use them—are needed. Creative Commons +gives people a way effectively to begin to build those rules. +

+Why would creators participate in giving up total control? Some participate +to better spread their content. Cory Doctorow, for example, is a science +fiction author. His first novel, Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom, was +released on-line and for free, under a Creative Commons license, on the same +day that it went on sale in bookstores. +

+Why would a publisher ever agree to this? I suspect his publisher reasoned +like this: There are two groups of people out there: (1) those who will buy +Cory's book whether or not it's on the Internet, and (2) those who may never +hear of Cory's book, if it isn't made available for free on the +Internet. Some part of (1) will download Cory's book instead of buying +it. Call them bad-(1)s. Some part of (2) will download Cory's book, like +it, and then decide to buy it. Call them (2)-goods. If there are more +(2)-goods than bad-(1)s, the strategy of releasing Cory's book free on-line +will probably increase sales of Cory's book. +

+Indeed, the experience of his publisher clearly supports that conclusion. +The book's first printing was exhausted months before the publisher had +expected. This first novel of a science fiction author was a total success. +

+ +The idea that free content might increase the value of nonfree content was +confirmed by the experience of another author. Peter Wayner, who wrote a +book about the free software movement titled Free for All, made an +electronic version of his book free on-line under a Creative Commons license +after the book went out of print. He then monitored used book store prices +for the book. As predicted, as the number of downloads increased, the used +book price for his book increased, as well. +

+These are examples of using the Commons to better spread proprietary +content. I believe that is a wonderful and common use of the Commons. There +are others who use Creative Commons licenses for other reasons. Many who use +the "sampling license" do so because anything else would be +hypocritical. The sampling license says that others are free, for commercial +or noncommercial purposes, to sample content from the licensed work; they +are just not free to make full copies of the licensed work available to +others. This is consistent with their own art—they, too, sample from +others. Because the legal costs of sampling are so high (Walter Leaphart, +manager of the rap group Public Enemy, which was born sampling the music of +others, has stated that he does not "allow" Public Enemy to sample anymore, +because the legal costs are so high[211]), +these artists release into the creative environment content that others can +build upon, so that their form of creativity might grow. +

+Finally, there are many who mark their content with a Creative Commons +license just because they want to express to others the importance of +balance in this debate. If you just go along with the system as it is, you +are effectively saying you believe in the "All Rights Reserved" model. Good +for you, but many do not. Many believe that however appropriate that rule is +for Hollywood and freaks, it is not an appropriate description of how most +creators view the rights associated with their content. The Creative Commons +license expresses this notion of "Some Rights Reserved," and gives many the +chance to say it to others. +

+ +In the first six months of the Creative Commons experiment, over 1 million +objects were licensed with these free-culture licenses. The next step is +partnerships with middleware content providers to help them build into their +technologies simple ways for users to mark their content with Creative +Commons freedoms. Then the next step is to watch and celebrate creators who +build content based upon content set free. +

+These are first steps to rebuilding a public domain. They are not mere +arguments; they are action. Building a public domain is the first step to +showing people how important that domain is to creativity and +innovation. Creative Commons relies upon voluntary steps to achieve this +rebuilding. They will lead to a world in which more than voluntary steps are +possible. +

+Creative Commons is just one example of voluntary efforts by individuals and +creators to change the mix of rights that now govern the creative field. The +project does not compete with copyright; it complements it. Its aim is not +to defeat the rights of authors, but to make it easier for authors and +creators to exercise their rights more flexibly and cheaply. That +difference, we believe, will enable creativity to spread more easily. +

Dem, snart

+We will not reclaim a free culture by individual action alone. It will also +take important reforms of laws. We have a long way to go before the +politicians will listen to these ideas and implement these reforms. But +that also means that we have time to build awareness around the changes that +we need. +

+In this chapter, I outline five kinds of changes: four that are general, and +one that's specific to the most heated battle of the day, music. Each is a +step, not an end. But any of these steps would carry us a long way to our +end. +

1. Flere formaliteter

+If you buy a house, you have to record the sale in a deed. If you buy land +upon which to build a house, you have to record the purchase in a deed. If +you buy a car, you get a bill of sale and register the car. If you buy an +airplane ticket, it has your name on it. +

+ + +These are all formalities associated with property. They are requirements +that we all must bear if we want our property to be protected. +

+In contrast, under current copyright law, you automatically get a copyright, +regardless of whether you comply with any formality. You don't have to +register. You don't even have to mark your content. The default is control, +and "formalities" are banished. +

+Why? +

+As I suggested in chapter 10, the motivation to abolish formalities was a +good one. In the world before digital technologies, formalities imposed a +burden on copyright holders without much benefit. Thus, it was progress when +the law relaxed the formal requirements that a copyright owner must bear to +protect and secure his work. Those formalities were getting in the way. +

+But the Internet changes all this. Formalities today need not be a +burden. Rather, the world without formalities is the world that burdens +creativity. Today, there is no simple way to know who owns what, or with +whom one must deal in order to use or build upon the creative work of +others. There are no records, there is no system to trace— there is no +simple way to know how to get permission. Yet given the massive increase in +the scope of copyright's rule, getting permission is a necessary step for +any work that builds upon our past. And thus, the lack of formalities forces +many into silence where they otherwise could speak. +

+The law should therefore change this requirement[212]—but it should not change it by going back to the old, broken +system. We should require formalities, but we should establish a system that +will create the incentives to minimize the burden of these formalities. +

+The important formalities are three: marking copyrighted work, registering +copyrights, and renewing the claim to copyright. Traditionally, the first of +these three was something the copyright owner did; the second two were +something the government did. But a revised system of formalities would +banish the government from the process, except for the sole purpose of +approving standards developed by others. +

Registrering og fornying

+Under the old system, a copyright owner had to file a registration with the +Copyright Office to register or renew a copyright. When filing that +registration, the copyright owner paid a fee. As with most government +agencies, the Copyright Office had little incentive to minimize the burden +of registration; it also had little incentive to minimize the fee. And as +the Copyright Office is not a main target of government policymaking, the +office has historically been terribly underfunded. Thus, when people who +know something about the process hear this idea about formalities, their +first reaction is panic—nothing could be worse than forcing people to +deal with the mess that is the Copyright Office. +

+Yet it is always astonishing to me that we, who come from a tradition of +extraordinary innovation in governmental design, can no longer think +innovatively about how governmental functions can be designed. Just because +there is a public purpose to a government role, it doesn't follow that the +government must actually administer the role. Instead, we should be creating +incentives for private parties to serve the public, subject to standards +that the government sets. +

+In the context of registration, one obvious model is the Internet. There +are at least 32 million Web sites registered around the world. Domain name +owners for these Web sites have to pay a fee to keep their registration +alive. In the main top-level domains (.com, .org, .net), there is a central +registry. The actual registrations are, however, performed by many competing +registrars. That competition drives the cost of registering down, and more +importantly, it drives the ease with which registration occurs up. +

+ +We should adopt a similar model for the registration and renewal of +copyrights. The Copyright Office may well serve as the central registry, but +it should not be in the registrar business. Instead, it should establish a +database, and a set of standards for registrars. It should approve +registrars that meet its standards. Those registrars would then compete with +one another to deliver the cheapest and simplest systems for registering and +renewing copyrights. That competition would substantially lower the burden +of this formality—while producing a database of registrations that +would facilitate the licensing of content. +

Merking

+It used to be that the failure to include a copyright notice on a creative +work meant that the copyright was forfeited. That was a harsh punishment for +failing to comply with a regulatory rule—akin to imposing the death +penalty for a parking ticket in the world of creative rights. Here again, +there is no reason that a marking requirement needs to be enforced in this +way. And more importantly, there is no reason a marking requirement needs to +be enforced uniformly across all media. +

+The aim of marking is to signal to the public that this work is copyrighted +and that the author wants to enforce his rights. The mark also makes it easy +to locate a copyright owner to secure permission to use the work. +

+One of the problems the copyright system confronted early on was that +different copyrighted works had to be differently marked. It wasn't clear +how or where a statue was to be marked, or a record, or a film. A new +marking requirement could solve these problems by recognizing the +differences in media, and by allowing the system of marking to evolve as +technologies enable it to. The system could enable a special signal from the +failure to mark—not the loss of the copyright, but the loss of the +right to punish someone for failing to get permission first. +

+ +Let's start with the last point. If a copyright owner allows his work to be +published without a copyright notice, the consequence of that failure need +not be that the copyright is lost. The consequence could instead be that +anyone has the right to use this work, until the copyright owner complains +and demonstrates that it is his work and he doesn't give +permission.[213] The meaning of an unmarked +work would therefore be "use unless someone complains." If someone does +complain, then the obligation would be to stop using the work in any new +work from then on though no penalty would attach for existing uses. This +would create a strong incentive for copyright owners to mark their work. +

+That in turn raises the question about how work should best be marked. Here +again, the system needs to adjust as the technologies evolve. The best way +to ensure that the system evolves is to limit the Copyright Office's role to +that of approving standards for marking content that have been crafted +elsewhere. +

+For example, if a recording industry association devises a method for +marking CDs, it would propose that to the Copyright Office. The Copyright +Office would hold a hearing, at which other proposals could be made. The +Copyright Office would then select the proposal that it judged preferable, +and it would base that choice solely upon the consideration of which method +could best be integrated into the registration and renewal system. We would +not count on the government to innovate; but we would count on the +government to keep the product of innovation in line with its other +important functions. +

+Finally, marking content clearly would simplify registration requirements. +If photographs were marked by author and year, there would be little reason +not to allow a photographer to reregister, for example, all photographs +taken in a particular year in one quick step. The aim of the formality is +not to burden the creator; the system itself should be kept as simple as +possible. +

+The objective of formalities is to make things clear. The existing system +does nothing to make things clear. Indeed, it seems designed to make things +unclear. +

+If formalities such as registration were reinstated, one of the most +difficult aspects of relying upon the public domain would be removed. It +would be simple to identify what content is presumptively free; it would be +simple to identify who controls the rights for a particular kind of content; +it would be simple to assert those rights, and to renew that assertion at +the appropriate time. +

2. Kortere vernetid

+The term of copyright has gone from fourteen years to ninety-five years for +corporate authors, and life of the author plus seventy years for natural +authors. +

+In The Future of Ideas, I proposed a seventy-five-year term, granted in +five-year increments with a requirement of renewal every five years. That +seemed radical enough at the time. But after we lost Eldred v. Ashcroft, +the proposals became even more radical. The Economist endorsed a proposal +for a fourteen-year copyright term.[214] +Others have proposed tying the term to the term for patents. +

+I agree with those who believe that we need a radical change in copyright's +term. But whether fourteen years or seventy-five, there are four principles +that are important to keep in mind about copyright terms. +

  1. + + +Keep it short: The term should be as long as necessary to give incentives to +create, but no longer. If it were tied to very strong protections for +authors (so authors were able to reclaim rights from publishers), rights to +the same work (not derivative works) might be extended further. The key is +not to tie the work up with legal regulations when it no longer benefits an +author.

  2. + + + +Gjør det enkelt: Skillelinjen mellom verker uten opphavsrettslig vern og +innhold som er beskyttet må forbli klart. Advokater liker uklarheten som +"rimelig bruk" og forskjellen mellom "idéer" og "uttrykk" har. Denne type +lovverk gir dem en masse arbeid. Men de som skrev grunnloven hadde en +enklere idé: vernet versus ikke vernet. Verdien av korte vernetider er at +det er lite behov for å bygge inn unntak i opphavsretten når vernetiden +holdes kort. En klar og aktiv "advokat-fri sone" gjør komplesiteten av +"rimelig bruk" og "idé/uttrykk" mindre nødvendig å håndtere. + +

  3. + +Keep it alive: Copyright should have to be renewed. Especially if the +maximum term is long, the copyright owner should be required to signal +periodically that he wants the protection continued. This need not be an +onerous burden, but there is no reason this monopoly protection has to be +granted for free. On average, it takes ninety minutes for a veteran to apply +for a pension.[215] If we make veterans +suffer that burden, I don't see why we couldn't require authors to spend ten +minutes every fifty years to file a single form. +

  4. + + +Keep it prospective: Whatever the term of copyright should be, the clearest +lesson that economists teach is that a term once given should not be +extended. It might have been a mistake in 1923 for the law to offer authors +only a fifty-six-year term. I don't think so, but it's possible. If it was a +mistake, then the consequence was that we got fewer authors to create in +1923 than we otherwise would have. But we can't correct that mistake today +by increasing the term. No matter what we do today, we will not increase the +number of authors who wrote in 1923. Of course, we can increase the reward +that those who write now get (or alternatively, increase the copyright +burden that smothers many works that are today invisible). But increasing +their reward will not increase their creativity in 1923. What's not done is +not done, and there's nothing we can do about that now.

+Disse endringene vil sammen gi en gjennomsnittlig opphavsrettslig vernetid +som er mye kortere enn den gjeldende vernetiden. Frem til 1976 var +gjennomsnittelig vernetid kun 32.2 år. Vårt mål bør være det samme. +

+Uten tvil vil ekstremistene kalle disse idéene "radikale". (Tross alt, så +kaller jeg dem "ekstremister".) Men igjen, vernetiden jeg anbefalte var +lengre enn vernetiden under Richard Nixon. hvor "radikalt" kan det være å be +om en mer sjenerøs opphavsrettighet enn da Richard Nixon var president? +

3. Fri Bruk vs. rimelig bruk

+As I observed at the beginning of this book, property law originally granted +property owners the right to control their property from the ground to the +heavens. The airplane came along. The scope of property rights quickly +changed. There was no fuss, no constitutional challenge. It made no sense +anymore to grant that much control, given the emergence of that new +technology. +

+Our Constitution gives Congress the power to give authors "exclusive right" +to "their writings." Congress has given authors an exclusive right to "their +writings" plus any derivative writings (made by others) that are +sufficiently close to the author's original work. Thus, if I write a book, +and you base a movie on that book, I have the power to deny you the right to +release that movie, even though that movie is not "my writing." +

+Congress granted the beginnings of this right in 1870, when it expanded the +exclusive right of copyright to include a right to control translations and +dramatizations of a work.[216] The courts +have expanded it slowly through judicial interpretation ever since. This +expansion has been commented upon by one of the law's greatest judges, Judge +Benjamin Kaplan. +

+So inured have we become to the extension of the monopoly to a large range +of so-called derivative works, that we no longer sense the oddity of +accepting such an enlargement of copyright while yet intoning the +abracadabra of idea and expression.[217] +

+I think it's time to recognize that there are airplanes in this field and +the expansiveness of these rights of derivative use no longer make +sense. More precisely, they don't make sense for the period of time that a +copyright runs. And they don't make sense as an amorphous grant. Consider +each limitation in turn. +

+Term: If Congress wants to grant a derivative right, then that right should +be for a much shorter term. It makes sense to protect John Grisham's right +to sell the movie rights to his latest novel (or at least I'm willing to +assume it does); but it does not make sense for that right to run for the +same term as the underlying copyright. The derivative right could be +important in inducing creativity; it is not important long after the +creative work is done. +

+Scope: Likewise should the scope of derivative rights be narrowed. Again, +there are some cases in which derivative rights are important. Those should +be specified. But the law should draw clear lines around regulated and +unregulated uses of copyrighted material. When all "reuse" of creative +material was within the control of businesses, perhaps it made sense to +require lawyers to negotiate the lines. It no longer makes sense for lawyers +to negotiate the lines. Think about all the creative possibilities that +digital technologies enable; now imagine pouring molasses into the +machines. That's what this general requirement of permission does to the +creative process. Smothers it. +

+This was the point that Alben made when describing the making of the Clint +Eastwood CD. While it makes sense to require negotiation for foreseeable +derivative rights—turning a book into a movie, or a poem into a +musical score—it doesn't make sense to require negotiation for the +unforeseeable. Here, a statutory right would make much more sense. +

+In each of these cases, the law should mark the uses that are protected, and +the presumption should be that other uses are not protected. This is the +reverse of the recommendation of my colleague Paul Goldstein.[218] His view is that the law should be written so that +expanded protections follow expanded uses. +

+Goldstein's analysis would make perfect sense if the cost of the legal +system were small. But as we are currently seeing in the context of the +Internet, the uncertainty about the scope of protection, and the incentives +to protect existing architectures of revenue, combined with a strong +copyright, weaken the process of innovation. +

+ +The law could remedy this problem either by removing protection beyond the +part explicitly drawn or by granting reuse rights upon certain statutory +conditions. Either way, the effect would be to free a great deal of culture +to others to cultivate. And under a statutory rights regime, that reuse +would earn artists more income. +

4. Frigjør musikken—igjen

+The battle that got this whole war going was about music, so it wouldn't be +fair to end this book without addressing the issue that is, to most people, +most pressing—music. There is no other policy issue that better +teaches the lessons of this book than the battles around the sharing of +music. +

+The appeal of file-sharing music was the crack cocaine of the Internet's +growth. It drove demand for access to the Internet more powerfully than any +other single application. It was the Internet's killer app—possibly in +two senses of that word. It no doubt was the application that drove demand +for bandwidth. It may well be the application that drives demand for +regulations that in the end kill innovation on the network. +

+The aim of copyright, with respect to content in general and music in +particular, is to create the incentives for music to be composed, performed, +and, most importantly, spread. The law does this by giving an exclusive +right to a composer to control public performances of his work, and to a +performing artist to control copies of her performance. +

+File-sharing networks complicate this model by enabling the spread of +content for which the performer has not been paid. But of course, that's not +all the file-sharing networks do. As I described in chapter 5, they enable +four different kinds of sharing: +

  1. + + +Det er noen som bruker delingsnettverk som erstatninger for å kjøpe CDer. +

  2. + + +There are also some who are using sharing networks to sample, on the way to +purchasing CDs. +

  3. + + + + +Det er mange som bruker fildelingsnettverk til å få tilgang til innhold som +ikke lenger er i salg, men fortsatt er vernet av opphavsrett eller som ville +ha vært altfor vanskelig å få kjøpt via nettet. +

  4. + + +Det er mange som bruker fildelingsnettverk for å få tilgang til innhold som +ikke er opphavsrettsbeskyttet, eller for å få tilgang som +opphavsrettsinnehaveren åpenbart går god for. +

+Any reform of the law needs to keep these different uses in focus. It must +avoid burdening type D even if it aims to eliminate type A. The eagerness +with which the law aims to eliminate type A, moreover, should depend upon +the magnitude of type B. As with VCRs, if the net effect of sharing is +actually not very harmful, the need for regulation is significantly +weakened. +

+As I said in chapter 5, the actual harm caused by sharing is controversial. +For the purposes of this chapter, however, I assume the harm is real. I +assume, in other words, that type A sharing is significantly greater than +type B, and is the dominant use of sharing networks. +

+Uansett, det er et avgjørende faktum om den gjeldende teknologiske +omgivelsen som vi må huske på hvis vi skal forstå hvordan loven bør reagere. +

+Today, file sharing is addictive. In ten years, it won't be. It is addictive +today because it is the easiest way to gain access to a broad range of +content. It won't be the easiest way to get access to a broad range of +content in ten years. Today, access to the Internet is cumbersome and +slow—we in the United States are lucky to have broadband service at +1.5 MBs, and very rarely do we get service at that speed both up and +down. Although wireless access is growing, most of us still get access +across wires. Most only gain access through a machine with a keyboard. The +idea of the always on, always connected Internet is mainly just an idea. +

+ +But it will become a reality, and that means the way we get access to the +Internet today is a technology in transition. Policy makers should not make +policy on the basis of technology in transition. They should make policy on +the basis of where the technology is going. The question should not be, how +should the law regulate sharing in this world? The question should be, what +law will we require when the network becomes the network it is clearly +becoming? That network is one in which every machine with electricity is +essentially on the Net; where everywhere you are—except maybe the +desert or the Rockies—you can instantaneously be connected to the +Internet. Imagine the Internet as ubiquitous as the best cell-phone service, +where with the flip of a device, you are connected. +

+In that world, it will be extremely easy to connect to services that give +you access to content on the fly—such as Internet radio, content that +is streamed to the user when the user demands. Here, then, is the critical +point: When it is extremely easy to connect to services that give access to +content, it will be easier to connect to services that give you access to +content than it will be to download and store content on the many devices +you will have for playing content. It will be easier, in other words, to +subscribe than it will be to be a database manager, as everyone in the +download-sharing world of Napster-like technologies essentially is. Content +services will compete with content sharing, even if the services charge +money for the content they give access to. Already cell-phone services in +Japan offer music (for a fee) streamed over cell phones (enhanced with plugs +for headphones). The Japanese are paying for this content even though "free" +content is available in the form of MP3s across the Web.[219] + +

+ +This point about the future is meant to suggest a perspective on the +present: It is emphatically temporary. The "problem" with file +sharing—to the extent there is a real problem—is a problem that +will increasingly disappear as it becomes easier to connect to the +Internet. And thus it is an extraordinary mistake for policy makers today +to be "solving" this problem in light of a technology that will be gone +tomorrow. The question should not be how to regulate the Internet to +eliminate file sharing (the Net will evolve that problem away). The question +instead should be how to assure that artists get paid, during this +transition between twentieth-century models for doing business and +twenty-first-century technologies. +

+The answer begins with recognizing that there are different "problems" here +to solve. Let's start with type D content—uncopyrighted content or +copyrighted content that the artist wants shared. The "problem" with this +content is to make sure that the technology that would enable this kind of +sharing is not rendered illegal. You can think of it this way: Pay phones +are used to deliver ransom demands, no doubt. But there are many who need +to use pay phones who have nothing to do with ransoms. It would be wrong to +ban pay phones in order to eliminate kidnapping. +

+Type C content raises a different "problem." This is content that was, at +one time, published and is no longer available. It may be unavailable +because the artist is no longer valuable enough for the record label he +signed with to carry his work. Or it may be unavailable because the work is +forgotten. Either way, the aim of the law should be to facilitate the access +to this content, ideally in a way that returns something to the artist. +

+Again, the model here is the used book store. Once a book goes out of print, +it may still be available in libraries and used book stores. But libraries +and used book stores don't pay the copyright owner when someone reads or +buys an out-of-print book. That makes total sense, of course, since any +other system would be so burdensome as to eliminate the possibility of used +book stores' existing. But from the author's perspective, this "sharing" of +his content without his being compensated is less than ideal. +

+The model of used book stores suggests that the law could simply deem +out-of-print music fair game. If the publisher does not make copies of the +music available for sale, then commercial and noncommercial providers would +be free, under this rule, to "share" that content, even though the sharing +involved making a copy. The copy here would be incidental to the trade; in a +context where commercial publishing has ended, trading music should be as +free as trading books. +

+ + + +Alternatively, the law could create a statutory license that would ensure +that artists get something from the trade of their work. For example, if the +law set a low statutory rate for the commercial sharing of content that was +not offered for sale by a commercial publisher, and if that rate were +automatically transferred to a trust for the benefit of the artist, then +businesses could develop around the idea of trading this content, and +artists would benefit from this trade. +

+This system would also create an incentive for publishers to keep works +available commercially. Works that are available commercially would not be +subject to this license. Thus, publishers could protect the right to charge +whatever they want for content if they kept the work commercially +available. But if they don't keep it available, and instead, the computer +hard disks of fans around the world keep it alive, then any royalty owed for +such copying should be much less than the amount owed a commercial +publisher. +

+The hard case is content of types A and B, and again, this case is hard only +because the extent of the problem will change over time, as the technologies +for gaining access to content change. The law's solution should be as +flexible as the problem is, understanding that we are in the middle of a +radical transformation in the technology for delivering and accessing +content. +

+Så her er en løsning som i første omgang kan virke veldig undelig for begge +sider i denne krigen, men som jeg tror vil gi mer mening når en får tenkt +seg om. +

+Stripped of the rhetoric about the sanctity of property, the basic claim of +the content industry is this: A new technology (the Internet) has harmed a +set of rights that secure copyright. If those rights are to be protected, +then the content industry should be compensated for that harm. Just as the +technology of tobacco harmed the health of millions of Americans, or the +technology of asbestos caused grave illness to thousands of miners, so, too, +has the technology of digital networks harmed the interests of the content +industry. +

+ + +Jeg elsker internett, så jeg liker ikke å sammenligne det med tobakk eller +asbest. Men analogien er rimelig når en ser det fra lovens perspektiv. Og +det foreslår en rimelig respons: I stedet for å forsøke å ødelegge internett +eller p2p-teknologien som i dag skader innholdsleverandører på internett, så +bør vi finne en relativt enkel måte å kompensere de som blir skadelidende. +

+The idea would be a modification of a proposal that has been floated by +Harvard law professor William Fisher.[220] +Fisher suggests a very clever way around the current impasse of the +Internet. Under his plan, all content capable of digital transmission would +(1) be marked with a digital watermark (don't worry about how easy it is to +evade these marks; as you'll see, there's no incentive to evade them). Once +the content is marked, then entrepreneurs would develop (2) systems to +monitor how many items of each content were distributed. On the basis of +those numbers, then (3) artists would be compensated. The compensation would +be paid for by (4) an appropriate tax. +

+Fisher's proposal is careful and comprehensive. It raises a million +questions, most of which he answers well in his upcoming book, Promises to +Keep. The modification that I would make is relatively simple: Fisher +imagines his proposal replacing the existing copyright system. I imagine it +complementing the existing system. The aim of the proposal would be to +facilitate compensation to the extent that harm could be shown. This +compensation would be temporary, aimed at facilitating a transition between +regimes. And it would require renewal after a period of years. If it +continues to make sense to facilitate free exchange of content, supported +through a taxation system, then it can be continued. If this form of +protection is no longer necessary, then the system could lapse into the old +system of controlling access. +

+ +Fisher would balk at the idea of allowing the system to lapse. His aim is +not just to ensure that artists are paid, but also to ensure that the system +supports the widest range of "semiotic democracy" possible. But the aims of +semiotic democracy would be satisfied if the other changes I described were +accomplished—in particular, the limits on derivative uses. A system +that simply charges for access would not greatly burden semiotic democracy +if there were few limitations on what one was allowed to do with the content +itself. +

+No doubt it would be difficult to calculate the proper measure of "harm" to +an industry. But the difficulty of making that calculation would be +outweighed by the benefit of facilitating innovation. This background system +to compensate would also not need to interfere with innovative proposals +such as Apple's MusicStore. As experts predicted when Apple launched the +MusicStore, it could beat "free" by being easier than free is. This has +proven correct: Apple has sold millions of songs at even the very high price +of 99 cents a song. (At 99 cents, the cost is the equivalent of a per-song +CD price, though the labels have none of the costs of a CD to pay.) Apple's +move was countered by Real Networks, offering music at just 79 cents a +song. And no doubt there will be a great deal of competition to offer and +sell music on-line. +

+This competition has already occurred against the background of "free" music +from p2p systems. As the sellers of cable television have known for thirty +years, and the sellers of bottled water for much more than that, there is +nothing impossible at all about "competing with free." Indeed, if anything, +the competition spurs the competitors to offer new and better products. This +is precisely what the competitive market was to be about. Thus in Singapore, +though piracy is rampant, movie theaters are often luxurious—with +"first class" seats, and meals served while you watch a movie—as they +struggle and succeed in finding ways to compete with "free." +

+Dette konkurranseregimet, med en sikringsmekanisme å sikre at kunstnere ikke +taper, ville bidra mye til nyskapning innen levering av +innhold. Konkurransen ville fortsette å redusere type-A-deling. Det ville +inspirere en ekstraordinær rekke av nye innovatører—som ville ha +retten til a bruke innhold, og ikke lenger frykte usikre og barbarisk +strenge straffer fra loven. +

+Oppsummert, så er dette mitt forslag: +

+ + + +Internett er i endring. Vi bør ikke regulere en teknologi i endring. Vi bør +i stedet regulere for å minimere skaden påført interesser som er berørt av +denne teknologiske endringen, samtidig vi muliggjør, og oppmuntrer, den mest +effektive teknologien vi kan lage. +

+Vi kan minimere skaden og samtidig maksimere fordelen med innovasjon ved å +

  1. + + +garantere retten til å engasjere seg i type-D-deling; +

  2. + + +tillate ikke-kommersiell type-C-deling uten erstatningsansvar, og +kommersiell type-C-deling med en lav og fast rate fastsatt ved lov. +

  3. + + +mens denne overgangen pågår, skattlegge og kompensere for type-A-deling, i +den grad faktiske skade kan påvises. +

+Men hva om "piratvirksomheten" ikke forsvinner? Hva om det finnes et +konkurranseutsatt marked som tilbyr innhold til en lav kostnad, men et +signifikant antall av forbrukere fortsetter å "ta" innhold uten å betale? +Burde loven gjøre noe da? +

+Ja, det bør den. Men, nok en gang, hva den bør gjøre avhenger hvordan +realitetene utvikler seg. Disse endringene fjerner kanskje ikke all +type-A-deling. Men det virkelige spørmålet er ikke om de eliminerer deling i +abstrakt betydning. Det virkelige spørsmålet er hvilken effekt det har på +markedet. Er det bedre (a) å ha en teknologi som er 95 prosent sikker og +gir et marked av størrelse x, eller (b) å ha en teknologi som er 50 prosent +sikker, og som gir et marked som er fem ganger større enn x? Mindre sikker +kan gi mer uautorisert deling, men det vil sannsynligvis også gi et mye +større marked for autorisert deling. Det viktigste er å sikre kunstneres +kompensasjon uten å ødelegge internettet. Når det er på plass, kan det +hende det er riktig å finne måter å spore opp de smålige piratene. +

+ +Men vi er langt unna å spikke problemet ned til dette delsettet av +type-A-delere. Og vårt fokus inntil er der bør ikke være å finne måter å +ødelegge internettet. Var fokus inntil vi er der bør være hvordan sikre at +artister får betalt, mens vi beskytter rommet for nyskapning og kreativitet +som internettet er. +

5. Spark en masse advokater

+Jeg er en advokat. Jeg lever av å utdanne advokater. Jeg tror på loven. Jeg +tror på opphavsrettsloven. Jeg har faktisk viet livet til å jobbe med loven, +ikke fordi det er mye penger å tjene, men fordi det innebærer idealer som +jeg elsker å leve opp til. +

+Likevel har mye av denne boken vært kritikk av advokater, eller rollen +advokater har spilt i denne debatten. Loven taler om idealer, mens det er +min oppfatning av vår yrkesgruppe er blitt for knyttet til klienten. Og i +en verden der rike klienter har sterke synspunkter vil uviljen hos vår +yrkesgruppe til å stille spørsmål med eller protestere mot dette sterke +synet ødelegge loven. +

+Indisiene for slik bøyning er overbevisene. Jeg er angrepet som en +"radikal" av mange innenfor yrket, og likevel er meningene jeg argumenterer +for nøyaktig de meningene til mange av de mest moderate og betydningsfulle +personene i historien til denne delen av loven. Mange trodde for eksempel at +vår utfordring til lovforslaget om å utvide opphavsrettens vernetid var +galskap. Mens bare tredve år siden mente den dominerende foreleser og +utøver i opphavsrettsfeltet, Melville Nimmer, at den var +åpenbar.[221] + +

+Min kritikk av rollen som advokater har spilt i denne debatten handler +imidlertid ikke bare om en profesjonell skjevhet. Det handler enda viktigere +om vår manglende evne til å faktisk ta inn over oss hva loven koster. +

+Økonomer er forventet å være gode til å forstå utgifter og inntekter. Men +som oftest antar økonomene uten peiling på hvordan det juridiske systemet +egentlig fungerer, at transaksjonskostnaden i det juridiske systemet er +lav.[222] De ser et system som har +eksistert i hundrevis av år, og de antar at det fungerer slik grunnskolens +samfunnsfagsundervisning lærte dem at det fungerer. +

+ + +Men det juridiske systemet fungerer ikke. Eller for å være mer nøyaktig, det +fungerer kun for de med mest ressurser. Det er ikke fordi systemet er +korrupt. Jeg tror overhodet ikke vårt juridisk system (på føderalt nivå, i +hvert fall) er korrupt. Jeg mener ganske enkelt at på grunn av at kostnadene +med vårt juridiske systemet er så hårreisende høyt vil en praktisk talt +aldri oppnå rettferdighet. +

+Disse kostnadene forstyrrer fri kultur på mange vis. En advokats tid +faktureres hos de største firmaene for mer enn $400 pr. time. Hvor mye tid +bør en slik advokat bruke på å lese sakene nøye, eller undersøke obskure +rettskilder. Svaret er i økende grad: svært lite. Jussen er avhengig av +nøye formulering og utvikling av doktrine, men nøye formulering og utvikling +av doktrine er avhengig av nøyaktig arbeid. Men nøyaktig arbeid koster for +mye, bortsett fra i de mest høyprofilerte og kostbare sakene. +

+Kostbarheten, klomsetheten og tilfeldigheten til dette systemet håner vår +tradisjon. Og advokater, såvel som akademikere, bør se det som sin plikt å +endre hvordan loven praktiseres— eller bedre, endre loven slik at den +fungerer. Det er galt at systemet fungerer godt bare for den øverste +1-prosenten av klientene. Det kan gjøres radikalt mer effektivt, og billig, +og dermed radikalt mer rettferdig. +

+Men inntil en slik reform er gjennomført, bør vi som samfunn holde lover +unna områder der vi vet den bare vil skade. Og det er nettopp det loven +altfor ofte vil gjøre hvis for mye av vår kultur er lovregulert. +

+Tenk på de fantastiske tingene ditt barn kan gjøre eller lage med digital +teknologi—filmen, musikken, web-siden, bloggen. Eller tenk på de +fantastiske tingene ditt fellesskap kunne få til med digital +teknologi—en wiki, oppsetting av låve, kampanje til å endre noe. Tenk +på alle de kreative tingene, og tenk deretter på kald sirup helt inn i +maskinene. Dette er hva et hvert regime som krever tillatelser fører +til. Dette er virkeligheten slik den var i Brezhnevs Russland. +

+ +Loven bør regulere i visse områder av kulturen—men det bør regulere +kultur bare der reguleringen bidrar positivt. Likevel tester advokater +sjeldent sin kraft, eller kraften som de fremmer, mot dette enkle pragmatisk +spørsmålet: "vil det bidra positivt?". Når de blir utfordret om det +utvidede rekkevidden til loven, er advokat-svaret, "Hvorfor ikke?" +

+Vi burde spørre: "Hvorfor?". Vis meg hvorfor din regulering av kultur er +nødvendig og vis meg hvordan reguleringen bidrar positivt. Før du kan vise +meg begge, holde advokatene din unna. +



[210] + + + +See, for example, Marc Rotenberg, "Fair Information Practices and the +Architecture of Privacy (What Larry Doesn't Get)," Stanford Technology Law +Review 1 (2001): par. 6–18, available at link #72 (describing examples in +which technology defines privacy policy). See also Jeffrey Rosen, The Naked +Crowd: Reclaiming Security and Freedom in an Anxious Age (New York: Random +House, 2004) (mapping tradeoffs between technology and privacy).

[211] + + + +Willful Infringement: A Report from the Front Lines of the Real Culture Wars +(2003), produced by Jed Horovitz, directed by Greg Hittelman, a Fiat Lucre +production, available at link +#72. +

[212] + + +The proposal I am advancing here would apply to American works only. +Obviously, I believe it would be beneficial for the same idea to be adopted +by other countries as well.

[213] + + +There would be a complication with derivative works that I have not solved +here. In my view, the law of derivatives creates a more complicated system +than is justified by the marginal incentive it creates. +

[214] + + +"A Radical Rethink," Economist, 366:8308 (25. januar 2003): 15, tilgjengelig +fra link #74. +

[215] + + +Department of Veterans Affairs, Veteran's Application for Compensation +and/or Pension, VA Form 21-526 (OMB Approved No. 2900-0001), tilgjengelig +fra link #75. +

[216] + + +Benjamin Kaplan, An Unhurried View of Copyright (New York: Columbia +University Press, 1967), 32. +

[217] + +Ibid., 56. +

[218] + +Paul Goldstein, Copyright's Highway: From Gutenberg to the Celestial Jukebox +(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003), 187–216. +

[219] + + +For eksempel, se, "Music Media Watch," The J@pan Inc. Newsletter, 3 April +2002, tilgjengelig fra link +#76. +

[220] + William Fisher, Digital Music: Problems and Possibilities (last revised: 10 +October 2000), available at link +#77; William Fisher, Promises to Keep: Technology, Law, and the +Future of Entertainment (forthcoming) (Stanford: Stanford University Press, +2004), ch. 6, available at link +#78. Professor Netanel has proposed a related idea that would exempt +noncommercial sharing from the reach of copyright and would establish +compensation to artists to balance any loss. See Neil Weinstock Netanel, +"Impose a Noncommercial Use Levy to Allow Free P2P File Sharing," available +at link #79. For other +proposals, see Lawrence Lessig, "Who's Holding Back Broadband?" Washington +Post, 8 January 2002, A17; Philip S. Corwin on behalf of Sharman Networks, A +Letter to Senator Joseph R. Biden, Jr., Chairman of the Senate Foreign +Relations Committee, 26 February 2002, available at link #80; Serguei Osokine, A +Quick Case for Intellectual Property Use Fee (IPUF), 3 March 2002, available +at link #81; Jefferson +Graham, "Kazaa, Verizon Propose to Pay Artists Directly," USA Today, 13 May +2002, available at link +#82; Steven M. Cherry, "Getting Copyright Right," IEEE Spectrum +Online, 1 July 2002, available at link #83; Declan McCullagh, +"Verizon's Copyright Campaign," CNET News.com, 27 August 2002, available at +link #84. Fisher's +proposal is very similar to Richard Stallman's proposal for DAT. Unlike +Fisher's, Stallman's proposal would not pay artists directly proportionally, +though more popular artists would get more than the less popular. As is +typical with Stallman, his proposal predates the current debate by about a +decade. See link #85. + +

[221] + + +Lawrence Lessig, "Copyright's First Amendment" (Melville B. Nimmer Memorial +Lecture), UCLA law Review 48 (2001): 1057, 1069–70. +

[222] + +Et godt eksempel er arbeidet til professor Stan Liebowitz. Liebowitz bør få +ros for sin nøye gjennomgang av data om opphavsrettsbrudd, som fikk ham til +å stille spørsmål med sin egen uttalte posisjon—to ganger. I starten +predicated han at nedlasting ville påføre industrien vesentlig skade. Han +endret så sitt syn etter i lys av dataene, og han har siden endret sitt syn +på nytt. Sammenlign Stan J. Liebowitz, Rethinking the Network Economy: The +True Forces That Drive the Digital Marketplace (New York: Amacom, 2002), +(gikk igjennom hans originale syn men uttrykte skepsis) med Stan J. +Liebowitz, "Will MP3s Annihilate the Record Industry?" artikkelutkast, juni +2003, tilgjengelig fra link +#86. Den nøye analysen til Liebowitz er ekstremt verdifull i sin +estimering av effekten av fildelingsteknologi. Etter mitt syn +underestimerer han forøvrig kostnaden til det juridiske system. Se, for +eksempel, Rethinking, 174–76. +

Kapittel 8. Notater

+I denne teksten er det referanser til lenker på verdensveven. Og som alle +som har forsøkt å bruke nettet vet, så vil disse lenkene være svært +ustabile. Jeg har forsøkt å motvirke denne ustabiliteten ved å omdirigere +lesere til den originale kilden gjennom en nettside som hører til denne +boken. For hver lenke under, så kan du gå til http://free-culture.cc/notes +og finne den originale kilden ved å klikke på nummeret etter #-tegnet. Hvis +den originale lenken fortsatt er i live, så vil du bli omdirigert til den +lenken. Hvis den originale lenken har forsvunnet, så vil du bli omdirigert +til en passende referanse til materialet. +

Kapittel 9. Takk til

+Denne boken er produktet av en lang og så langt mislykket kamp som begynte +da jeg leste om Eric Eldreds krig for å sørge for at bøker forble +frie. Eldreds innsats bidro til å lansere en bevegelse, fri +kultur-bevegelsen, og denne boken er tilegnet ham. +

+Jeg fikk veiledning på ulike steder fra venner og akademikere, inkludert +Glenn Brown, Peter DiCola, Jennifer Mnookin, Richard Posner, Mark Rose og +Kathleen Sullivan. Og jeg fikk korreksjoner og veiledning fra mange +fantastiske studenter ved Stanford Law School og Stanford University. Det +inkluderer Andrew B. Coan, John Eden, James P. Fellers, Christopher +Guzelian, Erica Goldberg, Robert Hallman, Andrew Harris, Matthew Kahn, +Brian-Link, Ohad Mayblum, Alina Ng og Erica Platt. Jeg er særlig takknemlig +overfor Catherine Crump og Harry Surden, som hjalp til med å styre deres +forskning og til Laura Lynch, som briljant håndterte hæren de samlet, samt +bidro med sitt egen kritisk blikk på mye av dette. +

+ +Yuko Noguchi hjalp meg å forstå lovene i Japan, så vel som Japans +kultur. Jeg er henne takknemlig, og til de mange i Japan som hjalp meg med +forundersøkelsene til denne boken: Joi Ito, Takayuki Matsutani, Naoto +Misaki, Michihiro Sasaki, Hiromichi Tanaka, Hiroo Yamagata og Yoshihiro +Yonezawa. Jeg er også takknemlig til professor Nobuhiro Nakayama og Tokyo +University Business Law Center, som ga meg muligheten til å bruke tid i +Japan, og Tadashi Shiraishi og Kiyokazu Yamagami for deres generøse hjelp +mens jeg var der. +

+Dette er de tradisjonelle former for hjelp som akademikere regelmessig +trekker på. Men i tillegg til dem, har Internett gjort det mulig å motta råd +og korrigering fra mange som jeg har aldri møtt. Blant de som har svart med +svært nyttig råd etter forespørsler om boken på bloggen min er Dr. Muhammed +Al-Ubaydli, David Gerstein og Peter Dimauro, I tillegg en lang liste med de +som hadde spesifikke ideer om måter å utvikle mine argumenter på. De +inkluderte Richard Bondi, Steven Cherry, David Coe, Nik Cubrilovic, Bob +Devine, Charles Eicher, Thomas Guida, Elihu M. Gerson, Jeremy Hunsinger, +Vaughn Iverson, John Karabaic, Jeff Keltner, James Lindenschmidt, +K. L. Mann, Mark Manning, Nora McCauley, Jeffrey McHugh, Evan McMullen, Fred +Norton, John Pormann, Pedro A. D. Rezende, Shabbir Safdar, Saul Schleimer, +Clay Shirky, Adam Shostack, Kragen Sitaker, Chris Smith, Bruce Steinberg, +Andrzej Jan Taramina, Sean Walsh, Matt Wasserman, Miljenko Williams, "Wink," +Roger Wood, "Ximmbo da Jazz," og Richard Yanco. (jeg beklager hvis jeg gikk +glipp av noen, med datamaskiner kommer feil og en krasj i e-postsystemet +mitt gjorde at jeg mistet en haug med flotte svar.) +

+Richard Stallman og Michael Carroll har begge lest hele boken i utkast, og +hver av dem har bidratt med svært nyttige korreksjoner og råd. Michael hjalp +meg å se mer tydelig betydningen av regulering for avledede verker . Og +Richard korrigerte en pinlig stor mengde feil. Selv om mitt arbeid er +delvis inspirert av Stallmans, er han ikke enig med meg på vesentlige steder +i denne boken. +

+Til slutt, og for evig, er jeg Bettina takknemlig, som alltid har insistert +på at det ville være endeløs lykke utenfor disse kampene, og som alltid har +hatt rett. Denne trege eleven er som alltid takknemlig for hennes +evigvarende tålmodighet og kjærlighet. +

diff --git a/archive/freeculture.nb.pdf b/archive/freeculture.nb.pdf index 017bec4..7b0410e 100644 Binary files a/archive/freeculture.nb.pdf and b/archive/freeculture.nb.pdf differ